Stromquist–Woodall Theorem
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The Stromquist–Woodall theorem is a theorem in fair division and
measure theory In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures ( length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as mass and probability of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many simil ...
. Informally, it says that, for any cake, for any ''n'' people with different tastes, and for any fraction ''w'', there exists a subset of the cake that all people value at exactly a fraction ''w'' of the total cake value, and it can be cut using at most 2n-2 cuts. The theorem is about a circular 1-dimensional cake (a "pie"). Formally, it can be described as the interval ,1in which the two endpoints are identified. There are ''n'' continuous measures over the cake: V_1,\ldots,V_n; each measure represents the valuations of a different person over subsets of the cake. The theorem says that, for every weight w \in ,1/math>, there is a subset C_w, which all people value at exactly w: : \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, V_i(C_w)=w, where C_w is a union of at most n-1 intervals. This means that 2n-2 cuts are sufficient for cutting the subset C_w. If the cake is not circular (that is, the endpoints are not identified), then C_w may be the union of up to n intervals, in case one interval is adjacent to 0 and one other interval is adjacent to 1.


Proof sketch

Let W \subseteq ,1/math> be the subset of all weights for which the theorem is true. Then: # 1 \in W. Proof: take C_1 := C (recall that the value measures are normalized such that all partners value the entire cake as 1). # If w\in W, then also 1-w \in W. Proof: take C_ := C\smallsetminus C_w. If C_w is a union of n-1 intervals in a circle, then C_ is also a union of n-1 intervals. # W is a
closed set In geometry, topology, and related branches of mathematics, a closed set is a set whose complement is an open set. In a topological space, a closed set can be defined as a set which contains all its limit points. In a complete metric space, a cl ...
. This is easy to prove, since the space of unions of n-1 intervals is a compact set under a suitable topology. # If w\in W, then also w/2 \in W. This is the most interesting part of the proof; see below. From 1-4, it follows that W= ,1/math>. In other words, the theorem is valid for ''every'' possible weight.


Proof sketch for part 4

* Assume that C_w is a union of n-1 intervals and that all n partners value it as exactly w. * Define the following function on the cake, f: C \to \mathbb^n: :: f(t) = (t, t^2, \ldots, t^n)\,\,\,\,\,\,t\in ,1/math> * Define the following measures on \mathbb^n: :: U_i(Y) = V_i(f^(Y) \cap C_w)\,\,\,\,\,\,\,\,\, Y\subseteq \mathbb^n * Note that f^(\mathbb^n) = C. Hence, for every partner i: U_i(\mathbb^n) = w. * Hence, by the Stone–Tukey theorem, there is a hyper-plane that cuts \mathbb^n to two half-spaces, H, H', such that: :: \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, U_i(H)=U_i(H')=w/2 * Define M=f^(H)\cap C_w and M'=f^(H')\cap C_w. Then, by the definition of the U_i: :: \forall i = 1,\ldots,n: \,\,\,\,\, V_i(M)=V_i(M')=w/2 * The set C_w has n-1 connected components (intervals). Hence, its image f(C_w) also has n-1 connected components (1-dimensional curves in \mathbb^n). * The hyperplane that forms the boundary between H and H' intersects f(C_w) in at most n points. Hence, the total number of connected components (curves) in H\cap f(C_w) and H'\cap f(C_w) is 2n-1. Hence, one of these must have at most n-1 components. * Suppose it is H that has at most n-1 components (curves). Hence, M has at most n-1 components (intervals). * Hence, we can take C_=M. This proves that w\in W.


Tightness proof

Stromquist and Woodall prove that the number n-1 is tight if the weight w is either irrational, or rational with a reduced fraction r/s such that s\geq n.


Proof sketch for w=1/n

* Choose (n-1)(n+1) equally-spaced points along the circle; call them P_1,\ldots,P_. * Define n-1 measures in the following way. Measure i is concentrated in small neighbourhoods of the following (n+1) points: P_,P_,\ldots,P_. So, near each point P_, there is a fraction 1/(n+1) of the measure u_i. * Define the n-th measure as proportional to the length measure. * Every subset whose consensus value is 1/n, must touch at least two points for each of the first n-1 measures (since the value near each single point is 1/(n+1) which is slightly less than the required 1/n). Hence, it must touch at least 2(n-1) points. * On the other hand, every subset whose consensus value is 1/n, must have total length 1/n (because of the n-th measure). The number of "gaps" between the points is 1/\big((n+1)(n-1)\big); hence the subset can contain at most n-1 gaps. * The consensus subset must touch 2(n-1) points but contain at most n-1 gaps; hence it must contain at least n-1 intervals.


See also

* Fair cake-cutting * Fair pie-cutting * Exact division * Stone–Tukey theorem


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stromquist-Woodall theorem Cake-cutting Theorems in measure theory