Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with
possible world semantics) is a formal
semantics for
non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by
Saul Kripke and
André Joyal. It was first conceived for
modal logic
Modal logic is a collection of formal systems developed to represent statements about necessity and possibility. It plays a major role in philosophy of language, epistemology, metaphysics, and natural language semantics. Modal logics extend other ...
s, and later adapted to
intuitionistic logic and other non-classical systems. The development of Kripke semantics was a breakthrough in the theory of non-classical logics, because the
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the s ...
of such logics was almost non-existent before Kripke (algebraic semantics existed, but were considered 'syntax in disguise').
Semantics of modal logic
The language of propositional modal logic consists of a
countably infinite set of
propositional variables, a set of truth-functional
connectives (in this article
and
), and the modal operator
("necessarily"). The modal operator
("possibly") is (classically) the
dual
Dual or Duals may refer to:
Paired/two things
* Dual (mathematics), a notion of paired concepts that mirror one another
** Dual (category theory), a formalization of mathematical duality
*** see more cases in :Duality theories
* Dual (grammatical ...
of
and
may be defined in terms of necessity like so:
("possibly A" is defined as equivalent to "not necessarily not A").
Basic definitions
A Kripke frame or modal frame is a pair
, where ''W'' is a (possibly empty) set, and ''R'' is a
binary relation
In mathematics, a binary relation associates elements of one set, called the ''domain'', with elements of another set, called the ''codomain''. A binary relation over Set (mathematics), sets and is a new set of ordered pairs consisting of ele ...
on ''W''. Elements
of ''W'' are called ''nodes'' or ''worlds'', and ''R'' is known as the
accessibility relation.
A Kripke model is a triple
, where
is a Kripke frame, and
is a relation between nodes of ''W'' and modal formulas, such that for all ''w'' ∈ ''W'' and modal formulas ''A'' and ''B'':
*
if and only if
,
*
if and only if
or
,
*
if and only if
for all
such that
.
We read
as “''w'' satisfies
''A''”, “''A'' is satisfied in ''w''”, or
“''w'' forces ''A''”. The relation
is called the
''satisfaction relation'', ''evaluation'', or ''
forcing
Forcing may refer to: Mathematics and science
* Forcing (mathematics), a technique for obtaining independence proofs for set theory
*Forcing (recursion theory), a modification of Paul Cohen's original set theoretic technique of forcing to deal with ...
relation''.
The satisfaction relation is uniquely determined by its
value on propositional variables.
A formula ''A'' is valid in:
* a model
, if
for all ''w'' ∈ ''W'',
* a frame
, if it is valid in
for all possible choices of
,
* a class ''C'' of frames or models, if it is valid in every member of ''C''.
We define Thm(''C'') to be the set of all formulas that are valid in
''C''. Conversely, if ''X'' is a set of formulas, let Mod(''X'') be the
class of all frames which validate every formula from ''X''.
A modal logic (i.e., a set of formulas) ''L'' is
sound with
respect to a class of frames ''C'', if ''L'' ⊆ Thm(''C''). ''L'' is
complete wrt ''C'' if ''L'' ⊇ Thm(''C'').
Correspondence and completeness
Semantics is useful for investigating a logic (i.e. a
derivation system) only if the
semantic consequence relation reflects its syntactical counterpart, the ''
syntactic consequence
Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic, which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A Validity (lo ...
'' relation (''derivability''). It is vital to know which modal logics are sound and complete with respect to a class of Kripke frames, and to determine also which class that is.
For any class ''C'' of Kripke frames, Thm(''C'') is a
normal modal logic (in particular, theorems of the minimal normal modal logic, ''K'', are valid in every Kripke model). However, the converse does not hold in general: while most of the modal systems studied are complete of classes of frames described by simple conditions,
Kripke incomplete normal modal logics do exist. A natural example of such a system is
Japaridze's polymodal logic.
A normal modal logic ''L'' corresponds to a class of frames ''C'', if ''C'' = Mod(''L''). In other words, ''C'' is the largest class of frames such that ''L'' is sound wrt ''C''. It follows that ''L'' is Kripke complete if and only if it is complete of its corresponding class.
Consider the schema T :
.
T is valid in any
reflexive frame
: if
, then
since ''w'' ''R'' ''w''. On the other hand, a frame which
validates T has to be reflexive: fix ''w'' ∈ ''W'', and
define satisfaction of a propositional variable ''p'' as follows:
if and only if ''w'' ''R'' ''u''. Then
, thus
by T, which means ''w'' ''R'' ''w'' using the definition of
. T corresponds to the class of reflexive
Kripke frames.
It is often much easier to characterize the corresponding class of
''L'' than to prove its completeness, thus correspondence serves as a
guide to completeness proofs. Correspondence is also used to show
''incompleteness'' of modal logics: suppose
''L''
1 ⊆ ''L''
2 are normal modal logics that
correspond to the same class of frames, but ''L''
1 does not
prove all theorems of ''L''
2. Then ''L''
1 is
Kripke incomplete. For example, the schema
generates an incomplete logic, as it
corresponds to the same class of frames as GL (viz. transitive and
converse well-founded frames), but does not prove the GL-tautology
.
Common modal axiom schemata
The following table lists common modal axioms together with their corresponding classes. The naming of the axioms often varies; Here, axiom K is named after
Saul Kripke; axiom T is named after the
truth axiom in
epistemic logic; axiom D is named after
deontic logic; axiom B is named after
L. E. J. Brouwer; and axioms 4 and 5 are named based on
C. I. Lewis's numbering of
symbolic logic systems.
Axiom K can also be
rewritten as
, which logically establishes
modus ponens
In propositional logic, ''modus ponens'' (; MP), also known as ''modus ponendo ponens'' (Latin for "method of putting by placing") or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. ...
as a
rule of inference
In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of in ...
in every possible world.
Note that for axiom D,
implicity implies
, which means that for every possible world in the model, there is always at least one possible world accessible from it (which could be itself). This implicit implication
is similar to the implicit implication by
existential quantifier on the range of quantification.
Common modal systems
Canonical models
For any normal modal logic, ''L'', a Kripke model (called the canonical model) can be constructed that refutes precisely the non-theorems of
''L'', by an adaptation of the standard technique of using
maximal consistent sets as models. Canonical Kripke models play a
role similar to the
Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra construction in algebraic
semantics.
A set of formulas is ''L''-''consistent'' if no contradiction can be derived from it using the theorems of ''L'', and Modus Ponens. A ''maximal L-consistent set'' (an ''L''-''MCS''
for short) is an ''L''-consistent set that has no proper ''L''-consistent superset.
The canonical model of ''L'' is a Kripke model
, where ''W'' is the set of all ''L''-''MCS'',
and the relations ''R'' and
are as follows:
:
if and only if for every formula
, if
then
,
:
if and only if
.
The canonical model is a model of ''L'', as every ''L''-''MCS'' contains
all theorems of ''L''. By
Zorn's lemma, each ''L''-consistent set
is contained in an ''L''-''MCS'', in particular every formula
unprovable in ''L'' has a counterexample in the canonical model.
The main application of canonical models are completeness proofs. Properties of the canonical model of K immediately imply completeness of K with respect to the class of all Kripke frames.
This argument does ''not'' work for arbitrary ''L'', because there is no guarantee that the underlying ''frame'' of the canonical model satisfies the frame conditions of ''L''.
We say that a formula or a set ''X'' of formulas is canonical
with respect to a property ''P'' of Kripke frames, if
* ''X'' is valid in every frame that satisfies ''P'',
* for any normal modal logic ''L'' that contains ''X'', the underlying frame of the canonical model of ''L'' satisfies ''P''.
A union of canonical sets of formulas is itself canonical.
It follows from the preceding discussion that any logic axiomatized by
a canonical set of formulas is Kripke complete, and
compact.
The axioms T, 4, D, B, 5, H, G (and thus
any combination of them) are canonical. GL and Grz are not
canonical, because they are not compact. The axiom M by itself is
not canonical (Goldblatt, 1991), but the combined logic S4.1 (in
fact, even K4.1) is canonical.
In general, it is
undecidable whether a given axiom is
canonical. We know a nice sufficient condition:
Henrik Sahlqvist identified a broad class of formulas (now called
Sahlqvist formulas) such that
* a Sahlqvist formula is canonical,
* the class of frames corresponding to a Sahlqvist formula is
first-order definable,
* there is an algorithm that computes the corresponding frame condition to a given Sahlqvist formula.
This is a powerful criterion: for example, all axioms
listed above as canonical are (equivalent to) Sahlqvist formulas.
Finite model property
A logic has the
finite model property (FMP) if it is complete
with respect to a class of finite frames. An application of this
notion is the
decidability question: it
follows from
Post's theorem that a recursively axiomatized modal logic ''L''
which has FMP is decidable, provided it is decidable whether a given
finite frame is a model of ''L''. In particular, every finitely
axiomatizable logic with FMP is decidable.
There are various methods for establishing FMP for a given logic.
Refinements and extensions of the canonical model construction often
work, using tools such as
filtration
Filtration is a physical separation process that separates solid matter and fluid from a mixture using a ''filter medium'' that has a complex structure through which only the fluid can pass. Solid particles that cannot pass through the filter ...
or
unravelling. As another possibility,
completeness proofs based on
cut-free
sequent calculi usually produce finite models
directly.
Most of the modal systems used in practice (including all listed
above) have FMP.
In some cases, we can use FMP to prove Kripke completeness of a logic:
every normal modal logic is complete with respect to a class of
modal algebra In algebra and logic, a modal algebra is a structure \langle A,\land,\lor,-,0,1,\Box\rangle such that
*\langle A,\land,\lor,-,0,1\rangle is a Boolean algebra,
*\Box is a unary operation on ''A'' satisfying \Box1=1 and \Box(x\land y)=\Box x\land\Box ...
s, and a ''finite'' modal algebra can be transformed
into a Kripke frame. As an example, Robert Bull proved using this method
that every normal extension of S4.3 has FMP, and is Kripke
complete.
Multimodal logics
Kripke semantics has a straightforward generalization to logics with
more than one modality. A Kripke frame for a language with
as the set of its necessity operators
consists of a non-empty set ''W'' equipped with binary relations
''R
i'' for each ''i'' ∈ ''I''. The definition of a
satisfaction relation is modified as follows:
:
if and only if
A simplified semantics, discovered by Tim Carlson, is often used for
polymodal
provability logics. A Carlson model is a structure
with a single accessibility relation ''R'', and subsets
''D
i'' ⊆ ''W'' for each modality. Satisfaction is
defined as
:
if and only if
Carlson models are easier to visualize and to work with than usual
polymodal Kripke models; there are, however, Kripke complete polymodal
logics which are Carlson incomplete.
Semantics of intuitionistic logic
Kripke semantics for
intuitionistic logic follows the same
principles as the semantics of modal logic, but it uses a different
definition of satisfaction.
An intuitionistic Kripke model is a triple
, where
is a
preorder
In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive and transitive. Preorders are more general than equivalence relations and (non-strict) partial orders, both of which are special c ...
ed Kripke frame, and
satisfies the following conditions:
* if ''p'' is a propositional variable,
, and
, then
(''persistency'' condition (cf.
monotonicity)),
*
if and only if
and
,
*
if and only if
or
,
*
if and only if for all
,
implies
,
* not
.
The negation of ''A'', ¬''A'', could be defined as an abbreviation for ''A'' → ⊥. If for all ''u'' such that ''w'' ≤ ''u'', not ''u''
⊩ ''A'', then ''w''
⊩ ''A'' → ⊥ is
vacuously true, so ''w''
⊩ ¬''A''.
Intuitionistic logic is sound and complete with respect to its Kripke
semantics, and it has the
finite model property.
Intuitionistic first-order logic
Let ''L'' be a
first-order language. A Kripke
model of ''L'' is a triple
, where
is an intuitionistic Kripke frame, ''M
w'' is a
(classical) ''L''-structure for each node ''w'' ∈ ''W'', and
the following compatibility conditions hold whenever ''u'' ≤ ''v'':
* the domain of ''M
u'' is included in the domain of ''M
v'',
* realizations of function symbols in ''M
u'' and ''M
v'' agree on elements of ''M
u'',
* for each ''n''-ary predicate ''P'' and elements ''a''
1,...,''a
n'' ∈ ''M
u'': if ''P''(''a''
1,...,''a
n'') holds in ''M
u'', then it holds in ''M
v''.
Given an evaluation ''e'' of variables by elements of ''M
w'', we
define the satisfaction relation