HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, nonstandard calculus is the modern application of
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a non-zero quantity that is closer to 0 than any non-zero real number is. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally referred to the " ...
s, in the sense of
nonstandard analysis The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using (ε, δ)-definitio ...
, to infinitesimal
calculus Calculus is the mathematics, mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations. Originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the ...
. It provides a rigorous justification for some arguments in calculus that were previously considered merely
heuristic A heuristic or heuristic technique (''problem solving'', '' mental shortcut'', ''rule of thumb'') is any approach to problem solving that employs a pragmatic method that is not fully optimized, perfected, or rationalized, but is nevertheless ...
. Non-rigorous calculations with infinitesimals were widely used before
Karl Weierstrass Karl Theodor Wilhelm Weierstrass (; ; 31 October 1815 – 19 February 1897) was a German mathematician often cited as the " father of modern analysis". Despite leaving university without a degree, he studied mathematics and trained as a school t ...
sought to replace them with the
(ε, δ)-definition of limit Although the function is not defined at zero, as becomes closer and closer to zero, becomes arbitrarily close to 1. In other words, the limit of as approaches zero, equals 1. In mathematics, the limit of a function is a fundame ...
starting in the 1870s. For almost one hundred years thereafter, mathematicians such as
Richard Courant Richard Courant (January 8, 1888 – January 27, 1972) was a German-American mathematician. He is best known by the general public for the book '' What is Mathematics?'', co-written with Herbert Robbins. His research focused on the areas of real ...
viewed infinitesimals as being naive and vague or meaningless. Contrary to such views, Abraham Robinson showed in 1960 that infinitesimals are precise, clear, and meaningful, building upon work by Edwin Hewitt and Jerzy Łoś. According to Howard Keisler, "Robinson solved a three hundred year old problem by giving a precise treatment of infinitesimals. Robinson's achievement will probably rank as one of the major mathematical advances of the twentieth century."


History

The history of nonstandard calculus began with the use of infinitely small quantities, called
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a non-zero quantity that is closer to 0 than any non-zero real number is. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally referred to the " ...
s in
calculus Calculus is the mathematics, mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations. Originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the ...
. The use of infinitesimals can be found in the foundations of calculus independently developed by
Gottfried Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (or Leibnitz; – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat who is credited, alongside Isaac Newton, Sir Isaac Newton, with the creation of calculus in ad ...
and
Isaac Newton Sir Isaac Newton () was an English polymath active as a mathematician, physicist, astronomer, alchemist, theologian, and author. Newton was a key figure in the Scientific Revolution and the Age of Enlightenment, Enlightenment that followed ...
starting in the 1660s.
John Wallis John Wallis (; ; ) was an English clergyman and mathematician, who is given partial credit for the development of infinitesimal calculus. Between 1643 and 1689 Wallis served as chief cryptographer for Parliament and, later, the royal court. ...
refined earlier techniques of indivisibles of Cavalieri and others by exploiting an
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a non-zero quantity that is closer to 0 than any non-zero real number is. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally referred to the " ...
quantity he denoted \tfrac in area calculations, preparing the ground for integral
calculus Calculus is the mathematics, mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations. Originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the ...
. They drew on the work of such mathematicians as
Pierre de Fermat Pierre de Fermat (; ; 17 August 1601 – 12 January 1665) was a French mathematician who is given credit for early developments that led to infinitesimal calculus, including his technique of adequality. In particular, he is recognized for his d ...
,
Isaac Barrow Isaac Barrow (October 1630 – 4 May 1677) was an English Christian theologian and mathematician who is generally given credit for his early role in the development of infinitesimal calculus; in particular, for proof of the fundamental theorem ...
and
René Descartes René Descartes ( , ; ; 31 March 1596 – 11 February 1650) was a French philosopher, scientist, and mathematician, widely considered a seminal figure in the emergence of modern philosophy and Modern science, science. Mathematics was paramou ...
. In early calculus the use of
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a non-zero quantity that is closer to 0 than any non-zero real number is. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally referred to the " ...
quantities was criticized by a number of authors, most notably Michel Rolle and Bishop Berkeley in his book ''
The Analyst ''The Analyst'' (subtitled ''A Discourse Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician: Wherein It Is Examined Whether the Object, Principles, and Inferences of the Modern Analysis Are More Distinctly Conceived, or More Evidently Deduced, Than Religious ...
''. Several mathematicians, including Maclaurin and
d'Alembert Jean-Baptiste le Rond d'Alembert ( ; ; 16 November 1717 – 29 October 1783) was a French mathematician, mechanics, mechanician, physicist, philosopher, and music theorist. Until 1759 he was, together with Denis Diderot, a co-editor of the ''E ...
, advocated the use of limits. Augustin Louis Cauchy developed a versatile spectrum of foundational approaches, including a definition of continuity in terms of infinitesimals and a (somewhat imprecise) prototype of an ε, δ argument in working with differentiation.
Karl Weierstrass Karl Theodor Wilhelm Weierstrass (; ; 31 October 1815 – 19 February 1897) was a German mathematician often cited as the " father of modern analysis". Despite leaving university without a degree, he studied mathematics and trained as a school t ...
formalized the concept of limit in the context of a (real) number system without infinitesimals. Following the work of Weierstrass, it eventually became common to base calculus on ε, δ arguments instead of infinitesimals. This approach formalized by Weierstrass came to be known as the ''standard'' calculus. After many years of the infinitesimal approach to calculus having fallen into disuse other than as an introductory pedagogical tool, use of infinitesimal quantities was finally given a rigorous foundation by Abraham Robinson in the 1960s. Robinson's approach is called
nonstandard analysis The history of calculus is fraught with philosophical debates about the meaning and logical validity of fluxions or infinitesimal numbers. The standard way to resolve these debates is to define the operations of calculus using (ε, δ)-definitio ...
to distinguish it from the standard use of limits. This approach used technical machinery from
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
to create a theory of
hyperreal number In mathematics, hyperreal numbers are an extension of the real numbers to include certain classes of infinite and infinitesimal numbers. A hyperreal number x is said to be finite if, and only if, , x, for some integer n
s that interpret infinitesimals in a manner that allows a Leibniz-like development of the usual rules of calculus. An alternative approach, developed by
Edward Nelson Edward Nelson (May 4, 1932 – September 10, 2014) was an American mathematician. He was professor in the Mathematics Department at Princeton University. He was known for his work on mathematical physics and mathematical logic. In mathematical l ...
, finds infinitesimals on the ordinary real line itself, and involves a modification of the foundational setting by extending ZFC through the introduction of a new unary predicate "standard".


Motivation

To calculate the derivative f ' of the function y =f(x)=x^2 at ''x'', both approaches agree on the algebraic manipulations: : \frac = \frac = \frac = 2 x + \Delta x \approx 2 x This becomes a computation of the derivatives using the
hyperreals In mathematics, hyperreal numbers are an extension of the real numbers to include certain classes of infinite and infinitesimal numbers. A hyperreal number x is said to be finite if, and only if, , x, for some integer n
if \Delta x is interpreted as an infinitesimal and the symbol "\approx" is the relation "is infinitely close to". In order to make ''f a real-valued function, the final term \Delta x is dispensed with. In the standard approach using only real numbers, that is done by taking the limit as \Delta x tends to zero. In the
hyperreal Hyperreal may refer to: * Hyperreal numbers, an extension of the real numbers in mathematics that are used in non-standard analysis * Hyperreal.org, a rave culture website based in San Francisco, US * Hyperreality, a term used in semiotics and po ...
approach, the quantity \Delta x is taken to be an infinitesimal, a nonzero number that is closer to 0 than to any nonzero real. The manipulations displayed above then show that \Delta y /\Delta x is infinitely close to 2''x'', so the derivative of ''f'' at ''x'' is then 2''x''. Discarding the "error term" is accomplished by an application of the
standard part function In nonstandard analysis, the standard part function is a function from the limited (finite) hyperreal numbers to the real numbers. Briefly, the standard part function "rounds off" a finite hyperreal to the nearest real. It associates to every suc ...
. Dispensing with infinitesimal error terms was historically considered paradoxical by some writers, most notably
George Berkeley George Berkeley ( ; 12 March 168514 January 1753), known as Bishop Berkeley (Bishop of Cloyne of the Anglican Church of Ireland), was an Anglo-Irish philosopher, writer, and clergyman who is regarded as the founder of "immaterialism", a philos ...
. Once the hyperreal number system (an infinitesimal-enriched continuum) is in place, one has successfully incorporated a large part of the technical difficulties at the foundational level. Thus, the epsilon, delta techniques that some believe to be the essence of analysis can be implemented once and for all at the foundational level, and the students needn't be "dressed to perform multiple-quantifier logical stunts on pretense of being taught
infinitesimal calculus Calculus is the mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations. Originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the calculus of ...
", to quote a recent study. More specifically, the basic concepts of calculus such as continuity, derivative, and integral can be defined using infinitesimals without reference to epsilon, delta.


Keisler's textbook

Keisler's Elementary Calculus: An Infinitesimal Approach defines continuity on page 125 in terms of infinitesimals, to the exclusion of epsilon, delta methods. The derivative is defined on page 45 using infinitesimals rather than an epsilon-delta approach. The integral is defined on page 183 in terms of infinitesimals. Epsilon, delta definitions are introduced on page 282.


Definition of derivative

The
hyperreals In mathematics, hyperreal numbers are an extension of the real numbers to include certain classes of infinite and infinitesimal numbers. A hyperreal number x is said to be finite if, and only if, , x, for some integer n
can be constructed in the framework of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, the standard axiomatisation of set theory used elsewhere in mathematics. To give an intuitive idea for the hyperreal approach, note that, naively speaking, nonstandard analysis postulates the existence of positive numbers ε ''which are infinitely small'', meaning that ε is smaller than any standard positive real, yet greater than zero. Every real number ''x'' is surrounded by an infinitesimal "cloud" of hyperreal numbers infinitely close to it. To define the derivative of ''f'' at a standard real number ''x'' in this approach, one no longer needs an infinite limiting process as in standard calculus. Instead, one sets : f'(x) = \mathrm \left( \frac \right), where st is the
standard part function In nonstandard analysis, the standard part function is a function from the limited (finite) hyperreal numbers to the real numbers. Briefly, the standard part function "rounds off" a finite hyperreal to the nearest real. It associates to every suc ...
, yielding the real number infinitely close to the hyperreal argument of st, and f^* is the natural extension of f to the hyperreals.


Continuity

A real function ''f'' is continuous at a standard real number ''x'' if for every hyperreal ''x' '' infinitely close to ''x'', the value ''f''(''x' '') is also infinitely close to ''f''(''x''). This captures Cauchy's definition of continuity as presented in his 1821 textbook Cours d'Analyse, p. 34. Here to be precise, ''f'' would have to be replaced by its natural hyperreal extension usually denoted ''f''*. Using the notation \approx for the relation of being infinitely close as above, the definition can be extended to arbitrary (standard or nonstandard) points as follows: A function ''f'' is '' microcontinuous'' at ''x'' if whenever x'\approx x, one has f^*(x')\approx f^*(x) Here the point x' is assumed to be in the domain of (the natural extension of) ''f''. The above requires fewer quantifiers than the (''ε'', ''δ'')-definition familiar from standard elementary calculus: ''f'' is continuous at ''x'' if for every ''ε'' > 0, there exists a ''δ'' > 0 such that for every ''x' '', whenever , ''x'' − ''x' '',  < ''δ'', one has , ''f''(''x'') − ''f''(''x' ''),  < ''ε''.


Uniform continuity

A function ''f'' on an interval ''I'' is uniformly continuous if its natural extension ''f''* in ''I''* has the following property: for every pair of hyperreals ''x'' and ''y'' in ''I''*, if x\approx y then f^*(x)\approx f^*(y). In terms of microcontinuity defined in the previous section, this can be stated as follows: a real function is uniformly continuous if its natural extension f* is microcontinuous at every point of the domain of f*. This definition has a reduced quantifier complexity when compared with the standard (ε, δ)-definition. Namely, the epsilon-delta definition of uniform continuity requires four quantifiers, while the infinitesimal definition requires only two quantifiers. It has the same quantifier complexity as the definition of uniform continuity in terms of ''sequences'' in standard calculus, which however is not expressible in the
first-order language First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
of the real numbers. The hyperreal definition can be illustrated by the following three examples. Example 1: a function ''f'' is uniformly continuous on the semi-open interval (0,1], if and only if its natural extension f* is microcontinuous (in the sense of the formula above) at every positive infinitesimal, in addition to continuity at the standard points of the interval. Example 2: a function ''f'' is uniformly continuous on the semi-open interval [0,∞) if and only if it is continuous at the standard points of the interval, and in addition, the natural extension ''f''* is microcontinuous at every positive infinite hyperreal point. Example 3: similarly, the failure of uniform continuity for the squaring function :x^2 is due to the absence of microcontinuity at a single infinite hyperreal point. Concerning quantifier complexity, the following remarks were made by Kevin Houston (mathematician), Kevin Houston: :The number of quantifiers in a mathematical statement gives a rough measure of the statement’s complexity. Statements involving three or more quantifiers can be difficult to understand. This is the main reason why it is hard to understand the rigorous definitions of limit, convergence, continuity and differentiability in analysis as they have many quantifiers. In fact, it is the alternation of the \forall and \exists that causes the complexity. Andreas Blass wrote as follows: :Often ... the nonstandard definition of a concept is simpler than the standard definition (both intuitively simpler and simpler in a technical sense, such as quantifiers over lower types or fewer alternations of quantifiers).


Compactness

A set A is compact if and only if its natural extension A* has the following property: every point in A* is infinitely close to a point of A. Thus, the open interval (0,1) is not compact because its natural extension contains positive infinitesimals which are not infinitely close to any positive real number.


Heine–Cantor theorem

The fact that a continuous function on a compact interval ''I'' is necessarily uniformly continuous (the
Heine–Cantor theorem In mathematics, the Heine–Cantor theorem states that a continuous function between two metric spaces is uniformly continuous if its domain is compact. The theorem is named after Eduard Heine and Georg Cantor. An important special case of the C ...
) admits a succinct hyperreal proof. Let ''x'', ''y'' be hyperreals in the natural extension ''I*'' of ''I''. Since ''I'' is compact, both st(''x'') and st(''y'') belong to ''I''. If ''x'' and ''y'' were infinitely close, then by the triangle inequality, they would have the same standard part :c = \operatorname(x) = \operatorname(y). Since the function is assumed continuous at c, :f(x)\approx f(c)\approx f(y), and therefore ''f''(''x'') and ''f''(''y'') are infinitely close, proving uniform continuity of ''f''.


Why is the squaring function not uniformly continuous?

Let ''f''(''x'') = ''x''2 defined on \mathbb. Let N\in \mathbb^* be an infinite hyperreal. The hyperreal number N + \tfrac is infinitely close to ''N''. Meanwhile, the difference : f(N+\tfrac) - f(N) = N^2 + 2 + \tfrac - N^2 = 2 + \tfrac is not infinitesimal. Therefore, ''f*'' fails to be microcontinuous at the hyperreal point ''N''. Thus, the squaring function is not uniformly continuous, according to the definition in
uniform continuity In mathematics, a real function f of real numbers is said to be uniformly continuous if there is a positive real number \delta such that function values over any function domain interval of the size \delta are as close to each other as we want. In ...
above. A similar proof may be given in the standard setting .


Example: Dirichlet function

Consider the
Dirichlet function In mathematics, the Dirichlet function is the indicator function \mathbf_\Q of the set of rational numbers \Q, i.e. \mathbf_\Q(x) = 1 if is a rational number and \mathbf_\Q(x) = 0 if is not a rational number (i.e. is an irrational number). \mathb ...
:I_Q(x):=\begin 1 & \textx \text, \\ 0 & \text x \text. \end It is well known that, under the standard definition of continuity, the function is discontinuous at every point. Let us check this in terms of the hyperreal definition of continuity above, for instance let us show that the Dirichlet function is not continuous at π. Consider the continued fraction approximation an of π. Now let the index n be an infinite hypernatural number. By the
transfer principle In model theory, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the firs ...
, the natural extension of the Dirichlet function takes the value 1 at an. Note that the hyperrational point an is infinitely close to π. Thus the natural extension of the Dirichlet function takes different values (0 and 1) at these two infinitely close points, and therefore the Dirichlet function is not continuous at ''π''.


Limit

While the thrust of Robinson's approach is that one can dispense with the approach using multiple quantifiers, the notion of limit can be easily recaptured in terms of the
standard part function In nonstandard analysis, the standard part function is a function from the limited (finite) hyperreal numbers to the real numbers. Briefly, the standard part function "rounds off" a finite hyperreal to the nearest real. It associates to every suc ...
st, namely :\lim_ f(x) = L if and only if whenever the difference ''x'' − ''a'' is infinitesimal, the difference ''f''(''x'') − ''L'' is infinitesimal, as well, or in formulas: :if st(''x'') = ''a''  then st(''f''(''x'')) = L, cf.
(ε, δ)-definition of limit Although the function is not defined at zero, as becomes closer and closer to zero, becomes arbitrarily close to 1. In other words, the limit of as approaches zero, equals 1. In mathematics, the limit of a function is a fundame ...
.


Limit of sequence

Given a sequence of real numbers \, if L\in \R ''L'' is ''the limit'' of the sequence and : L = \lim_ x_n if for every infinite hypernatural ''n'', st(''x''''n'')=''L'' (here the extension principle is used to define ''x''''n'' for every hyperinteger ''n''). This definition has no quantifier alternations. The standard (ε, δ)-style definition, on the other hand, does have quantifier alternations: :L = \lim_ x_n \Longleftrightarrow \forall \varepsilon>0\;, \exists N \in \N\;, \forall n \in \N : n >N \rightarrow , x_n - L, < \varepsilon.


Extreme value theorem

To show that a real continuous function ''f'' on ,1has a maximum, let ''N'' be an infinite hyperinteger. The interval , 1has a natural hyperreal extension. The function ''f'' is also naturally extended to hyperreals between 0 and 1. Consider the partition of the hyperreal interval ,1into ''N'' subintervals of equal
infinitesimal In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a non-zero quantity that is closer to 0 than any non-zero real number is. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally referred to the " ...
length 1/''N'', with partition points ''x''''i'' = ''i'' /''N'' as ''i'' "runs" from 0 to ''N''. In the standard setting (when ''N'' is finite), a point with the maximal value of ''f'' can always be chosen among the ''N''+1 points ''x''''i'', by induction. Hence, by the
transfer principle In model theory, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the firs ...
, there is a hyperinteger ''i''0 such that 0 ≤ ''i''0 ≤ ''N'' and f(x_)\geq f(x_i) for all ''i'' = 0, …, ''N'' (an alternative explanation is that every hyperfinite set admits a maximum). Consider the real point :c= (x_) where st is the
standard part function In nonstandard analysis, the standard part function is a function from the limited (finite) hyperreal numbers to the real numbers. Briefly, the standard part function "rounds off" a finite hyperreal to the nearest real. It associates to every suc ...
. An arbitrary real point ''x'' lies in a suitable sub-interval of the partition, namely x\in _i,x_/math>, so that st(''x''''i'') = ''x''. Applying st to the inequality f(x_)\geq f(x_i), (f(x_))\geq (f(x_i)). By continuity of ''f'', :(f(x_))= f( (x_))=f(c). Hence ''f''(''c'') ≥ ''f''(''x''), for all ''x'', proving ''c'' to be a maximum of the real function ''f''.


Intermediate value theorem

As another illustration of the power of Robinson's approach, a short proof of the
intermediate value theorem In mathematical analysis, the intermediate value theorem states that if f is a continuous function whose domain contains the interval , then it takes on any given value between f(a) and f(b) at some point within the interval. This has two imp ...
(Bolzano's theorem) using infinitesimals is done by the following. Let ''f'' be a continuous function on 'a'',''b''such that ''f''(''a'')<0 while ''f''(''b'')>0. Then there exists a point ''c'' in 'a'',''b''such that ''f''(''c'')=0. The proof proceeds as follows. Let ''N'' be an infinite hyperinteger. Consider a partition of 'a'',''b''into ''N'' intervals of equal length, with partition points ''xi'' as ''i'' runs from 0 to ''N''. Consider the collection ''I'' of indices such that ''f''(''x''''i'')>0. Let ''i''0 be the least element in ''I'' (such an element exists by the
transfer principle In model theory, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the firs ...
, as ''I'' is a hyperfinite set). Then the real number c=\mathrm(x_) is the desired zero of ''f''. Such a proof reduces the quantifier complexity of a standard proof of the IVT.


Basic theorems

If ''f'' is a real valued function defined on an interval 'a'', ''b'' then the transfer operator applied to ''f'', denoted by ''*f'', is an ''internal'', hyperreal-valued function defined on the hyperreal interval ''a'', *''b'' ''Theorem'': Let ''f'' be a real-valued function defined on an interval 'a'', ''b'' Then ''f'' is differentiable at ''a < x < b'' if and only if for every ''non-zero'' infinitesimal ''h'', the value : \Delta_h f := \operatorname \frac is independent of ''h''. In that case, the common value is the derivative of ''f'' at ''x''. This fact follows from the
transfer principle In model theory, a transfer principle states that all statements of some language that are true for some structure are true for another structure. One of the first examples was the Lefschetz principle, which states that any sentence in the firs ...
of nonstandard analysis and overspill. Note that a similar result holds for differentiability at the endpoints ''a'', ''b'' provided the sign of the infinitesimal ''h'' is suitably restricted. For the second theorem, the Riemann integral is defined as the limit, if it exists, of a directed family of ''Riemann sums''; these are sums of the form : \sum_^ f(\xi_k) (x_ - x_k) where :a = x_0 \leq \xi_0 \leq x_1 \leq \ldots x_ \leq \xi_ \leq x_n = b. Such a sequence of values is called a ''partition'' or ''mesh'' and : \sup_k (x_ - x_k) the width of the mesh. In the definition of the Riemann integral, the limit of the Riemann sums is taken as the width of the mesh goes to 0. ''Theorem'': Let ''f'' be a real-valued function defined on an interval 'a'', ''b'' Then ''f'' is Riemann-integrable on 'a'', ''b''if and only if for every internal mesh of infinitesimal width, the quantity : S_M = \operatorname \sum_^ f\xi_k) (x_ - x_k) is independent of the mesh. In this case, the common value is the Riemann integral of ''f'' over 'a'', ''b''


Applications

One immediate application is an extension of the standard definitions of differentiation and integration to internal functions on intervals of hyperreal numbers. An internal hyperreal-valued function ''f'' on 'a, b''is ''S''-differentiable at ''x'', provided : \Delta_h f = \operatorname \frac exists and is independent of the infinitesimal ''h''. The value is the ''S'' derivative at ''x''. ''Theorem'': Suppose ''f'' is ''S''-differentiable at every point of 'a, b''where ''b'' − ''a'' is a bounded hyperreal. Suppose furthermore that : , f'(x), \leq M \quad a \leq x \leq b. Then for some infinitesimal ε : , f(b) - f(a), \leq M (b-a) + \epsilon. To prove this, let ''N'' be a nonstandard natural number. Divide the interval 'a'', ''b''into ''N'' subintervals by placing ''N'' − 1 equally spaced intermediate points: :a = x_0 < x_1< \cdots < x_ < x_N = b Then : , f(b) - f(a), \leq \sum_^ , f(x_) - f(x_), \leq \sum_^ \left\, x_ - x_, . Now the maximum of any internal set of infinitesimals is infinitesimal. Thus all the εk's are dominated by an infinitesimal ε. Therefore, : , f(b) - f(a), \leq \sum_^ (M + \epsilon)(x_ - x_) = M(b-a) + \epsilon (b-a) from which the result follows.


See also

*
Adequality Adequality is a technique developed by Pierre de Fermat in his treatise ''Methodus ad disquirendam maximam et minimam'' (a Latin treatise circulated in France c. 1636 ) to calculate maxima and minima of functions, tangents to curves, area, center o ...
*
Archimedes' use of infinitesimals ''The Method of Mechanical Theorems'' (), also referred to as ''The Method'', is one of the major surviving works of the ancient Greek polymath Archimedes. ''The Method'' takes the form of a letter from Archimedes to Eratosthenes, the chief libra ...
* Criticism of nonstandard analysis *
Differential_(mathematics) In mathematics, differential refers to several related notions derived from the early days of calculus, put on a rigorous footing, such as infinitesimal differences and the derivatives of functions. The term is used in various branches of mathe ...
* '' Elementary Calculus: An Infinitesimal Approach'' * Non-classical analysis *
History of calculus Calculus, originally called infinitesimal calculus, is a mathematical discipline focused on limits, continuity, derivatives, integrals, and infinite series. Many elements of calculus appeared in ancient Greece, then in China and the Middle East ...


Notes


References

* *H. Jerome Keisler: Elementary Calculus: An Approach Using Infinitesimals. First edition 1976; 2nd edition 1986. (This book is now out of print. The publisher has reverted the copyright to the author, who has made available the 2nd edition in .pdf format available for downloading at http://www.math.wisc.edu/~keisler/calc.html.) *H. Jerome Keisler: Foundations of Infinitesimal Calculus, available for downloading at http://www.math.wisc.edu/~keisler/foundations.html (10 jan '07) * * Baron, Margaret E.: The origins of the infinitesimal calculus. Pergamon Press, Oxford-Edinburgh-New York 1969. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1987. (A new edition of Baron's book appeared in 2004) *


External links

*
On-line version (2022)
*
''Brief Calculus''
(2005, rev. 2015) by Benjamin Crowel. This short text is designed more for self-study or review than for classroom use. Infinitesimals are used when appropriate, and are treated more rigorously than in old books like Thompson's ''Calculus Made Easy'', but in less detail than in Keisler's ''Elementary Calculus: An Approach Using Infinitesimals''. {{Infinitesimals Nonstandard analysis Calculus Infinity