In
mathematics
Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, the epsilon numbers are a collection of
transfinite numbers whose defining property is that they are
fixed points of an exponential map. Consequently, they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of "weaker" operations like addition and multiplication. The original epsilon numbers were introduced by
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( , ; – January 6, 1918) was a German mathematician. He played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor established the importance of ...
in the context of
ordinal arithmetic; they are the
ordinal numbers ''ε'' that satisfy the
equation
In mathematics, an equation is a formula that expresses the equality of two expressions, by connecting them with the equals sign . The word ''equation'' and its cognates in other languages may have subtly different meanings; for example, in ...
:
in which ω is the smallest infinite ordinal.
The least such ordinal is ''ε''
0 (pronounced epsilon nought or epsilon zero), which can be viewed as the "limit" obtained by
transfinite recursion from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals:
:
where is the
supremum
In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest l ...
function, which is equivalent to
set union
In set theory, the union (denoted by ∪) of a collection of sets is the set of all elements in the collection. It is one of the fundamental operations through which sets can be combined and related to each other.
A refers to a union of ze ...
in the case of the von Neumann representation of ordinals.
Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts, resulting in
.
[Stephen G. Simpson, ''Subsystems of Second-order Arithmetic'' (2009, p.387)] The ordinal ε
0 is still
countable, as is any epsilon number whose index is countable (there exist uncountable ordinals, and uncountable epsilon numbers whose index is an uncountable ordinal).
The smallest epsilon number ε
0 appears in many
induction
Induction, Inducible or Inductive may refer to:
Biology and medicine
* Labor induction (birth/pregnancy)
* Induction chemotherapy, in medicine
* Induced stem cells, stem cells derived from somatic, reproductive, pluripotent or other cell t ...
proofs, because for many purposes,
transfinite induction
Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC.
Induction by cases
Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
is only required up to ε
0 (as in
Gentzen's consistency proof
Gentzen's consistency proof is a result of proof theory in mathematical logic, published by Gerhard Gentzen in 1936. It shows that the Peano axioms of first-order arithmetic do not contain a contradiction (i.e. are "consistent"), as long as a cer ...
and the proof of
Goodstein's theorem). Its use by
Gentzen
Gerhard Karl Erich Gentzen (24 November 1909 – 4 August 1945) was a German mathematician and logician. He made major contributions to the foundations of mathematics, proof theory, especially on natural deduction and sequent calculus. He died o ...
to prove the consistency of
Peano arithmetic
In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
, along with
Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the
well-foundedness of this ordering (it is in fact the least ordinal with this property, and as such, in proof-theoretic
ordinal analysis
In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength.
If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory has ...
, is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic).
Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the
Veblen function
In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous strictly increasing functions from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by Oswald Veblen in . If φ0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal α, φ ...
.
A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by
John Horton Conway and
Donald Knuth in the
surreal number system, consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base ω exponential map ''x'' → ω
''x''.
defined gamma numbers (see
additively indecomposable ordinal
In set theory, a branch of mathematics, an additively indecomposable ordinal ''α'' is any ordinal number that is not 0 such that for any \beta,\gamma<\alpha, we have Additively indecomposable ordi ...
) to be numbers γ>0 such that α+γ=γ whenever α<γ, and delta numbers (see
multiplicatively indecomposable ordinals) to be numbers δ>1 such that αδ=δ whenever 0<α<δ, and epsilon numbers to be numbers ''ε''>2 such that ''α''
''ε''=''ε'' whenever 1<''α''<''ε''. His gamma numbers are those of the form ω
''β'', and his delta numbers are those of the form ω
ω''β''.
Ordinal ε numbers
The standard definition of
ordinal exponentiation with base α is:
*
*
when
has an immediate predecessor
.
*
, whenever
is a
limit ordinal.
From this definition, it follows that for any fixed ordinal , the
mapping is a
normal function
In axiomatic set theory, a function ''f'' : Ord → Ord is called normal (or a normal function) if and only if it is continuous (with respect to the order topology) and strictly monotonically increasing. This is equivalent to the following two c ...
, so it has arbitrarily large
fixed points by the
fixed-point lemma for normal functions
The fixed-point lemma for normal functions is a basic result in axiomatic set theory stating that any normal function has arbitrarily large fixed points (Levy 1979: p. 117). It was first proved by Oswald Veblen in 1908.
Background and for ...
. When
, these fixed points are precisely the ordinal epsilon numbers.
*
*
when
has an immediate predecessor
.
*
, whenever
is a limit ordinal.
Because
:
:
:
a different sequence with the same supremum,
, is obtained by starting from 0 and exponentiating with base ε
0 instead:
:
Generally, the epsilon number
indexed by any ordinal that has an immediate predecessor
can be constructed similarly.
:
In particular, whether or not the index β is a limit ordinal,
is a fixed point not only of base ω exponentiation but also of base δ exponentiation for all ordinals
.
Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers, they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves. For any ordinal number
,
is the least epsilon number (fixed point of the exponential map) not already in the set
. It might appear that this is the non-constructive equivalent of the constructive definition using iterated exponentiation; but the two definitions are equally non-constructive at steps indexed by limit ordinals, which represent transfinite recursion of a higher order than taking the supremum of an exponential series.
The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove:
* Although it is quite a large number,
is still
countable, being a countable union of countable ordinals; in fact,
is countable if and only if
is countable.
* The union (or supremum) of any nonempty set of epsilon numbers is an epsilon number; so for instance
::
: is an epsilon number. Thus, the mapping
is a normal function.
* The
initial ordinal
In a written or published work, an initial capital, also referred to as a drop capital or simply an initial cap, initial, initcapital, initcap or init or a drop cap or drop, is a letter at the beginning of a word, a chapter, or a paragraph that ...
of any
uncountable cardinal
Cardinal or The Cardinal may refer to:
Animals
* Cardinal (bird) or Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds
**''Cardinalis'', genus of cardinal in the family Cardinalidae
**''Cardinalis cardinalis'', or northern cardinal, the ...
is an epsilon number.
::
Representation of ε0 by rooted trees
Any epsilon number ε has
Cantor normal form
In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
, which means that the Cantor normal form is not very useful for epsilon numbers. The ordinals less than ε
0, however, can be usefully described by their Cantor normal forms, which leads to a representation of ε
0 as the ordered set of all
finite rooted trees, as follows. Any ordinal
has Cantor normal form
where ''k'' is a natural number and
are ordinals with
, uniquely determined by
. Each of the ordinals
in turn has a similar Cantor normal form. We obtain the finite rooted tree representing α by joining the roots of the trees representing
to a new root. (This has the consequence that the number 0 is represented by a single root while the number
is represented by a tree containing a root and a single leaf.) An order on the set of finite rooted trees is defined recursively: we first order the subtrees joined to the root in decreasing order, and then use
lexicographic order on these ordered sequences of subtrees. In this way the set of all finite rooted trees becomes a
well-ordered set which is order-isomorphic to ε
0.
This representation is related to the proof of the
hydra theorem, which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a graph-theoretic game.
Veblen hierarchy
The fixed points of the "epsilon mapping"
form a normal function, whose fixed points form a normal function; this is known as the
Veblen hierarchy
In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions (continuous function (set theory), continuous strictly increasing function, strictly increasing function (mathematics), functions from ordinal number, ordinals to ordinals), i ...
(the Veblen functions with base φ
0(α) = ω
α). In the notation of the Veblen hierarchy, the epsilon mapping is φ
1, and its fixed points are enumerated by φ
2.
Continuing in this vein, one can define maps φ
α for progressively larger ordinals α (including, by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion, limit ordinals), with progressively larger least fixed points φ
α+1(0). The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure—i. e., the least ordinal α for which φ
α(0)=α, or equivalently the first fixed point of the map
—is the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal
In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal.
It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion.
It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schütte, ...
Γ
0. In a set theory where such an ordinal can be proved to exist, one has a map Γ that enumerates the fixed points Γ
0, Γ
1, Γ
2, ... of
; these are all still epsilon numbers, as they lie in the image of φ
β for every β ≤ Γ
0, including of the map φ
1 that enumerates epsilon numbers.
Surreal ε numbers
In ''
On Numbers and Games'', the classic exposition on
surreal numbers,
John Horton Conway provided a number of examples of concepts that had natural extensions from the ordinals to the surreals. One such function is the
-map ; this mapping generalises naturally to include all surreal numbers in its
domain
Domain may refer to:
Mathematics
*Domain of a function, the set of input values for which the (total) function is defined
**Domain of definition of a partial function
**Natural domain of a partial function
**Domain of holomorphy of a function
* Do ...
, which in turn provides a natural generalisation of the
Cantor normal form
In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
for surreal numbers.
It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number, whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number. Some examples of non-ordinal epsilon numbers are
:
and
:
There is a natural way to define
for every surreal number ''n'', and the map remains order-preserving. Conway goes on to define a broader class of "irreducible" surreal numbers that includes the epsilon numbers as a particularly-interesting subclass.
See also
*
Ordinal arithmetic
*
Large countable ordinal
In the mathematical discipline of set theory, there are many ways of describing specific countable ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their Cantor normal forms. Beyond that, many ordinals of releva ...
References
* J.H. Conway, ''On Numbers and Games'' (1976) Academic Press
* Section XIV.20 of
{{countable ordinals
Ordinal numbers