In
logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, a quantifier is an operator that specifies how many individuals in the
domain of discourse satisfy an
open formula. For instance, the
universal quantifier in the
first-order formula
expresses that everything in the domain satisfies the property denoted by
. On the other hand, the
existential quantifier in the formula
expresses that there exists something in the domain which satisfies that property. A formula where a quantifier takes widest
scope is called a quantified formula. A quantified formula must contain a
bound variable and a
subformula
In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbol (formal), symbols from a given alphabet (computer science), alphabet that is part ...
specifying a property of the referent of that variable.
The most commonly used quantifiers are
and
. These quantifiers are standardly defined as
duals; in
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
: each can be defined in terms of the other using
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
. They can also be used to define more complex quantifiers, as in the formula
which expresses that nothing has the property
. Other quantifiers are only definable within
second-order logic or
higher-order logic
In mathematics and logic, a higher-order logic (abbreviated HOL) is a form of logic that is distinguished from first-order logic by additional quantifiers and, sometimes, stronger semantics. Higher-order logics with their standard semantics are m ...
s. Quantifiers have been generalized beginning with the work of
Andrzej Mostowski and
Per Lindström.
In a first-order logic statement, quantifications in the same type (either universal quantifications or existential quantifications) can be exchanged without changing the meaning of the statement, while the exchange of quantifications in different types changes the meaning. As an example, the only difference in the definition of
uniform continuity and
(ordinary) continuity is the order of quantifications.
First order quantifiers approximate the meanings of some
natural language quantifiers such as "some" and "all". However, many natural language quantifiers can only be analyzed in terms of
generalized quantifiers.
Relations to logical conjunction and disjunction
For a finite domain of discourse
, the universally quantified formula
is equivalent to the
logical conjunction
In logic, mathematics and linguistics, ''and'' (\wedge) is the Truth function, truth-functional operator of conjunction or logical conjunction. The logical connective of this operator is typically represented as \wedge or \& or K (prefix) or ...
.
Dually, the existentially quantified formula
is equivalent to the
logical disjunction .
For example, if
is the set of
binary digits, the formula
abbreviates
, which evaluates to ''true''.
Infinite domain of discourse
Consider the following statement (''using dot notation for multiplication''):
This has the appearance of an ''infinite
conjunction'' of propositions. From the point of view of
formal languages, this is immediately a problem, since
syntax
In linguistics, syntax ( ) is the study of how words and morphemes combine to form larger units such as phrases and sentences. Central concerns of syntax include word order, grammatical relations, hierarchical sentence structure (constituenc ...
rules are expected to generate
finite statements.
The example above is fortunate in that there is a
procedure to generate all the conjuncts. However, if the same assertion were to be made about
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s instead of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, there would be no way to enumerate all the conjuncts, since real numbers
cannot be enumerated. Succinct equivalent formulations, which avoid these problems, uses ''universal quantification'':
A similar analysis applies to the
disjunction
In logic, disjunction (also known as logical disjunction, logical or, logical addition, or inclusive disjunction) is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is ...
,
which can be rephrased using ''existential quantification'':
Algebraic approaches to quantification
It is possible to devise
abstract algebra
In mathematics, more specifically algebra, abstract algebra or modern algebra is the study of algebraic structures, which are set (mathematics), sets with specific operation (mathematics), operations acting on their elements. Algebraic structur ...
s whose
models
A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , .
Models can be divided int ...
include
formal languages with quantification, but progress has been slow and interest in such algebra has been limited. Three approaches have been devised to date:
*
Relation algebra, invented by
Augustus De Morgan, and developed by
Charles Sanders Peirce
Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". According to philosopher Paul Weiss (philosopher), Paul ...
,
Ernst Schröder,
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
, and Tarski's students. Relation algebra cannot represent any formula with quantifiers nested more than three deep. Surprisingly, the models of relation algebra include the
axiomatic set theory ZFC and
Peano arithmetic;
*
Cylindric algebra, devised by
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
,
Leon Henkin, and others;
* The
polyadic algebra of
Paul Halmos
Paul Richard Halmos (; 3 March 1916 – 2 October 2006) was a Kingdom of Hungary, Hungarian-born United States, American mathematician and probabilist who made fundamental advances in the areas of mathematical logic, probability theory, operat ...
.
Notation
The two most common quantifiers are the universal quantifier and the existential quantifier. The traditional symbol for the universal quantifier is "
∀", a rotated letter "
A", which stands for "for all" or "all". The corresponding symbol for the existential quantifier is "
∃", a rotated letter "
E", which stands for "there exists" or "exists".
An example of translating a quantified statement in a natural language such as English would be as follows. Given the statement, "Each of Peter's friends either likes to dance or likes to go to the beach (or both)", key aspects can be identified and rewritten using symbols including quantifiers. So, let ''X'' be the set of all Peter's friends, ''P''(''x'') the
predicate "''x'' likes to dance", and ''Q''(''x'') the predicate "''x'' likes to go to the beach". Then the above sentence can be written in formal notation as
, which is read, "for every ''x'' that is a member of ''X'', ''P'' applies to ''x''
or ''Q'' applies to ''x''".
Some other quantified expressions are constructed as follows,
*
*
for a formula ''P''. These two expressions (using the definitions above) are read as "there exists a friend of Peter who likes to dance" and "all friends of Peter like to dance", respectively. Variant notations include, for set ''X'' and set members ''x'':
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
All of these variations also apply to universal quantification.
Other variations for the universal quantifier are
*
*
*
Some versions of the notation explicitly mention the range of quantification. The range of quantification must always be specified; for a given mathematical theory, this can be done in several ways:
* Assume a fixed domain of discourse for every quantification, as is done in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
.
* Fix several domains of discourse in advance and require that each variable have a declared domain, which is the ''type'' of that variable. This is analogous to the situation in
statically typed
In computer programming, a type system is a logical system comprising a set of rules that assigns a property called a ''type'' (for example, integer, floating point, string) to every '' term'' (a word, phrase, or other set of symbols). Usu ...
computer programming
Computer programming or coding is the composition of sequences of instructions, called computer program, programs, that computers can follow to perform tasks. It involves designing and implementing algorithms, step-by-step specifications of proc ...
languages, where variables have declared types.
* Mention explicitly the range of quantification, perhaps using a symbol for the set of all objects in that domain (or the
type of the objects in that domain).
One can use any variable as a quantified variable in place of any other, under certain restrictions in which ''variable capture'' does not occur. Even if the notation uses typed variables, variables of that type may be used.
Informally or in natural language, the "∀''x''" or "∃''x''" might appear after or in the middle of ''P''(''x''). Formally, however, the phrase that introduces the dummy variable is placed in front.
Mathematical formulas mix symbolic expressions for quantifiers with natural language quantifiers such as,
Keywords for
uniqueness quantification include:
Further, ''x'' may be replaced by a
pronoun
In linguistics and grammar, a pronoun (Interlinear gloss, glossed ) is a word or a group of words that one may substitute for a noun or noun phrase.
Pronouns have traditionally been regarded as one of the part of speech, parts of speech, but so ...
. For example,
Order of quantifiers (nesting)
The order of quantifiers is critical to meaning, as is illustrated by the following two propositions:
This is clearly true; it just asserts that every natural number has a square. The meaning of the assertion in which the order of quantifiers is reversed is different:
This is clearly false; it asserts that there is a single natural number ''s'' that is the square of ''every'' natural number. This is because the syntax directs that any variable cannot be a function of subsequently introduced variables.
A less trivial example from
mathematical analysis
Analysis is the branch of mathematics dealing with continuous functions, limit (mathematics), limits, and related theories, such as Derivative, differentiation, Integral, integration, measure (mathematics), measure, infinite sequences, series ( ...
regards the concepts of
uniform
A uniform is a variety of costume worn by members of an organization while usually participating in that organization's activity. Modern uniforms are most often worn by armed forces and paramilitary organizations such as police, emergency serv ...
and
pointwise continuity, whose definitions differ only by an exchange in the positions of two quantifiers. A function ''f'' from
R to R is called
* Pointwise continuous if
* Uniformly continuous if
In the former case, the particular value chosen for ''δ'' can be a function of both ''ε'' and ''x'', the variables that precede it.
In the latter case, ''δ'' can be a function only of ''ε'' (i.e., it has to be chosen independent of ''x''). For example, ''f''(''x'') = ''x''
2 satisfies pointwise, but not uniform continuity (its slope is unbound). In contrast, interchanging the two initial universal quantifiers in the definition of pointwise continuity does not change the meaning.
As a general rule, swapping two adjacent universal quantifiers with the same
scope (or swapping two adjacent existential quantifiers with the same scope) doesn't change the meaning of the formula (see
Example here), but swapping an existential quantifier and an adjacent universal quantifier may change its meaning.
The maximum depth of nesting of quantifiers in a formula is called its "
quantifier rank".
Equivalent expressions
If ''D'' is a domain of ''x'' and ''P''(''x'') is a predicate dependent on object variable ''x'', then the universal proposition can be expressed as
This notation is known as restricted or relativized or
bounded quantification. Equivalently one can write,
The existential proposition can be expressed with bounded quantification as
or equivalently
Together with negation, only one of either the universal or existential quantifier is needed to perform both tasks:
which shows that to disprove a "for all ''x''" proposition, one needs no more than to find an ''x'' for which the predicate is false. Similarly,
to disprove a "there exists an ''x''" proposition, one needs to show that the predicate is false for all ''x''.
In
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
, every formula is
logically equivalent to a formula in
prenex normal form, that is, a string of quantifiers and bound variables followed by a quantifier-free formula.
Quantifier elimination
Range of quantification
Every quantification involves one specific variable and a
domain of discourse or range of quantification of that variable. The range of quantification specifies the set of values that the variable takes. In the examples above, the range of quantification is the set of natural numbers. Specification of the range of quantification allows us to express the difference between, say, asserting that a predicate holds for some natural number or for some
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
. Expository conventions often reserve some variable names such as "''n''" for natural numbers, and "''x''" for real numbers, although relying exclusively on naming conventions cannot work in general, since ranges of variables can change in the course of a mathematical argument.
A universally quantified formula over an empty range (like
) is always
vacuously true. Conversely, an existentially quantified formula over an empty range (like
) is always false.
A more natural way to restrict the domain of discourse uses ''guarded quantification''. For example, the guarded quantification
means
In some
mathematical theories, a single domain of discourse fixed in advance is assumed. For example, in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, variables range over all sets. In this case, guarded quantifiers can be used to mimic a smaller range of quantification. Thus in the example above, to express
in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, one would write
where N is the set of all natural numbers.
Formal semantics
Mathematical semantics is the application of
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
to study the meaning of expressions in a formal language. It has three elements: a mathematical specification of a class of objects via
syntax
In linguistics, syntax ( ) is the study of how words and morphemes combine to form larger units such as phrases and sentences. Central concerns of syntax include word order, grammatical relations, hierarchical sentence structure (constituenc ...
, a mathematical specification of various
semantic domains and the relation between the two, which is usually expressed as a function from syntactic objects to semantic ones. This article only addresses the issue of how quantifier elements are interpreted.
The syntax of a formula can be given by a syntax tree. A quantifier has a
scope, and an occurrence of a variable ''x'' is
free if it is not within the scope of a quantification for that variable. Thus in
the occurrence of both ''x'' and ''y'' in ''C''(''y'', ''x'') is free, while the occurrence of ''x'' and ''y'' in ''B''(''y'', ''x'') is bound (i.e. non-free).

An
interpretation for
first-order predicate calculus assumes as given a domain of individuals ''X''. A formula ''A'' whose free variables are ''x''
1, ..., ''x''
n is interpreted as a
Boolean-valued function ''F''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n'') of ''n'' arguments, where each argument ranges over the domain ''X''. Boolean-valued means that the function assumes one of the values T (interpreted as truth) or F (interpreted as falsehood). The interpretation of the formula
is the function ''G'' of ''n''-1 arguments such that ''G''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1) = T if and only if ''F''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1, ''w'') = T for every ''w'' in ''X''. If ''F''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1, ''w'') = F for at least one value of ''w'', then ''G''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1) = F. Similarly the interpretation of the formula
is the function ''H'' of ''n''-1 arguments such that ''H''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1) = T if and only if ''F''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1, ''w'') = T for at least one ''w'' and ''H''(''v''
1, ..., ''v''
''n''-1) = F otherwise.
The semantics for
uniqueness quantification requires first-order predicate calculus with equality. This means there is given a distinguished two-placed predicate "="; the semantics is also modified accordingly so that "=" is always interpreted as the two-place equality relation on ''X''. The interpretation of
then is the function of ''n''-1 arguments, which is the logical ''and'' of the interpretations of
Each kind of quantification defines a corresponding
closure operator on the set of formulas, by adding, for each free variable ''x'', a quantifier to bind ''x''. For example, the ''existential closure'' of the
open formula ''n''>2 ∧ ''x''
''n''+''y''
''n''=''z''
''n'' is the closed formula ∃''n'' ∃''x'' ∃''y'' ∃''z'' (''n''>2 ∧ ''x''
''n''+''y''
''n''=''z''
''n''); the latter formula, when interpreted over the positive integers, is known to be false by
Fermat's Last Theorem
In number theory, Fermat's Last Theorem (sometimes called Fermat's conjecture, especially in older texts) states that no three positive number, positive integers , , and satisfy the equation for any integer value of greater than . The cases ...
. As another example, equational axioms, like ''x''+''y''=''y''+''x'', are usually meant to denote their ''universal closure'', like ∀''x'' ∀''y'' (''x''+''y''=''y''+''x'') to express
commutativity.
Paucal, multal and other degree quantifiers
None of the quantifiers previously discussed apply to a quantification such as
One possible interpretation mechanism can be obtained as follows: Suppose that in addition to a semantic domain ''X'', we have given a
probability measure
In mathematics, a probability measure is a real-valued function defined on a set of events in a σ-algebra that satisfies Measure (mathematics), measure properties such as ''countable additivity''. The difference between a probability measure an ...
P defined on ''X'' and cutoff numbers 0 < ''a'' ≤ ''b'' ≤ 1. If ''A'' is a formula with free variables ''x''
1,...,''x''
''n'' whose interpretation is
the function ''F'' of variables ''v''
1,...,''v''
''n'' then the interpretation of
is the function of ''v''
1,...,''v''
''n''-1 which is T if and only if
and F otherwise. Similarly, the interpretation of
is the function of ''v''
1,...,''v''
''n''-1 which is F if and only if
and T otherwise.
Other quantifiers
A few other quantifiers have been proposed over time. In particular, the solution quantifier, noted § (
section sign) and read "those". For example,
is read "those ''n'' in N such that ''n''
2 ≤ 4 are in ." The same construct is expressible in
set-builder notation as
Contrary to the other quantifiers, § yields a set rather than a formula.
Some other quantifiers sometimes used in mathematics include:
*There are infinitely many elements such that...
*For all but finitely many elements... (sometimes expressed as "for
almost all
In mathematics, the term "almost all" means "all but a negligible quantity". More precisely, if X is a set (mathematics), set, "almost all elements of X" means "all elements of X but those in a negligible set, negligible subset of X". The meaning o ...
elements...").
*There are uncountably many elements such that...
*For all but countably many elements...
*For all elements in a set of positive measure...
*For all elements except those in a set of measure zero...
History
Term logic, also called Aristotelian logic, treats quantification in a manner that is closer to natural language, and also less suited to formal analysis. Term logic treated ''All'', ''Some'' and ''No'' in the 4th century BC, in an account also touching on the
alethic modalities.
In 1827,
George Bentham
George Bentham (22 September 1800 – 10 September 1884) was an English botanist, described by the weed botanist Duane Isely as "the premier systematic botanist of the nineteenth century". Born into a distinguished family, he initially studie ...
published his ''Outline of a New System of Logic: With a Critical Examination of Dr. Whately's Elements of Logic'', describing the principle of the quantifier, but the book was not widely circulated.
William Hamilton claimed to have coined the terms "quantify" and "quantification", most likely in his Edinburgh lectures c. 1840.
Augustus De Morgan confirmed this in 1847, but modern usage began with De Morgan in 1862 where he makes statements such as "We are to take in both ''all'' and ''some-not-all'' as quantifiers".
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
, in his 1879 , was the first to employ a quantifier to bind a variable ranging over a
domain of discourse and appearing in
predicates. He would universally quantify a variable (or relation) by writing the variable over a dimple in an otherwise straight line appearing in his diagrammatic formulas. Frege did not devise an explicit notation for existential quantification, instead employing his equivalent of ~∀''x''~, or
contraposition. Frege's treatment of quantification went largely unremarked until
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
's 1903 ''Principles of Mathematics''.
In work that culminated in Peirce (1885),
Charles Sanders Peirce
Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". According to philosopher Paul Weiss (philosopher), Paul ...
and his student
Oscar Howard Mitchell independently invented universal and existential quantifiers, and
bound variables. Peirce and Mitchell wrote Î
x and Σ
x where we now write ∀''x'' and ∃''x''. Peirce's notation can be found in the writings of
Ernst Schröder,
Leopold Loewenheim,
Thoralf Skolem, and Polish logicians into the 1950s. Most notably, it is the notation of
Kurt Gödel's landmark 1930 paper on the
completeness of
first-order logic, and 1931 paper on the
incompleteness of
Peano arithmetic.
Per Martin-Löf adopted a similar notation for dependent products and sums in his
intuitionistic type theory, which are conceptually related to quantification.
Peirce's approach to quantification also influenced
William Ernest Johnson and
Giuseppe Peano
Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much Mathematical notati ...
, who invented yet another notation, namely (''x'') for the universal quantification of ''x'' and (in 1897) ∃''x'' for the existential quantification of ''x''. Hence for decades, the canonical notation in philosophy and mathematical logic was (''x'')''P'' to express "all individuals in the domain of discourse have the property ''P''", and "(∃''x'')''P''" for "there exists at least one individual in the domain of discourse having the property ''P''". Peano, who was much better known than Peirce, in effect diffused the latter's thinking throughout Europe. Peano's notation was adopted by the ''
Principia Mathematica
The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by the mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1 ...
'' of
Whitehead and
Russell,
Quine, and
Alonzo Church
Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
. In 1935,
Gentzen introduced the ∀ symbol, by analogy with Peano's ∃ symbol. ∀ did not become canonical until the 1960s.
Around 1895, Peirce began developing his
existential graphs, whose variables can be seen as tacitly quantified. Whether the shallowest instance of a variable is even or odd determines whether that variable's quantification is universal or existential. (Shallowness is the contrary of depth, which is determined by the nesting of negations.) Peirce's graphical logic has attracted some attention in recent years by those researching
heterogeneous reasoning and
diagrammatic inference.
See also
*
Absolute generality
*
Almost all
In mathematics, the term "almost all" means "all but a negligible quantity". More precisely, if X is a set (mathematics), set, "almost all elements of X" means "all elements of X but those in a negligible set, negligible subset of X". The meaning o ...
*
Branching quantifier
*
Conditional quantifier
*
Counting quantification
*
Eventually (mathematics)
*
Generalized quantifier — a higher-order property used as standard semantics of quantified
noun phrases
*
Lindström quantifier — a generalized polyadic quantifier
*
Quantifier shift
References
Bibliography
*
Barwise, Jon; and
Etchemendy, John, 2000. ''Language Proof and Logic''. CSLI (University of Chicago Press) and New York: Seven Bridges Press. A gentle introduction to
first-order logic by two first-rate logicians.
*
*
Frege, Gottlob, 1879. ''
Begriffsschrift''. Translated in
Jean van Heijenoort, 1967. ''From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book on Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931''. Harvard University Press. The first appearance of quantification.
*
Hilbert, David; and
Ackermann, Wilhelm, 1950 (1928). ''
Principles of Mathematical Logic''. Chelsea. Translation of ''Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik''. Springer-Verlag. The 1928 first edition is the first time quantification was consciously employed in the now-standard manner, namely as binding variables ranging over some fixed domain of discourse. This is the defining aspect of
first-order logic.
*
Peirce, C. S., 1885, "On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation, ''American Journal of Mathematics'', Vol. 7, pp. 180–202. Reprinted in Kloesel, N. ''et al.'', eds., 1993. ''Writings of C. S. Peirce, Vol. 5''. Indiana University Press. The first appearance of quantification in anything like its present form.
*
Reichenbach, Hans, 1975 (1947). ''Elements of Symbolic Logic'', Dover Publications. The quantifiers are discussed in chapters §18 "Binding of variables" through §30 "Derivations from Synthetic Premises".
* Westerståhl, Dag, 2001, "Quantifiers," in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell.
* Wiese, Heike, 2003. ''Numbers, language, and the human mind''. Cambridge University Press. .
External links
*
* . From College of Natural Sciences,
University of Hawaii at Manoa.
*
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''SEP'') is a freely available online philosophy resource published and maintained by Stanford University, encompassing both an online encyclopedia of philosophy and peer-reviewed original publication ...
:
** Shapiro, Stewart (2000)
"Classical Logic"(Covers syntax, model theory, and metatheory for first order logic in the natural deduction style.)
** Westerståhl, Dag (2005)
"Generalized quantifiers"* Peters, Stanley; Westerståhl, Dag (2002)
"Quantifiers"
{{Authority control
Logic
Predicate logic
Quantifier (logic)
Philosophical logic
Semantics