In
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, a universal set is a set which contains all objects, including itself. In set theory as usually formulated, it can be proven in multiple ways that a universal set does not exist. However, some non-standard variants of set theory include a universal set.
Reasons for nonexistence
Many set theories do not allow for the existence of a universal set. There are several different arguments for its non-existence, based on different choices of axioms for set theory.
Russell's paradox
Russell's paradox concerns the impossibility of a set of sets, whose members are all sets that do not contain themselves. If such a set could exist, it could neither contain itself (because its members all do not contain themselves) nor avoid containing itself (because if it did, it should be included as one of its members). This paradox prevents the existence of a universal set in set theories that include either
Zermelo's
axiom of restricted comprehension, or the
axiom of regularity and
axiom of pairing
In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It was introduced by as a special case of his axiom of elementary sets ...
.
Regularity and pairing
In
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, the
axiom of regularity and
axiom of pairing
In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It was introduced by as a special case of his axiom of elementary sets ...
prevent any set from containing itself. For any set
, the set
(constructed using pairing) necessarily contains an element disjoint from
, by regularity. Because its only element is
, it must be the case that
is disjoint from
, and therefore that
does not contain itself. Because a universal set would necessarily contain itself, it cannot exist under these axioms.
Comprehension
Russell's paradox prevents the existence of a universal set in set theories that include
Zermelo's
axiom of restricted comprehension.
This axiom states that, for any formula
and any set
, there exists a set
that contains exactly those elements
of
that satisfy
.
If this axiom could be applied to a universal set
, with
defined as the predicate
,
it would state the existence of Russell's paradoxical set, giving a contradiction.
It was this contradiction that led the axiom of comprehension to be stated in its restricted form, where it asserts the existence of a subset of a given set rather than the existence of a set of all sets that satisfy a given formula.
When the axiom of restricted comprehension is applied to an arbitrary set
, with the predicate
, it produces the subset of elements of
that do not contain themselves. It cannot be a member of
, because if it were it would be included as a member of itself, by its definition, contradicting the fact that it cannot contain itself. In this way, it is possible to construct a witness to the non-universality of
, even in versions of set theory that allow sets to contain themselves. This indeed holds even with
predicative comprehension and over
intuitionistic logic.
Cantor's theorem
Another difficulty with the idea of a universal set concerns the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of the set of all sets. Because this power set is a set of sets, it would necessarily be a subset of the set of all sets, provided that both exist. However, this conflicts with Cantor's theorem that the power set of any set (whether infinite or not) always has strictly higher
cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
than the set itself.
Theories of universality
The difficulties associated with a universal set can be avoided either by using a variant of set theory in which the axiom of comprehension is restricted in some way, or by using a universal object that is not considered to be a set.
Restricted comprehension
There are set theories known to be
consistent
In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
(if the usual set theory is consistent) in which the universal set does exist (and
is true). In these theories, Zermelo's
axiom of comprehension does not hold in general, and the axiom of comprehension of
naive set theory is restricted in a different way. A set theory containing a universal set is necessarily a
non-well-founded set theory.
The most widely studied set theory with a universal set is
Willard Van Orman Quine
Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century" ...
's
New Foundations.
Alonzo Church
Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
and
Arnold Oberschelp also published work on such set theories. Church speculated that his theory might be extended in a manner consistent with Quine's,
[. See also , , and .] but this is not possible for Oberschelp's, since in it the singleton function is provably a set, which leads immediately to paradox in New Foundations.
Another example is
positive set theory, where the axiom of comprehension is restricted to hold only for the
positive formulas (formulas that do not contain negations). Such set theories are motivated by notions of closure in topology.
Universal objects that are not sets
The idea of a universal set seems intuitively desirable in the
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, particularly because most versions of this theory do allow the use of quantifiers over all sets (see
universal quantifier). One way of allowing an object that behaves similarly to a universal set, without creating paradoxes, is to describe and similar large collections as
proper classes rather than as sets. Russell's paradox does not apply in these theories because the axiom of comprehension operates on sets, not on classes.
The
category of sets
In the mathematical field of category theory, the category of sets, denoted by Set, is the category whose objects are sets. The arrows or morphisms between sets ''A'' and ''B'' are the functions from ''A'' to ''B'', and the composition of mor ...
can also be considered to be a universal object that is, again, not itself a set. It has all sets as elements, and also includes arrows for all functions from one set to another.
Again, it does not contain itself, because it is not itself a set.
See also
*
Universe (mathematics)
*
Grothendieck universe
*
Domain of discourse
*
Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory — an extension of ZFC that admits the class of all sets
Notes
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Willard Van Orman Quine
Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century" ...
(1937) "New Foundations for Mathematical Logic," ''American Mathematical Monthly'' 44, pp. 70–80.
*
External links
*
Bibliography: Set Theory with a Universal Set originated by T. E. Forster and maintained by Randall Holmes.
{{DEFAULTSORT:Universal Set
Basic concepts in set theory
Families of sets
Paradoxes of naive set theory
Systems of set theory
Wellfoundedness
Self-reference