HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often
equiconsistent In mathematical logic, two theories are equiconsistent if the consistency of one theory implies the consistency of the other theory, and vice versa. In this case, they are, roughly speaking, "as consistent as each other". In general, it is not ...
, and if one theory has a larger proof-theoretic ordinal than another it can often prove the consistency of the second theory.


History

The field of ordinal analysis was formed when Gerhard Gentzen in 1934 used cut elimination to prove, in modern terms, that the proof-theoretic ordinal of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly ...
is ε0. See
Gentzen's consistency proof Gentzen's consistency proof is a result of proof theory in mathematical logic, published by Gerhard Gentzen in 1936. It shows that the Peano axioms of first-order arithmetic do not contain a contradiction (i.e. are " consistent"), as long as a c ...
.


Definition

Ordinal analysis concerns true, effective (recursive) theories that can interpret a sufficient portion of arithmetic to make statements about ordinal notations. The proof-theoretic ordinal of such a theory T is the supremum of the order types of all ordinal notations (necessarily recursive, see next section) that the theory can prove are well founded—the supremum of all ordinals \alpha for which there exists a notation o in Kleene's sense such that T proves that o is an ordinal notation. Equivalently, it is the supremum of all ordinals \alpha such that there exists a recursive relation R on \omega (the set of natural numbers) that well-orders it with ordinal \alpha and such that T proves transfinite induction of arithmetical statements for R.


Ordinal notations

Some theories, such as subsystems of second-order arithmetic, have no conceptualization of or way to make arguments about transfinite ordinals. For example, to formalize what it means for a subsystem of Z2 T to "prove \alpha well-ordered", we instead construct an ordinal notation (A,\tilde <) with order type \alpha. T can now work with various transfinite induction principles along (A,\tilde <), which substitute for reasoning about set-theoretic ordinals. However, some pathological notation systems exist that are unexpectedly difficult to work with. For example, Rathjen gives a primitive recursive notation system (\mathbb N,<_T) that is well-founded iff PA is consistent, despite having order type \omega - including such a notation in the ordinal analysis of PA would result in the false equality \mathsf=\omega.


Upper bound

For any theory that's both \Sigma^1_1-axiomatizable and \Pi^1_1-sound, the existence of a recursive ordering that the theory fails to prove is well-ordered follows from the \Sigma^1_1 bounding theorem, and said provably well-founded ordinal notations are in fact well-founded by \Pi^1_1-soundness. Thus the proof-theoretic ordinal of a \Pi^1_1-sound theory that has a \Sigma^1_1 axiomatization will always be a (countable) recursive ordinal, that is, less than the Church–Kleene ordinal \omega_1^.


Examples


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ω

*Q, Robinson arithmetic (although the definition of the proof-theoretic ordinal for such weak theories has to be tweaked). *PA, the first-order theory of the nonnegative part of a discretely ordered ring.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ω2

*RFA,
rudimentary function In set theory, a mathematical discipline, the Jensen hierarchy or J-hierarchy is a modification of Gödel's constructible hierarchy, L, that circumvents certain technical difficulties that exist in the constructible hierarchy. The J-Hierarchy figu ...
arithmetic. defines the rudimentary sets and rudimentary functions, and proves them equivalent to the Δ0-predicates on the naturals. An ordinal analysis of the system can be found in *IΔ0, arithmetic with induction on Δ0-predicates without any axiom asserting that exponentiation is total.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ω3

*EFA, elementary function arithmetic. *IΔ0 + exp, arithmetic with induction on Δ0-predicates augmented by an axiom asserting that exponentiation is total. *RCA, a second order form of EFA sometimes used in reverse mathematics. *WKL, a second order form of EFA sometimes used in reverse mathematics. Friedman's grand conjecture suggests that much "ordinary" mathematics can be proved in weak systems having this as their proof-theoretic ordinal.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ω''n'' (for ''n'' = 2, 3, ... ω)

*IΔ0 or EFA augmented by an axiom ensuring that each element of the ''n''-th level \mathcal^n of the Grzegorczyk hierarchy is total.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ωω

*RCA0, recursive comprehension. *WKL0, weak König's lemma. *PRA, primitive recursive arithmetic. *IΣ1, arithmetic with induction on Σ1-predicates.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal ε0

*PA,
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly ...
( shown by Gentzen using cut elimination). *ACA0, arithmetical comprehension.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0

*ATR0, arithmetical transfinite recursion. * Martin-Löf type theory with arbitrarily many finite level universes. This ordinal is sometimes considered to be the upper limit for "predicative" theories.


Theories with proof-theoretic ordinal the Bachmann–Howard ordinal

* ID1, the first theory of inductive definitions. * KP, Kripke–Platek set theory with the axiom of infinity. * CZF, Aczel's constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. * EON, a weak variant of the Feferman's explicit mathematics system T0. The Kripke-Platek or CZF set theories are weak set theories without axioms for the full powerset given as set of all subsets. Instead, they tend to either have axioms of restricted separation and formation of new sets, or they grant existence of certain function spaces (exponentiation) instead of carving them out from bigger relations.


Theories with larger proof-theoretic ordinals

*\Pi^1_1\mbox\mathsf_0, Π11 comprehension has a rather large proof-theoretic ordinal, which was described by Takeuti in terms of "ordinal diagrams", and which is bounded by ψ0ω) in
Buchholz's notation In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal notation is a partial function mapping the set of all finite sequences of symbols, themselves members of a finite alphabet, to a countable set of ordinals. A Gödel numbering is a function mapping t ...
. It is also the ordinal of ID_, the theory of finitely iterated inductive definitions. And also the ordinal of MLW, Martin-Löf type theory with indexed W-Types . *IDω, the theory of ω-iterated inductive definitions. Its proof-theoretic ordinal is equal to the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal. *T0, Feferman's constructive system of explicit mathematics has a larger proof-theoretic ordinal, which is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of the KPi, Kripke–Platek set theory with iterated admissibles and \Sigma^1_2\mbox\mathsf + \mathsf. *KPi, an extension of Kripke–Platek set theory based on a recursively inaccessible ordinal, has a very large proof-theoretic ordinal \psi(\varepsilon_) described in a 1983 paper of Jäger and Pohlers, where I is the smallest inaccessible.D. Madore
A Zoo of Ordinals
(2017, p.2). Accessed 12 August 2022.
This ordinal is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of \Delta^1_2\mbox\mathsf + \mathsf. *KPM, an extension of Kripke–Platek set theory based on a recursively Mahlo ordinal, has a very large proof-theoretic ordinal θ, which was described by . *MLM, an extension of Martin-Löf type theory by one Mahlo-universe, has an even larger proof-theoretic ordinal ψΩ1M + ω). *\mathsf + \Pi_3 - Ref has a proof-theoretic ordinal equal to \Psi(\varepsilon_), where K refers to the first weakly compact, using Rathjen's Psi function *\mathsf + \Pi_\omega - Ref has a proof-theoretic ordinal equal to \Psi^_X, where \Xi refers to the first \Pi^2_0-indescribable and \mathbb = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0), using Stegert's Psi function. *\mathsf has a proof-theoretic ordinal equal to \Psi^_ where \Upsilon is a cardinal analogue of the least ordinal \alpha which is \alpha+\beta-stable for all \beta < \alpha and \mathbb = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0), using Stegert's Psi function. Most theories capable of describing the power set of the natural numbers have proof-theoretic ordinals that are so large that no explicit combinatorial description has yet been given. This includes \Pi^1_2 - CA_0, full
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics. A precu ...
(\Pi^1_\infty - CA_0) and set theories with powersets including ZF and ZFC. The strength of intuitionistic ZF (IZF) equals that of ZF.


Table of ordinal analyses


Key

This is a list of symbols used in this table: * ψ represents Buchholz's psi unless stated otherwise. * Ψ represents either Rathjen's or Stegert's Psi. * φ represents Veblen's function. * ω represents the first transfinite ordinal. * εα represents the epsilon numbers. * Γα represents the gamma numbers (Γ0 is the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion. It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schüt ...
) * Ωα represent the uncountable ordinals (Ω1, abbreviated Ω, is ω1). This is a list of the abbreviations used in this table: * First-order arithmetic ** \mathsf is Robinson arithmetic ** \mathsf^- is the first-order theory of the nonnegative part of a discretely ordered ring. ** \mathsf is
rudimentary function In set theory, a mathematical discipline, the Jensen hierarchy or J-hierarchy is a modification of Gödel's constructible hierarchy, L, that circumvents certain technical difficulties that exist in the constructible hierarchy. The J-Hierarchy figu ...
arithmetic. ** \mathsf_0 is arithmetic with induction restricted to Δ0-predicates without any axiom asserting that exponentiation is total. ** \mathsf is elementary function arithmetic. ** \mathsf_0^ is arithmetic with induction restricted to Δ0-predicates augmented by an axiom asserting that exponentiation is total. ** \mathsf^ is elementary function arithmetic augmented by an axiom ensuring that each element of the ''n''-th level \mathcal^n of the Grzegorczyk hierarchy is total. ** \mathsf_0^ is \mathsf_0^ augmented by an axiom ensuring that each element of the ''n''-th level \mathcal^n of the Grzegorczyk hierarchy is total. ** \mathsf is primitive recursive arithmetic. ** \mathsf_1 is arithmetic with induction restricted to Σ1-predicates. ** \mathsf is
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly ...
. ** \mathsf_\nu\# is \widehat_\nu but with induction only for positive formulas. ** \widehat_\nu extends PA by ν iterated fixed points of monotone operators. ** \mathsf is not exactly a first-order arithmetic system, but captures what one can get by predicative reasoning based on the natural numbers. ** \mathsf is an automorphism on \widehat_\nu. ** \mathsf_\nu extends PA by ν iterated least fixed points of monotone operators. ** \mathsf_\nu\mathsf is not exactly a first-order arithmetic system, but captures what one can get by predicative reasoning based on ν-times iterated generalized inductive definitions. **\mathsf is an automorphism on \mathsf_\nu\mathsf. ** \mathsf_ is a weakened version of \mathsf_ based on W-types. * Second-order arithmetic ** \mathsf_0^* is a second order form of \mathsf sometimes used in reverse mathematics. ** \mathsf_0^* is a second order form of \mathsf sometimes used in reverse mathematics. ** \mathsf_0 is recursive comprehension. ** \mathsf_0 is weak König's lemma. ** \mathsf_0 is arithmetical comprehension. ** \mathsf is \mathsf_0 plus the full second-order induction scheme. ** \mathsf_0 is arithmetical transfinite recursion. ** \mathsf is \mathsf_0 plus the full second-order induction scheme. ** \mathsf_2^1\mathsf is \mathsf_2^1\mathsf plus the assertion ''"every true \mathsf^1_3-sentence with parameters holds in a (countable coded) \beta-model of \mathsf_2^1\mathsf".'' * Kripke-Platek set theory ** \mathsf is Kripke-Platek set theory with the axiom of infinity. ** \mathsf is Kripke-Platek set theory, whose universe is an admissible set containing \omega. ** \mathsf is a weakened version of \mathsf based on W-types. ** \mathsf asserts that the universe is a limit of admissible sets. ** \mathsf is a weakened version of \mathsf based on W-types. ** \mathsf asserts that the universe is inaccessible sets. ** \mathsf asserts that the universe is hyperinaccessible: an inaccessible set and a limit of inaccessible sets. ** \mathsf asserts that the universe is a Mahlo set. ** \mathsf_\mathsf - \mathsf is \mathsf augmented by a certain first-order reflection scheme. ** \mathsf is KPi augmented by the axiom \forall \alpha \exists \kappa \geq \alpha (L_\kappa \preceq_1 L_). ** \mathsf^+ is KPI augmented by the assertion ''"at least one recursively Mahlo ordinal exists".'' A superscript zero indicates that \in-induction is removed (making the theory significantly weaker). * Type theory ** \mathsf is the Herbelin-Patey Calculus of Primitive Recursive Constructions. ** \mathsf_\mathsf is type theory without W-types and with n universes. ** \mathsf_ is type theory without W-types and with finitely many universes. ** \mathsf is type theory with a next universe operator. ** \mathsf is type theory without W-types and with a superuniverse. **\mathsf is an automorphism on type theory without W-types. ** \mathsf_1\mathsf is type theory with one universe and Aczel's type of iterative sets. ** \mathsf is type theory with indexed W-Types. ** \mathsf_1\mathsf is type theory with W-types and one universe. ** \mathsf_\mathsf is type theory with W-types and finitely many universes. **\mathsf is an automorphism on type theory with W-types. ** \mathsf is type theory with a Mahlo universe. * Constructive set theory ** \mathsf is Aczel's constructive set theory. ** \mathsf is \mathsf plus the regular extension axiom. ** \mathsf_2 is \mathsf plus the full-second order induction scheme. ** \mathsf is \mathsf with a Mahlo universe. * Explicit mathematics ** \mathsf_0 is basic explicit mathematics plus elementary comprehension ** \mathsf_0 \mathsf is \mathsf_0 plus join rule ** \mathsf_0 \mathsf is \mathsf_0 plus join axioms ** \mathsf is a weak variant of the Feferman's \mathsf_0. ** \mathsf_0 is \mathsf_0 \mathsf, where \mathsf is inductive generation. ** \mathsf is \mathsf_0 \mathsf_2, where \mathsf_2 is the full second-order induction scheme.


See also

* Equiconsistency * Large cardinal property *
Feferman–Schütte ordinal In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion. It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schüt ...
* Bachmann–Howard ordinal *
Complexity class In computational complexity theory, a complexity class is a set of computational problems of related resource-based complexity. The two most commonly analyzed resources are time and memory. In general, a complexity class is defined in terms ...
*
Gentzen's consistency proof Gentzen's consistency proof is a result of proof theory in mathematical logic, published by Gerhard Gentzen in 1936. It shows that the Peano axioms of first-order arithmetic do not contain a contradiction (i.e. are " consistent"), as long as a c ...


Notes

:1.For 1 < n \leq \omega :2.The Veblen function \varphi with countably infinitely iterated least fixed points. :3.Can also be commonly written as \psi(\varepsilon_) in Madore's ψ. :4.Uses Madore's ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :5.Can also be commonly written as \psi(\varepsilon_) in Madore's ψ. :6.K represents the first recursively weakly compact ordinal. Uses Arai's ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :7.Also the proof-theoretic ordinal of \mathsf, as the amount of weakening given by the W-types is not enough. :8.I represents the first inaccessible cardinal. Uses Jäger's ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :9.L represents the limit of the \omega-inaccessible cardinals. Uses (presumably) Jäger's ψ. :10.L^*represents the limit of the \Omega-inaccessible cardinals. Uses (presumably) Jäger's ψ. :11.M represents the first Mahlo cardinal. Uses Rathjen's ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :12.K represents the first weakly compact cardinal. Uses Rathjen's Ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :13.\Xi represents the first \Pi^2_0-indescribable cardinal. Uses Stegert's Ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :14.Y is the smallest \alpha such that \forall \theta < Y \exists \kappa < Y ('\kappa is \theta-indescribable') and \forall \theta < Y \forall \kappa < Y ('\kappa is \theta-indescribable \rightarrow \theta < \kappa'). Uses Stegert's Ψ rather than Buchholz's ψ. :15.M represents the first Mahlo cardinal. Uses (presumably) Rathjen's ψ.


Citations


References

* * * * * * * * *{{citation, mr=0882549, last= Takeuti, first= Gaisi , title=Proof theory, edition= Second , series= Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, volume= 81, publisher= North-Holland Publishing Co., place= Amsterdam, year=1987, isbn= 0-444-87943-9 Proof theory Ordinal numbers