HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Modal logic is a kind of
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
used to represent statements about necessity and possibility. In
philosophy Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
and related fields it is used as a tool for understanding concepts such as
knowledge Knowledge is an Declarative knowledge, awareness of facts, a Knowledge by acquaintance, familiarity with individuals and situations, or a Procedural knowledge, practical skill. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is oft ...
,
obligation An obligation is a course of action which someone is required to take, be it a legal obligation or a moral obligation. Obligations are constraints; they limit freedom. People who are under obligations may choose to freely act under obligations. ...
, and causation. For instance, in epistemic modal logic, the
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
\Box P can be used to represent the statement that P is known. In
deontic modal logic Deontic logic is the field of philosophical logic that is concerned with obligation, permission, and related concepts. Alternatively, a deontic logic is a formal system that attempts to capture the essential logical features of these concepts. I ...
, that same formula can represent that P is a moral obligation. Modal logic considers the inferences that modal statements give rise to. For instance, most epistemic modal logics treat the formula \Box P \rightarrow P as a tautology, representing the principle that only true statements can count as knowledge. However, this formula is not a tautology in deontic modal logic, since what ought to be true can be false. Modal logics are
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure and formalization of an axiomatic system used for deducing, using rules of inference, theorems from axioms. In 1921, David Hilbert proposed to use formal systems as the foundation of knowledge in ma ...
s that include unary operators such as \Diamond and \Box, representing possibility and necessity respectively. For instance the modal formula \Diamond P can be read as "possibly P" while \Box P can be read as "necessarily P". In the standard relational semantics for modal logic, formulas are assigned truth values relative to a ''
possible world A possible world is a complete and consistent way the world is or could have been. Possible worlds are widely used as a formal device in logic, philosophy, and linguistics in order to provide a semantics for intensional and modal logic. Their met ...
''. A formula's truth value at one possible world can depend on the truth values of other formulas at other '' accessible''
possible worlds Possible Worlds may refer to: * Possible worlds, concept in philosophy * ''Possible Worlds'' (play), 1990 play by John Mighton ** ''Possible Worlds'' (film), 2000 film by Robert Lepage, based on the play * Possible Worlds (studio) * ''Possible ...
. In particular, \Diamond P is true at a world if P is true at ''some'' accessible possible world, while \Box P is true at a world if P is true at ''every'' accessible possible world. A variety of proof systems exist which are sound and complete with respect to the semantics one gets by restricting the accessibility relation. For instance, the deontic modal logic D is sound and complete if one requires the accessibility relation to be serial. While the intuition behind modal logic dates back to antiquity, the first modal
axiomatic system In mathematics and logic, an axiomatic system is a set of formal statements (i.e. axioms) used to logically derive other statements such as lemmas or theorems. A proof within an axiom system is a sequence of deductive steps that establishes ...
s were developed by C. I. Lewis in 1912. The now-standard relational semantics emerged in the mid twentieth century from work by
Arthur Prior Arthur Norman Prior (4 December 1914 – 6 October 1969), usually cited as A. N. Prior, was a New Zealand–born logician and philosopher. Prior (1957) founded tense logic, now also known as temporal logic, and made important contribution ...
,
Jaakko Hintikka Kaarlo Jaakko Juhani Hintikka (; ; 12 January 1929 – 12 August 2015) was a Finnish philosopher and logician. Hintikka is regarded as the founder of formal epistemic logic and of game semantics for logic. Life and career Hintikka was born in ...
, and
Saul Kripke Saul Aaron Kripke (; November 13, 1940 – September 15, 2022) was an American analytic philosophy, analytic philosopher and logician. He was Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York and emer ...
. Recent developments include alternative
topological Topology (from the Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, wit ...
semantics such as neighborhood semantics as well as applications of the relational semantics beyond its original philosophical motivation. Such applications include
game theory Game theory is the study of mathematical models of strategic interactions. It has applications in many fields of social science, and is used extensively in economics, logic, systems science and computer science. Initially, game theory addressed ...
,
moral A moral (from Latin ''morālis'') is a message that is conveyed or a lesson to be learned from a story or event. The moral may be left to the hearer, reader, or viewer to determine for themselves, or may be explicitly encapsulated in a maxim. ...
and
legal theory Jurisprudence, also known as theory of law or philosophy of law, is the examination in a general perspective of what law is and what it ought to be. It investigates issues such as the definition of law; legal validity; legal norms and values ...
,
web design Web design encompasses many different skills and disciplines in the production and maintenance of websites. The different areas of web design include web graphic design; user interface design (UI design); authoring, including standardised code a ...
, multiverse-based set theory, and
social epistemology Social epistemology refers to a broad set of approaches that can be taken in epistemology (the study of knowledge) that construes human knowledge as a collective achievement. Another way of characterizing social epistemology is as the evaluation ...
.


Syntax of modal operators

Modal logic differs from other kinds of logic in that it uses modal operators such as \Box and \Diamond. The former is conventionally read aloud as "necessarily", and can be used to represent notions such as moral or legal
obligation An obligation is a course of action which someone is required to take, be it a legal obligation or a moral obligation. Obligations are constraints; they limit freedom. People who are under obligations may choose to freely act under obligations. ...
,
knowledge Knowledge is an Declarative knowledge, awareness of facts, a Knowledge by acquaintance, familiarity with individuals and situations, or a Procedural knowledge, practical skill. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is oft ...
, historical inevitability, among others. The latter is typically read as "possibly" and can be used to represent notions including permission,
ability Abilities are powers an agent has to perform various Action (philosophy), actions. They include common abilities, like walking, and rare abilities, like performing a double backflip. Abilities are intelligent powers: they are guided by the person ...
, compatibility with
evidence Evidence for a proposition is what supports the proposition. It is usually understood as an indication that the proposition is truth, true. The exact definition and role of evidence vary across different fields. In epistemology, evidence is what J ...
. While
well-formed formula In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language. The abbreviation wf ...
s of modal logic include non-modal formulas such as P \land Q, it also contains modal ones such as \Box(P \land Q), P \land \Box Q, \Box(\Diamond P \land \Diamond Q), and so on. Thus, the
language Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
\mathcal of basic
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
can be defined recursively as follows. #If \phi is an atomic formula, then \phi is a formula of \mathcal. #If \phi is a formula of \mathcal, then \neg \phi is too. #If \phi and \psi are formulas of \mathcal, then \phi \land \psi is too. #If \phi is a formula of \mathcal, then \Diamond \phi is too. #If \phi is a formula of \mathcal, then \Box \phi is too. Modal operators can be added to other kinds of logic by introducing rules analogous to #4 and #5 above. Modal
predicate logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables ove ...
is one widely used variant which includes formulas such as \forall x \Diamond P(x) . In systems of modal logic where \Box and \Diamond are
duals ''Duals'' is a compilation album by the Irish rock band U2. It was released in April 2011 to u2.com subscribers. Track listing :* "Where the Streets Have No Name" and "Amazing Grace" are studio mix of U2's performance at the Rose Bowl, ...
, \Box \phi can be taken as an abbreviation for \neg \Diamond \neg \phi, thus eliminating the need for a separate syntactic rule to introduce it. However, separate syntactic rules are necessary in systems where the two operators are not interdefinable. Common notational variants include symbols such as /math> and \langle K \rangle in systems of modal logic used to represent knowledge and /math> and \langle B \rangle in those used to represent belief. These notations are particularly common in systems which use multiple modal operators simultaneously. For instance, a combined epistemic-deontic logic could use the formula langle D \rangle P read as "I know P is permitted". Systems of modal logic can include infinitely many modal operators distinguished by indices, i.e. \Box_1, \Box_2, \Box_3, and so on.


Semantics


Relational semantics


Basic notions

The standard semantics for modal logic is called the ''relational semantics''. In this approach, the truth of a formula is determined relative to a point which is often called a ''
possible world A possible world is a complete and consistent way the world is or could have been. Possible worlds are widely used as a formal device in logic, philosophy, and linguistics in order to provide a semantics for intensional and modal logic. Their met ...
''. For a formula that contains a modal operator, its truth value can depend on what is true at other accessible worlds. Thus, the relational semantics interprets formulas of modal logic using
models A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided int ...
defined as follows. * A ''relational model'' is a tuple \mathfrak = \langle W, R, V \rangle where: # W is a set of possible worlds # R is a binary relation on W # V is a valuation function which assigns a truth value to each pair of an atomic formula and a world, (i.e. V: W \times F \to \ where F is the set of atomic formulae) The set W is often called the ''universe''. The binary relation R is called an
accessibility relation An accessibility relation is a relation (math), relation which plays a key role in assigning truth values to sentences in the Kripke semantics, relational semantics for modal logic. In relational semantics, a modal formula's truth value at a '' ...
, and it controls which worlds can "see" each other for the sake of determining what is true. For example, w R u means that the world u is accessible from world w. That is to say, the state of affairs known as u is a live possibility for w. Finally, the function V is known as a valuation function. It determines which
atomic formula In mathematical logic, an atomic formula (also known as an atom or a prime formula) is a formula with no deeper propositional structure, that is, a formula that contains no logical connectives or equivalently a formula that has no strict subformu ...
s are true at which worlds. Then we recursively define the truth of a formula at a world w in a model \mathfrak: * \mathfrak, w \models P iff V(w, P)=1 * \mathfrak, w \models \neg P iff w \not \models P * \mathfrak, w \models (P \wedge Q) iff w \models P and w \models Q * \mathfrak, w \models \Box P iff for every element u of W, if w R u then u \models P * \mathfrak, w \models \Diamond P iff for some element u of W, it holds that w R u and u \models P According to this semantics, a formula is ''necessary'' with respect to a world w if it holds at every world that is accessible from w. It is ''possible'' if it holds at some world that is accessible from w. Possibility thereby depends upon the accessibility relation R, which allows us to express the relative nature of possibility. For example, we might say that given our laws of physics it is not possible for humans to travel faster than the speed of light, but that given other circumstances it could have been possible to do so. Using the accessibility relation we can translate this scenario as follows: At all of the worlds accessible to our own world, it is not the case that humans can travel faster than the speed of light, but at one of these accessible worlds there is ''another'' world accessible from ''those'' worlds but not accessible from our own at which humans can travel faster than the speed of light.


Frames and completeness

The choice of accessibility relation alone can sometimes be sufficient to guarantee the truth or falsity of a formula. For instance, consider a model \mathfrak whose accessibility relation is reflexive. Because the relation is reflexive, we will have that \mathfrak,w \models P \rightarrow \Diamond P for any w \in G regardless of which valuation function is used. For this reason, modal logicians sometimes talk about ''frames'', which are the portion of a relational model excluding the valuation function. * A ''relational frame'' is a pair \mathfrak = \langle G, R \rangle where G is a set of possible worlds, R is a binary relation on G. The different systems of modal logic are defined using ''frame conditions''. A frame is called: * reflexive if ''w R w'', for every ''w'' in ''G'' *
symmetric Symmetry () in everyday life refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, the term has a more precise definition and is usually used to refer to an object that is invariant under some transformations ...
if ''w R u'' implies ''u R w'', for all ''w'' and ''u'' in ''G'' * transitive if ''w R u'' and ''u R q'' together imply ''w R q'', for all ''w'', ''u'', ''q'' in ''G''. * serial if, for every ''w'' in ''G'' there is some ''u'' in ''G'' such that ''w R u''. * Euclidean if, for every ''u'', ''t'', and ''w'', ''w R u'' and ''w R t'' implies ''u R t'' (by symmetry, it also implies ''t R u'', as well as ''t R t'' and ''u R u'') The logics that stem from these frame conditions are: *''K'' := no conditions *''D'' := serial *''T'' := reflexive *''B'' := reflexive and symmetric *''S4'' := reflexive and transitive *'' S5'' := reflexive and Euclidean The Euclidean property along with reflexivity yields symmetry and transitivity. (The Euclidean property can be obtained, as well, from symmetry and transitivity.) Hence if the accessibility relation ''R'' is reflexive and Euclidean, ''R'' is provably
symmetric Symmetry () in everyday life refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, the term has a more precise definition and is usually used to refer to an object that is invariant under some transformations ...
and transitive as well. Hence for models of S5, ''R'' is an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
, because ''R'' is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. We can prove that these frames produce the same set of valid sentences as do the frames where all worlds can see all other worlds of ''W'' (''i.e.'', where ''R'' is a "total" relation). This gives the corresponding ''modal graph'' which is total complete (''i.e.'', no more edges (relations) can be added). For example, in any modal logic based on frame conditions: : w \models \Diamond P if and only if for some element ''u'' of ''G'', it holds that u \models P and ''w R u''. If we consider frames based on the total relation we can just say that : w \models \Diamond P if and only if for some element ''u'' of ''G'', it holds that u \models P. We can drop the accessibility clause from the latter stipulation because in such total frames it is trivially true of all ''w'' and ''u'' that ''w R u''. But this does not have to be the case in all S5 frames, which can still consist of multiple parts that are fully connected among themselves but still disconnected from each other. All of these logical systems can also be defined axiomatically, as is shown in the next section. For example, in S5, the axioms P \implies \Box\Diamond P, \Box P \implies \Box\Box P and \Box P \implies P (corresponding to ''symmetry'', ''transitivity'' and ''reflexivity'', respectively) hold, whereas at least one of these axioms does not hold in each of the other, weaker logics.


Topological semantics

Modal logic has also been interpreted using topological structures. For instance, the ''Interior Semantics'' interprets formulas of modal logic as follows. A ''topological model'' is a tuple \Chi = \langle X, \tau, V \rangle where \langle X, \tau \rangle is a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
and V is a valuation function which maps each atomic formula to some subset of X. The basic interior semantics interprets formulas of modal logic as follows: * \Chi, x \models P iff x \in V(P) * \Chi, x \models \neg \phi iff \Chi, x \not\models \phi * \Chi, x \models \phi \land \chi iff \Chi, x \models \phi and \Chi, x \models \chi * \Chi, x \models \Box \phi iff for some U \in \tau we have both that x \in U and also that \Chi, y \models \phi for all y \in U Topological approaches subsume relational ones, allowing non-normal modal logics. The extra structure they provide also allows a transparent way of modeling certain concepts such as the evidence or justification one has for one's beliefs. Topological semantics is widely used in recent work in formal epistemology and has antecedents in earlier work such as David Lewis and
Angelika Kratzer Angelika Kratzer is a professor emerita of linguistics in the Department of Linguistics at the University of Massachusetts Amherst. Biography She was born in Germany, and received her PhD from the University of Konstanz in 1979, with a dissert ...
's logics for counterfactuals.


Axiomatic systems

The first formalizations of modal logic were axiomatic. Numerous variations with very different properties have been proposed since C. I. Lewis began working in the area in 1912. Hughes and Cresswell (1996), for example, describe 42 normal and 25 non-normal modal logics. Zeman (1973) describes some systems Hughes and Cresswell omit. Modern treatments of modal logic begin by augmenting the
propositional calculus The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
with two unary operations, one denoting "necessity" and the other "possibility". The notation of C. I. Lewis, much employed since, denotes "necessarily ''p''" by a prefixed "box" (□''p'') whose scope is established by parentheses. Likewise, a prefixed "diamond" (◇''p'') denotes "possibly ''p''". Similar to the quantifiers in
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
, "necessarily ''p''" (□''p'') does not assume the range of quantification (the set of accessible possible worlds in
Kripke semantics Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
) to be non-empty, whereas "possibly ''p''" (◇''p'') often implicitly assumes \Diamond\top (viz. the set of accessible possible worlds is non-empty). Regardless of notation, each of these operators is definable in terms of the other in classical modal logic: * □''p'' (necessarily ''p'') is equivalent to ("not possible that not-''p''") * ◇''p'' (possibly ''p'') is equivalent to ("not necessarily not-''p''") Hence □ and ◇ form a dual pair of operators. In many modal logics, the necessity and possibility operators satisfy the following analogues of
de Morgan's laws In propositional calculus, propositional logic and Boolean algebra, De Morgan's laws, also known as De Morgan's theorem, are a pair of transformation rules that are both Validity (logic), valid rule of inference, rules of inference. They are nam ...
from
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
: :"It is not necessary that ''X''" is
logically equivalent In logic and mathematics, statements p and q are said to be logically equivalent if they have the same truth value in every model. The logical equivalence of p and q is sometimes expressed as p \equiv q, p :: q, \textsfpq, or p \iff q, depending on ...
to "It is possible that not ''X''". :"It is not possible that ''X''" is logically equivalent to "It is necessary that not ''X''". Precisely what axioms and rules must be added to the
propositional calculus The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
to create a usable system of modal logic is a matter of philosophical opinion, often driven by the theorems one wishes to prove; or, in computer science, it is a matter of what sort of computational or deductive system one wishes to model. Many modal logics, known collectively as
normal modal logic In logic, a normal modal logic is a set ''L'' of modal formulas such that ''L'' contains: * All propositional tautology (logic), tautologies; * All instances of the Kripke_semantics, Kripke schema: \Box(A\to B)\to(\Box A\to\Box B) and it is closed ...
s, include the following rule and axiom: * N, Necessitation Rule: If ''p'' is a
theorem In mathematics and formal logic, a theorem is a statement (logic), statement that has been Mathematical proof, proven, or can be proven. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to esta ...
/ tautology (of any system/model invoking N), then □''p'' is likewise a theorem (i.e. (\models p) \implies (\models \Box p) ). * K, Distribution Axiom: The weakest
normal modal logic In logic, a normal modal logic is a set ''L'' of modal formulas such that ''L'' contains: * All propositional tautology (logic), tautologies; * All instances of the Kripke_semantics, Kripke schema: \Box(A\to B)\to(\Box A\to\Box B) and it is closed ...
, named "''K''" in honor of
Saul Kripke Saul Aaron Kripke (; November 13, 1940 – September 15, 2022) was an American analytic philosophy, analytic philosopher and logician. He was Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York and emer ...
, is simply the
propositional calculus The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
augmented by □, the rule N, and the axiom K. ''K'' is weak in that it fails to determine whether a proposition can be necessary but only contingently necessary. That is, it is not a theorem of ''K'' that if □''p'' is true then □□''p'' is true, i.e., that necessary truths are "necessarily necessary". If such perplexities are deemed forced and artificial, this defect of ''K'' is not a great one. In any case, different answers to such questions yield different systems of modal logic. Adding axioms to ''K'' gives rise to other well-known modal systems. One cannot prove in ''K'' that if "''p'' is necessary" then ''p'' is true. The axiom T remedies this defect: *T, Reflexivity Axiom: (If ''p'' is necessary, then ''p'' is the case.) T holds in most but not all modal logics. Zeman (1973) describes a few exceptions, such as ''S10''. Other well-known elementary axioms are: *4: \Box p \to \Box \Box p *B: p \to \Box \Diamond p *D: \Box p \to \Diamond p *5: \Diamond p \to \Box \Diamond p These yield the systems (axioms in bold, systems in italics): *''K'' := K + N *''T'' := ''K'' + T *''S4'' := ''T'' + 4 *''S5'' := ''T'' + 5 *''D'' := ''K'' + D. ''K'' through ''S5'' form a nested hierarchy of systems, making up the core of
normal modal logic In logic, a normal modal logic is a set ''L'' of modal formulas such that ''L'' contains: * All propositional tautology (logic), tautologies; * All instances of the Kripke_semantics, Kripke schema: \Box(A\to B)\to(\Box A\to\Box B) and it is closed ...
. But specific rules or sets of rules may be appropriate for specific systems. For example, in deontic logic, \Box p \to \Diamond p (If it ought to be that ''p'', then it is permitted that ''p'') seems appropriate, but we should probably not include that p \to \Box \Diamond p. In fact, to do so is to commit the
naturalistic fallacy In metaethics, the naturalistic fallacy is the claim that it is possible to define good in terms of merely described entities, properties, or processes such as ''pleasant'', ''desirable'', or '' fitness''. The term was introduced by British phil ...
(i.e. to state that what is natural is also good, by saying that if ''p'' is the case, ''p'' ought to be permitted). The commonly employed system ''S5'' simply makes all modal truths necessary. For example, if ''p'' is possible, then it is "necessary" that ''p'' is possible. Also, if ''p'' is necessary, then it is necessary that ''p'' is necessary. Other systems of modal logic have been formulated, in part because ''S5'' does not describe every kind of modality of interest.


Structural proof theory

Sequent calculi In mathematical logic, sequent calculus is a style of formal logical argumentation in which every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhard Gentzen) instead of an unconditional tautology. Each conditional tautology ...
and systems of natural deduction have been developed for several modal logics, but it has proven hard to combine generality with other features expected of good structural proof theories, such as purity (the proof theory does not introduce extra-logical notions such as labels) and analyticity (the logical rules support a clean notion of
analytic proof {{Short description, Fundamental theory of logical analysis In mathematics, an analytic proof is a proof of a theorem in analysis that only makes use of methods from analysis, and that does not predominantly make use of algebraic or geometrical meth ...
). More complex calculi have been applied to modal logic to achieve generality.


Decision methods

Analytic tableaux In proof theory, the semantic tableau (; plural: tableaux), also called an analytic tableau, truth tree, or simply tree, is a decision procedure for sentential and related logics, and a proof procedure for formulae of first-order logic. An anal ...
provide the most popular decision method for modal logics.


Modal logics in philosophy


Alethic logic

Modalities of necessity and possibility are called ''alethic'' modalities. They are also sometimes called ''special'' modalities, from the
Latin Latin ( or ) is a classical language belonging to the Italic languages, Italic branch of the Indo-European languages. Latin was originally spoken by the Latins (Italic tribe), Latins in Latium (now known as Lazio), the lower Tiber area aroun ...
''species''. Modal logic was first developed to deal with these concepts, and only afterward was extended to others. For this reason, or perhaps for their familiarity and simplicity, necessity and possibility are often casually treated as ''the'' subject matter of modal logic. Moreover, it is easier to make sense of relativizing necessity, e.g. to legal, physical,
nomological In philosophy, nomology refers to a "science of laws" based on the theory that it is possible to elaborate descriptions dedicated not to particular aspects of reality but inspired by a scientific vision of universal validity expressed by scientific ...
,
epistemic Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowledg ...
, and so on, than it is to make sense of relativizing other notions. In
classical modal logic In modal logic, a classical modal logic L is any modal logic containing (as axiom or theorem) the duality of the modal operators :\Diamond A \leftrightarrow \lnot\Box\lnot A that is also closed under the rule :\frac. Alternatively, one can g ...
, a proposition is said to be *possible if it is ''not necessarily false'' (regardless of whether it is actually true or actually false); *necessary if it is ''not possibly false'' (i.e. true and necessarily true); *contingent if it is ''not necessarily false'' and ''not necessarily true'' (i.e. possible but not necessarily true); *impossible if it is ''not possibly true'' (i.e. false and necessarily false). In classical modal logic, therefore, the notion of either possibility or necessity may be taken to be basic, where these other notions are defined in terms of it in the manner of De Morgan duality. Intuitionistic modal logic treats possibility and necessity as not perfectly symmetric. For example, suppose that while walking to the convenience store we pass Friedrich's house, and observe that the lights are off. On the way back, we observe that they have been turned on. * "Somebody or something turned the lights on" is ''necessary''. * "Friedrich turned the lights on", "Friedrich's roommate Max turned the lights on" and "A burglar named Adolf broke into Friedrich's house and turned the lights on" are ''contingent''. * All of the above statements are ''possible''. * It is ''impossible'' that
Socrates Socrates (; ; – 399 BC) was a Ancient Greek philosophy, Greek philosopher from Classical Athens, Athens who is credited as the founder of Western philosophy and as among the first moral philosophers of the Ethics, ethical tradition ...
(who has been dead for over two thousand years) turned the lights on. (Of course, this analogy does not apply alethic modality in a ''truly'' rigorous fashion; for it to do so, it would have to axiomatically make such statements as "human beings cannot rise from the dead", "Socrates was a human being and not an immortal vampire", and "we did not take hallucinogenic drugs which caused us to falsely believe the lights were on", ''ad infinitum''. Absolute certainty of truth or falsehood exists only in the sense of logically constructed abstract concepts such as "it is impossible to draw a triangle with four sides" and "all bachelors are unmarried".) For those having difficulty with the concept of something being possible but not true, the meaning of these terms may be made more comprehensible by thinking of multiple "possible worlds" (in the sense of
Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (or Leibnitz; – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat who is credited, alongside Sir Isaac Newton, with the creation of calculus in addition to many ...
) or "alternate universes"; something "necessary" is true in all possible worlds, something "possible" is true in at least one possible world.


Physical possibility

Something is physically, or nomically, possible if it is permitted by the
laws of physics Scientific laws or laws of science are statements, based on repeated experiments or observations, that describe or predict a range of natural phenomena. The term ''law'' has diverse usage in many cases (approximate, accurate, broad, or narrow) ...
. For example, current theory is thought to allow for there to be an
atom Atoms are the basic particles of the chemical elements. An atom consists of a atomic nucleus, nucleus of protons and generally neutrons, surrounded by an electromagnetically bound swarm of electrons. The chemical elements are distinguished fr ...
with an
atomic number The atomic number or nuclear charge number (symbol ''Z'') of a chemical element is the charge number of its atomic nucleus. For ordinary nuclei composed of protons and neutrons, this is equal to the proton number (''n''p) or the number of pro ...
of 126, even if there are no such atoms in existence. In contrast, while it is logically possible to accelerate beyond the
speed of light The speed of light in vacuum, commonly denoted , is a universal physical constant exactly equal to ). It is exact because, by international agreement, a metre is defined as the length of the path travelled by light in vacuum during a time i ...
, See also Feinberg's later paper: Phys. Rev. D 17, 1651 (1978) modern science stipulates that it is not physically possible for material particles or information. Physical possibility does not coincide with empirical possibility.


Metaphysical possibility

Philosophers Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, value, mind, and language. It is a rational and critical inquiry that reflects on ...
debate if objects have properties independent of those dictated by scientific laws. For example, it might be metaphysically necessary, as some who advocate
physicalism In philosophy, physicalism is the view that "everything is physical", that there is "nothing over and above" the physical, or that everything supervenience, supervenes on the physical. It is opposed to idealism, according to which the world arises ...
have thought, that all thinking beings have bodies and can experience the passage of
time Time is the continuous progression of existence that occurs in an apparently irreversible process, irreversible succession from the past, through the present, and into the future. It is a component quantity of various measurements used to sequ ...
.
Saul Kripke Saul Aaron Kripke (; November 13, 1940 – September 15, 2022) was an American analytic philosophy, analytic philosopher and logician. He was Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York and emer ...
has argued that every person necessarily has the parents they do have: anyone with different parents would not be the same person. Metaphysical possibility has been thought to be more restricting than bare logical possibility (i.e., fewer things are metaphysically possible than are logically possible). However, its exact relation (if any) to logical possibility or to physical possibility is a matter of dispute. Philosophers also disagree over whether metaphysical truths are necessary merely "by definition", or whether they reflect some underlying deep facts about the world, or something else entirely.


Epistemic logic

Epistemic modalities (from the Greek ''episteme'', knowledge), deal with the ''certainty'' of sentences. The □ operator is translated as "x is certain that…", and the ◇ operator is translated as "For all x knows, it may be true that…" In ordinary speech both metaphysical and epistemic modalities are often expressed in similar words; the following contrasts may help: A person, Jones, might reasonably say ''both'': (1) "No, it is ''not'' possible that
Bigfoot Bigfoot (), also commonly referred to as Sasquatch (), is a large, hairy Mythic humanoids, mythical creature said to inhabit forests in North America, particularly in the Pacific Northwest.Example definitions include: *"A large, hairy, manlike ...
exists; I am quite certain of that"; ''and'', (2) "Sure, it's ''possible'' that Bigfoots could exist". What Jones means by (1) is that, given all the available information, there is no question remaining as to whether Bigfoot exists. This is an epistemic claim. By (2) he makes the ''metaphysical'' claim that it is ''possible for'' Bigfoot to exist, ''even though he does not'': there is no physical or biological reason that large, featherless, bipedal creatures with thick hair could not exist in the forests of North America (regardless of whether or not they do). Similarly, "it is possible for the person reading this sentence to be fourteen feet tall and named Chad" is ''metaphysically'' true (such a person would not somehow be prevented from doing so on account of their height and name), but not ''alethically'' true unless you match that description, and not ''epistemically'' true if it is known that fourteen-foot-tall human beings have never existed. From the other direction, Jones might say, (3) "It is ''possible'' that
Goldbach's conjecture Goldbach's conjecture is one of the oldest and best-known list of unsolved problems in mathematics, unsolved problems in number theory and all of mathematics. It states that every even and odd numbers, even natural number greater than 2 is the ...
is true; but also ''possible'' that it is false", and ''also'' (4) "if it ''is'' true, then it is necessarily true, and not possibly false". Here Jones means that it is ''epistemically possible'' that it is true or false, for all he knows (Goldbach's conjecture has not been proven either true or false), but if there ''is'' a proof (heretofore undiscovered), then it would show that it is not ''logically'' possible for Goldbach's conjecture to be false—there could be no set of numbers that violated it. Logical possibility is a form of ''alethic'' possibility; (4) makes a claim about whether it is possible (i.e., logically speaking) that a mathematical truth to have been false, but (3) only makes a claim about whether it is possible, for all Jones knows, (i.e., speaking of certitude) that the mathematical claim is specifically either true or false, and so again Jones does not contradict himself. It is worthwhile to observe that Jones is not necessarily correct: It is possible (epistemically) that
Goldbach's conjecture Goldbach's conjecture is one of the oldest and best-known list of unsolved problems in mathematics, unsolved problems in number theory and all of mathematics. It states that every even and odd numbers, even natural number greater than 2 is the ...
is both true and unprovable. Epistemic possibilities also bear on the actual world in a way that metaphysical possibilities do not. Metaphysical possibilities bear on ways the world ''might have been,'' but epistemic possibilities bear on the way the world ''may be'' (for all we know). Suppose, for example, that I want to know whether or not to take an umbrella before I leave. If you tell me "it is ''possible that'' it is raining outside" – in the sense of epistemic possibility – then that would weigh on whether or not I take the umbrella. But if you just tell me that "it is ''possible for'' it to rain outside" – in the sense of ''metaphysical possibility'' – then I am no better off for this bit of modal enlightenment. Some features of epistemic modal logic are in debate. For example, if ''x'' knows that ''p'', does ''x'' know that it knows that ''p''? That is to say, should □''P'' → □□''P'' be an axiom in these systems? While the answer to this question is unclear, there is at least one axiom that is generally included in epistemic modal logic, because it is minimally true of all normal modal logics (see the section on axiomatic systems): * K, ''Distribution Axiom'': \Box (p \to q) \to (\Box p \to \Box q). It has been questioned whether the epistemic and alethic modalities should be considered distinct from each other. The criticism states that there is no real difference between "the truth in the world" (alethic) and "the truth in an individual's mind" (epistemic). An investigation has not found a single language in which alethic and epistemic modalities are formally distinguished, as by the means of a
grammatical mood In linguistics, grammatical mood is a grammatical feature of verbs, used for signaling modality. That is, it is the use of verbal inflections that allow speakers to express their attitude toward what they are saying (for example, a statement ...
.


Temporal logic

Temporal logic is an approach to the semantics of expressions with tense, that is, expressions with qualifications of when. Some expressions, such as '2 + 2 = 4', are true at all times, while tensed expressions such as 'John is happy' are only true sometimes. In temporal logic, tense constructions are treated in terms of modalities, where a standard method for formalizing talk of time is to use ''two'' pairs of operators, one for the past and one for the future (P will just mean 'it is presently the case that P'). For example: :F''P'' : It will sometimes be the case that ''P'' :G''P'' : It will always be the case that ''P'' :P''P'' : It was sometime the case that ''P'' :H''P'' : It has always been the case that ''P'' There are then at least three modal logics that we can develop. For example, we can stipulate that, : \Diamond P = P is the case at some time ''t'' : \Box P = P is the case at every time ''t'' Or we can trade these operators to deal only with the future (or past). For example, : \Diamond_1 P = \mathsf FP : \Box_1 P = \mathsf GP or, : \Diamond_2 P = P \text\text \mathsf FP : \Box_2 P = P \text \mathsf GP The operators F and G may seem initially foreign, but they create normal modal systems. F''P'' is the same as ¬G¬''P''. We can combine the above operators to form complex statements. For example, P''P'' → □P''P'' says (effectively), ''Everything that is past and true is necessary''. It seems reasonable to say that possibly it will rain tomorrow, and possibly it will not; on the other hand, since we cannot change the past, if it is true that it rained yesterday, it cannot be true that it may not have rained yesterday. It seems the past is "fixed", or necessary, in a way the future is not. This is sometimes referred to as accidental necessity. But if the past is "fixed", and everything that is in the future will eventually be in the past, then it seems plausible to say that future events are necessary too. Similarly, the
problem of future contingents Future contingent propositions (or simply, future contingents) are statements about states of affairs in the future that are '' contingent:'' neither necessarily true nor necessarily false. The problem of future contingents seems to have been fi ...
considers the semantics of assertions about the future: is either of the propositions 'There will be a sea battle tomorrow', or 'There will not be a sea battle tomorrow' now true? Considering this thesis led
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
to reject the
principle of bivalence In logic, the semantic principle (or law) of bivalence states that every declarative sentence expressing a proposition (of a theory under inspection) has exactly one truth value, either true or false. A logic satisfying this principle is calle ...
for assertions concerning the future. Additional binary operators are also relevant to temporal logics (see
Linear temporal logic In logic, linear temporal logic or linear-time temporal logic (LTL) is a modal logic, modal temporal logic with modalities referring to time. In LTL, one can encode formula (logic), formulae about the future of path (graph theory), paths, e.g., a c ...
). Versions of temporal logic can be used in
computer science Computer science is the study of computation, information, and automation. Computer science spans Theoretical computer science, theoretical disciplines (such as algorithms, theory of computation, and information theory) to Applied science, ...
to model computer operations and prove theorems about them. In one version, ◇''P'' means "at a future time in the computation it is possible that the computer state will be such that ''P'' is true"; □''P'' means "at all future times in the computation P will be true". In another version, ◇''P'' means "at the immediate next state of the computation, ''P'' might be true"; □''P'' means "at the immediate next state of the computation, ''P'' will be true". These differ in the choice of
Accessibility relation An accessibility relation is a relation (math), relation which plays a key role in assigning truth values to sentences in the Kripke semantics, relational semantics for modal logic. In relational semantics, a modal formula's truth value at a '' ...
. (''P'' always means "''P'' is true at the current computer state".) These two examples involve nondeterministic or not-fully-understood computations; there are many other modal logics specialized to different types of program analysis. Each one naturally leads to slightly different axioms.


Deontic logic

Likewise talk of morality, or of
obligation An obligation is a course of action which someone is required to take, be it a legal obligation or a moral obligation. Obligations are constraints; they limit freedom. People who are under obligations may choose to freely act under obligations. ...
and norms generally, seems to have a modal structure. The difference between "You must do this" and "You may do this" looks a lot like the difference between "This is necessary" and "This is possible". Such logics are called ''
deontic In moral philosophy, deontological ethics or deontology (from Greek: and ) is the normative ethical theory that the morality of an action should be based on whether that action itself is right or wrong under a series of rules and principles, ...
'', from the Greek for "duty". Deontic logics commonly lack the axiom T semantically corresponding to the reflexivity of the accessibility relation in
Kripke semantics Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
: in symbols, \Box\phi\to\phi. Interpreting □ as "it is obligatory that", T informally says that every obligation is true. For example, if it is obligatory not to kill others (i.e. killing is morally forbidden), then T implies that people actually do not kill others. The consequent is obviously false. Instead, using
Kripke semantics Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
, we say that though our own world does not realize all obligations, the worlds accessible to it do (i.e., T holds at these worlds). These worlds are called ''idealized'' worlds. ''P'' is obligatory with respect to our own world if at all idealized worlds accessible to our world, ''P'' holds. Though this was one of the first interpretations of the formal semantics, it has recently come under criticism. One other principle that is often (at least traditionally) accepted as a deontic principle is ''D'', \Box\phi\to\Diamond\phi, which corresponds to the seriality (or extendability or unboundedness) of the accessibility relation. It is an embodiment of the Kantian idea that "ought implies can". (Clearly the "can" can be interpreted in various senses, e.g. in a moral or alethic sense.)


Intuitive problems with deontic logic

When we try to formalize ethics with standard modal logic, we run into some problems. Suppose that we have a proposition ''K'': you have stolen some money, and another, ''Q'': you have stolen a small amount of money. Now suppose we want to express the thought that "if you have stolen some money, it ought to be a small amount of money". There are two likely candidates, : (1) (K \to \Box Q) : (2) \Box (K \to Q) But (1) and ''K'' together entail □''Q'', which says that it ought to be the case that you have stolen a small amount of money. This surely is not right, because you ought not to have stolen anything at all. And (2) does not work either: If the right representation of "if you have stolen some money it ought to be a small amount" is (2), then the right representation of (3) "if you have stolen some money then it ought to be a large amount" is \Box (K \to (K \land \lnot Q)). Now suppose (as seems reasonable) that you ought not to steal anything, or \Box \lnot K. But then we can deduce \Box (K \to (K \land \lnot Q)) via \Box (\lnot K) \to \Box (K \to K \land \lnot K) and \Box (K \land \lnot K \to (K \land \lnot Q)) (the
contrapositive In logic and mathematics, contraposition, or ''transposition'', refers to the inference of going from a Conditional sentence, conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as . The contrap ...
of Q \to K); so sentence (3) follows from our hypothesis (of course the same logic shows sentence (2)). But that cannot be right, and is not right when we use natural language. Telling someone they should not steal certainly does not imply that they should steal large amounts of money if they do engage in theft.


Doxastic logic

''Doxastic logic'' concerns the logic of belief (of some set of agents). The term doxastic is derived from the
ancient Greek Ancient Greek (, ; ) includes the forms of the Greek language used in ancient Greece and the classical antiquity, ancient world from around 1500 BC to 300 BC. It is often roughly divided into the following periods: Mycenaean Greek (), Greek ...
''doxa'' which means "belief". Typically, a doxastic logic uses □, often written "B", to mean "It is believed that", or when relativized to a particular agent s, "It is believed by s that".


Extensions

Modal logics may be extended to fuzzy form with calculi in the class of fuzzy Kripke models. Modal logics may also be enhanced via ''base-extension semantics'' for the classical propositional systems. In this case, the validity of a formula can be shown by an inductive definition generated by provability in a ‘base’ of atomic rules. ⁠
Intuitionistic In the philosophy of mathematics, intuitionism, or neointuitionism (opposed to preintuitionism), is an approach where mathematics is considered to be purely the result of the constructive mental activity of humans rather than the discovery of f ...
modal logics are used in different areas of application, and they have often risen from different sources. The areas include the foundations of mathematics, computer science and philosophy. In these approaches, often modalities are added to intuitionistic logic to create new intuitionistic connectives and to simulate the monadic elements of intuitionistic
first order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
.


Metaphysical questions

In the most common interpretation of modal logic, one considers " logically possible worlds". If a statement is true in all
possible worlds Possible Worlds may refer to: * Possible worlds, concept in philosophy * ''Possible Worlds'' (play), 1990 play by John Mighton ** ''Possible Worlds'' (film), 2000 film by Robert Lepage, based on the play * Possible Worlds (studio) * ''Possible ...
, then it is a necessary truth. If a statement happens to be true in our world, but is not true in all possible worlds, then it is a contingent truth. A statement that is true in some possible world (not necessarily our own) is called a possible truth. Under this "possible worlds idiom", to maintain that Bigfoot's existence is possible but not actual, one says, "There is some possible world in which Bigfoot exists; but in the actual world, Bigfoot does not exist". However, it is unclear what this claim commits us to. Are we really alleging the existence of possible worlds, every bit as real as our actual world, just not actual?
Saul Kripke Saul Aaron Kripke (; November 13, 1940 – September 15, 2022) was an American analytic philosophy, analytic philosopher and logician. He was Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York and emer ...
believes that 'possible world' is something of a misnomer – that the term 'possible world' is just a useful way of visualizing the concept of possibility. For him, the sentences "you could have rolled a 4 instead of a 6" and "there is a possible world where you rolled a 4, but you rolled a 6 in the actual world" are not significantly different statements, and neither commit us to the existence of a possible world. David Lewis, on the other hand, made himself notorious by biting the bullet, asserting that all merely possible worlds are as real as our own, and that what distinguishes our world as ''actual'' is simply that it is indeed our world – '' this'' world. That position is a major tenet of "
modal realism Modal realism is the view propounded by the philosopher David Lewis that all possible worlds are real in the same way as is the actual world: they are "of a kind with this world of ours." It states that possible worlds exist, possible worlds are ...
". Some philosophers decline to endorse any version of modal realism, considering it ontologically extravagant, and prefer to seek various ways to paraphrase away these ontological commitments. Robert Adams holds that 'possible worlds' are better thought of as 'world-stories', or consistent sets of propositions. Thus, it is possible that you rolled a 4 if such a state of affairs can be described coherently. Computer scientists will generally pick a highly specific interpretation of the modal operators specialized to the particular sort of computation being analysed. In place of "all worlds", you may have "all possible next states of the computer", or "all possible future states of the computer".


Further applications

Modal logics have begun to be used in areas of the humanities such as literature, poetry, art and history. In the
philosophy of religion Philosophy of religion is "the philosophical examination of the central themes and concepts involved in religious traditions". Philosophical discussions on such topics date from ancient times, and appear in the earliest known Text (literary theo ...
, modal logics are commonly used in arguments for the
existence of God The existence of God is a subject of debate in the philosophy of religion and theology. A wide variety of arguments for and against the existence of God (with the same or similar arguments also generally being used when talking about the exis ...
.


History

The basic ideas of modal logic date back to antiquity.
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
developed a modal syllogistic in Book I of his '' Prior Analytics'' (ch. 8–22), which
Theophrastus Theophrastus (; ; c. 371 – c. 287 BC) was an ancient Greek Philosophy, philosopher and Natural history, naturalist. A native of Eresos in Lesbos, he was Aristotle's close colleague and successor as head of the Lyceum (classical), Lyceum, the ...
attempted to improve. There are also passages in Aristotle's work, such as the famous sea-battle argument in ''
De Interpretatione ''On Interpretation'' (Greek: , ) is the second text from Aristotle's ''Organon'' and is among the earliest surviving philosophical works in the Western tradition to deal with the relationship between language and logic in a comprehensive, explic ...
'' §9, that are now seen as anticipations of the connection of modal logic with potentiality and time. In the Hellenistic period, the logicians
Diodorus Cronus Diodorus Cronus (; died c. 284 BC) was a Greek philosopher and dialectician connected to the Megarian school. He was most notable for logic innovations, including his master argument formulated in response to Aristotle's discussion of future ...
, Philo the Dialectician and the Stoic
Chrysippus Chrysippus of Soli (; , ; ) was a Ancient Greece, Greek Stoicism, Stoic Philosophy, philosopher. He was a native of Soli, Cilicia, but moved to Athens as a young man, where he became a pupil of the Stoic philosopher Cleanthes. When Cleanthes ...
each developed a modal system that accounted for the interdefinability of possibility and necessity, accepted
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
T (see
below Below may refer to: *Earth *Ground (disambiguation) *Soil *Floor * Bottom (disambiguation) *Less than *Temperatures below freezing *Hell or underworld People with the surname * Ernst von Below (1863–1955), German World War I general * Fred Belo ...
), and combined elements of modal logic and
temporal logic In logic, temporal logic is any system of rules and symbolism for representing, and reasoning about, propositions qualified in terms of time (for example, "I am ''always'' hungry", "I will ''eventually'' be hungry", or "I will be hungry ''until'' I ...
in attempts to solve the notorious
Master Argument :''See Diodorus Cronus § Master argument for the classical master argument related to the problem of future contingents.'' The master argument is George Berkeley's argument that mind-independent objects do not exist because it is impossible to ...
. The earliest formal system of modal logic was developed by
Avicenna Ibn Sina ( – 22 June 1037), commonly known in the West as Avicenna ( ), was a preeminent philosopher and physician of the Muslim world, flourishing during the Islamic Golden Age, serving in the courts of various Iranian peoples, Iranian ...
, who ultimately developed a theory of " temporally modal" syllogistic.History of logic: Arabic logic
''
Encyclopædia Britannica The is a general knowledge, general-knowledge English-language encyclopaedia. It has been published by Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. since 1768, although the company has changed ownership seven times. The 2010 version of the 15th edition, ...
''.
Modal logic as a self-aware subject owes much to the writings of the
Scholastics Scholasticism was a medieval European philosophical movement or methodology that was the predominant education in Europe from about 1100 to 1700. It is known for employing logically precise analyses and reconciling classical philosophy and C ...
, in particular
William of Ockham William of Ockham or Occam ( ; ; 9/10 April 1347) was an English Franciscan friar, scholastic philosopher, apologist, and theologian, who was born in Ockham, a small village in Surrey. He is considered to be one of the major figures of medie ...
and
John Duns Scotus John Duns Scotus ( ; , "Duns the Scot";  – 8 November 1308) was a Scottish Catholic priest and Franciscan friar, university professor, philosopher and theologian. He is considered one of the four most important Christian philosopher-t ...
, who reasoned informally in a modal manner, mainly to analyze statements about
essence Essence () has various meanings and uses for different thinkers and in different contexts. It is used in philosophy and theology as a designation for the property (philosophy), property or set of properties or attributes that make an entity the ...
and
accident An accident is an unintended, normally unwanted event that was not deliberately caused by humans. The term ''accident'' implies that the event may have been caused by Risk assessment, unrecognized or unaddressed risks. Many researchers, insurers ...
. In the 19th century, Hugh MacColl made innovative contributions to modal logic, but did not find much acknowledgment. C. I. Lewis founded modern modal logic in a series of scholarly articles beginning in 1912 with "Implication and the Algebra of Logic". Lewis was led to invent modal logic, and specifically strict implication, on the grounds that classical logic grants
paradoxes of material implication The paradoxes of material implication are a group of true formulae involving material conditionals whose translations into natural language are intuitively false when the conditional is translated as "if ... then ...". A material conditional formu ...
such as the principle that a falsehood implies any proposition. This work culminated in his 1932 book ''Symbolic Logic'' (with C. H. Langford), which introduced the five systems ''S1'' through ''S5''. After Lewis, modal logic received little attention for several decades.
Nicholas Rescher Nicholas Rescher (; ; 15 July 1928 – 5 January 2024) was a German-born American philosopher, polymath, and author, who was a professor of philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh from 1961. He was chairman of the Center for Philosophy of Sc ...
has argued that this was because
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
rejected it. However, Jan Dejnozka has argued against this view, stating that a modal system which Dejnozka calls "MDL" is described in Russell's works, although Russell did believe the concept of modality to "come from confusing propositions with
propositional function In propositional calculus, a propositional function or a predicate is a sentence expressed in a way that would assume the value of true or false, except that within the sentence there is a variable (''x'') that is not defined or specified (thus be ...
s", as he wrote in ''The Analysis of Matter''. Ruth C. Barcan (later Ruth Barcan Marcus) developed the first axiomatic systems of quantified modal logic — first and second order extensions of Lewis' ''S2'', ''S4'', and ''S5''. Arthur Norman Prior warned her to prepare well in the debates concerning quantified modal logic with
Willard Van Orman Quine Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century" ...
, because of bias against modal logic. The contemporary era in modal semantics began in 1959, when
Saul Kripke Saul Aaron Kripke (; November 13, 1940 – September 15, 2022) was an American analytic philosophy, analytic philosopher and logician. He was Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York and emer ...
(then only a 18-year-old
Harvard University Harvard University is a Private university, private Ivy League research university in Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States. Founded in 1636 and named for its first benefactor, the History of the Puritans in North America, Puritan clergyma ...
undergraduate) introduced the now-standard
Kripke semantics Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
for modal logics. These are commonly referred to as "possible worlds" semantics. Kripke and A. N. Prior had previously corresponded at some length. Kripke semantics is basically simple, but proofs are eased using semantic-tableaux or
analytic tableaux In proof theory, the semantic tableau (; plural: tableaux), also called an analytic tableau, truth tree, or simply tree, is a decision procedure for sentential and related logics, and a proof procedure for formulae of first-order logic. An anal ...
, as explained by E. W. Beth. A. N. Prior created modern
temporal logic In logic, temporal logic is any system of rules and symbolism for representing, and reasoning about, propositions qualified in terms of time (for example, "I am ''always'' hungry", "I will ''eventually'' be hungry", or "I will be hungry ''until'' I ...
, closely related to modal logic, in 1957 by adding modal operators and meaning "eventually" and "previously".
Vaughan Pratt Vaughan Pratt (born April 12, 1944) is a Professor, Professor Emeritus at Stanford University, who was an early pioneer in the field of computer science. Since 1969, Pratt has made several contributions to foundational areas such as search algorit ...
introduced dynamic logic in 1976. In 1977, Amir Pnueli proposed using temporal logic to formalise the behaviour of continually operating concurrent programs. Flavors of temporal logic include propositional dynamic logic (PDL), (propositional)
linear temporal logic In logic, linear temporal logic or linear-time temporal logic (LTL) is a modal logic, modal temporal logic with modalities referring to time. In LTL, one can encode formula (logic), formulae about the future of path (graph theory), paths, e.g., a c ...
(LTL), computation tree logic (CTL), Hennessy–Milner logic, and ''T''. The mathematical structure of modal logic, namely
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
s augmented with
unary operation In mathematics, a unary operation is an operation with only one operand, i.e. a single input. This is in contrast to ''binary operations'', which use two operands. An example is any function , where is a set; the function is a unary operation ...
s (often called modal algebras), began to emerge with J. C. C. McKinsey's 1941 proof that ''S2'' and ''S4'' are decidable, and reached full flower in the work of
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
and his student
Bjarni Jónsson Bjarni Jónsson (February 15, 1920 – September 30, 2016) was an Icelandic mathematician and logician working in universal algebra, lattice theory, model theory and set theory. He was emeritus distinguished professor of mathematics at Vanderb ...
(Jónsson and Tarski 1951–52). This work revealed that ''S4'' and ''S5'' are models of interior algebra, a proper extension of Boolean algebra originally designed to capture the properties of the interior and
closure operator In mathematics, a closure operator on a Set (mathematics), set ''S'' is a Function (mathematics), function \operatorname: \mathcal(S)\rightarrow \mathcal(S) from the power set of ''S'' to itself that satisfies the following conditions for all sets ...
s of
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
. Texts on modal logic typically do little more than mention its connections with the study of
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
s and
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
. For a thorough survey of the history of formal modal logic and of the associated mathematics, see
Robert Goldblatt __NOTOC__ Robert Ian Goldblatt (born 1949) is a mathematical logician who is emeritus Professor in the School of Mathematics and Statistics at Victoria University, Wellington, New Zealand. His doctoral advisor was Max Cresswell. His most popula ...
(2006).Robert Goldbaltt
Mathematical Modal Logic: A view of its evolution
/ref>


See also

*
Accessibility relation An accessibility relation is a relation (math), relation which plays a key role in assigning truth values to sentences in the Kripke semantics, relational semantics for modal logic. In relational semantics, a modal formula's truth value at a '' ...
*
Conceptual necessity Conceptual necessity is a property of the certainty with which a state of affairs, as presented by a certain description, occurs: it occurs by conceptual necessity if and only if it occurs just by virtue of the meaning of the description. If someone ...
*
Counterpart theory In philosophy, specifically in the area of metaphysics, counterpart theory is an alternative to standard ( Kripkean) possible-worlds semantics for interpreting quantified modal logic. Counterpart theory still presupposes possible worlds, but differ ...
*
David Kellogg Lewis David (; , "beloved one") was a king of ancient Israel and Judah and the third king of the United Monarchy, according to the Hebrew Bible and Old Testament. The Tel Dan stele, an Aramaic-inscribed stone erected by a king of Aram-Dama ...
* ''De dicto'' and ''de re'' *
Description logic Description logics (DL) are a family of formal knowledge representation languages. Many DLs are more expressive than propositional logic but less expressive than first-order logic. In contrast to the latter, the core reasoning problems for DLs are ...
*
Doxastic logic Doxastic logic is a type of logic concerned with reasoning about beliefs. The term ' derives from the Ancient Greek (''doxa'', "opinion, belief"), from which the English term ''doxa'' ("popular opinion or belief") is also borrowed. Typically, a ...
* Dynamic logic *
Enthymeme An enthymeme (, ''enthýmēma'') is an argument with a hidden premise. Enthymemes are usually developed from premises that accord with the audience's view of the world and what is taken to be common sense. However, where the general premise of a s ...
*
Free choice inference Free choice is a phenomenon in natural language where a linguistic disjunction appears to receive a logical conjunctive interpretation when it interacts with a modal operator. For example, the following English sentences can be interpreted to me ...
* Hybrid logic * Interior algebra *
Interpretability logic Interpretability logics comprise a family of modal logics that extend provability logic to describe interpretability or various related metamathematical properties and relations such as weak interpretability, Π1-conservativity, cointerpretabilit ...
*
Kripke semantics Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André ...
* Metaphysical necessity *
Modal verb A modal verb is a type of verb that contextually indicates a modality such as a ''likelihood'', ''ability'', ''permission'', ''request'', ''capacity'', ''suggestion'', ''order'', ''obligation'', ''necessity'', ''possibility'' or ''advice''. Modal v ...
* Multimodal logic *
Multi-valued logic Many-valued logic (also multi- or multiple-valued logic) is a propositional calculus in which there are more than two truth values. Traditionally, in Aristotle's logical calculus, there were only two possible values (i.e., "true" and "false") ...
* Neighborhood semantics *
Provability logic Provability logic is a modal logic, in which the box (or "necessity") operator is interpreted as 'it is provable that'. The point is to capture the notion of a proof predicate of a reasonably rich formal theory, such as Peano arithmetic. Examples ...
* Regular modal logic *
Relevance logic Relevance logic, also called relevant logic, is a kind of non-classical logic requiring the antecedent and consequent of implications to be relevantly related. They may be viewed as a family of substructural or modal logics. It is generally, b ...
*
Strict conditional In logic, a strict conditional (symbol: \Box, or ⥽) is a conditional governed by a modal operator, that is, a logical connective of modal logic. It is logically equivalent to the material conditional of classical logic, combined with the necess ...
* Two-dimensionalism


Notes


References

* This article includes material from the
Free On-line Dictionary of Computing The Free On-line Dictionary of Computing (FOLDOC) is an online, searchable, encyclopedic dictionary of computing subjects. History FOLDOC was founded in 1985 by Denis Howe and was hosted by Imperial College London. In May 2015, the site was ...
, used with permission under the
GFDL The GNU Free Documentation License (GNU FDL or GFDL) is a copyleft license for free documentation, designed by the Free Software Foundation (FSF) for the GNU Project. It is similar to the GNU General Public License, giving readers the rights ...
. * Barcan-Marcus, Ruth JSL 11 (1946) and JSL 112 (1947) and "Modalities", OUP, 1993, 1995. * Beth, Evert W., 1955.
Semantic entailment and formal derivability
, Mededlingen van de Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Afdeling Letterkunde, N.R. Vol 18, no 13, 1955, pp 309–42. Reprinted in Jaakko Intikka (ed.) The Philosophy of Mathematics, Oxford University Press, 1969 (Semantic Tableaux proof methods). * Beth, Evert W.,
Formal Methods: An Introduction to Symbolic Logic and to the Study of Effective Operations in Arithmetic and Logic
, D. Reidel, 1962 (Semantic Tableaux proof methods). * Blackburn, P.; van Benthem, J.; and Wolter, Frank; Eds. (2006)
Handbook of Modal Logic
'. North Holland. * Blackburn, Patrick; de Rijke, Maarten; and Venema, Yde (2001) ''Modal Logic''. Cambridge University Press. * Chagrov, Aleksandr; and Zakharyaschev, Michael (1997) ''Modal Logic''. Oxford University Press. * Chellas, B. F. (1980)
Modal Logic: An Introduction
'. Cambridge University Press. * Cresswell, M. J. (2001) "Modal Logic" in Goble, Lou; Ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Basil Blackwell: 136–58. * Fitting, Melvin; and Mendelsohn, R. L. (1998) ''First Order Modal Logic''. Kluwer. * James Garson (2006) ''Modal Logic for Philosophers''. Cambridge University Press. . A thorough introduction to modal logic, with coverage of various derivation systems and a distinctive approach to the use of diagrams in aiding comprehension. * Girle, Rod (2000) ''Modal Logics and Philosophy''. Acumen (UK). . Proof by refutation trees. A good introduction to the varied interpretations of modal logic. *
Goldblatt, Robert
(1992) "Logics of Time and Computation", 2nd ed., CSLI Lecture Notes No. 7. University of Chicago Press. * —— (1993) ''Mathematics of Modality'', CSLI Lecture Notes No. 43. University of Chicago Press. * —— (2006)
Mathematical Modal Logic: a View of its Evolution
, in Gabbay, D. M.; and Woods, John; Eds., ''Handbook of the History of Logic, Vol. 6''. Elsevier BV. * Goré, Rajeev (1999) "Tableau Methods for Modal and Temporal Logics" in D'Agostino, M.; Gabbay, D.; Haehnle, R.; and Posegga, J.; Eds., ''Handbook of Tableau Methods''. Kluwer: 297–396. * Hughes, G. E., and Cresswell, M. J. (1996) ''A New Introduction to Modal Logic''. Routledge. * Jónsson, B. and Tarski, A., 1951–52, "Boolean Algebra with Operators I and II", ''American Journal of Mathematics 73'': 891–939 and ''74'': 129–62. * Kracht, Marcus (1999)
Tools and Techniques in Modal Logic
', Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics No. 142. North Holland. * Lemmon, E. J. (with Scott, D.) (1977) ''An Introduction to Modal Logic'', American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series, no. 11 (Krister Segerberg, series ed.). Basil Blackwell. * Lewis, C. I. (with Langford, C. H.) (1932). ''Symbolic Logic''. Dover reprint, 1959. * Prior, A. N. (1957)
Time and Modality
'. Oxford University Press. * Snyder, D. Paul "Modal Logic and its applications", Van Nostrand Reinhold Company, 1971 (proof tree methods). * Zeman, J. J. (1973)
Modal Logic.
' Reidel. Employs
Polish notation Polish notation (PN), also known as normal Polish notation (NPN), Łukasiewicz notation, Warsaw notation, Polish prefix notation, Eastern Notation or simply prefix notation, is a mathematical notation in which Operation (mathematics), operator ...
.
"History of logic"
Britannica Online.


Further reading

* Ruth Barcan Marcus, ''Modalities'', Oxford University Press, 1993. * D. M. Gabbay, A. Kurucz, F. Wolter and M. Zakharyaschev, ''Many-Dimensional Modal Logics: Theory and Applications'', Elsevier, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, volume 148, 2003, . overs many varieties of modal logics, e.g. temporal, epistemic, dynamic, description, spatial from a unified perspective with emphasis on computer science aspects, e.g. decidability and complexity.* Andrea Borghini
''A Critical Introduction to the Metaphysics of Modality''
New York: Bloomsbury, 2016.


External links

*
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''IEP'') is a scholarly online encyclopedia with around 900 articles about philosophy, philosophers, and related topics. The IEP publishes only peer review, peer-reviewed and blind-refereed original p ...
: **
Modal Logic: A Contemporary View
– by Johan van Benthem. **
Rudolf Carnap's Modal Logic
– by MJ Cresswell. *
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''SEP'') is a freely available online philosophy resource published and maintained by Stanford University, encompassing both an online encyclopedia of philosophy and peer-reviewed original publication ...
: **
Modal Logic
– by James Garson. **
Modern Origins of Modal Logic
– by Roberta Ballarin. **
Provability Logic
– by
Rineke Verbrugge Laurina Christina (Rineke) Verbrugge (born 12 March 1965 in Amsterdam) is a Dutch logician and computer scientist known for her work on interpretability logic and provability logic. She completed her PhD at the University of Amsterdam in 1993 ...
. * Edward N. Zalta, 1995,
Basic Concepts in Modal Logic.
* John McCarthy, 1996,
Modal Logic.

Molle
a Java prover for experimenting with modal logics * Suber, Peter, 2002,



List of many modal logics with sources, by John Halleck.
Advances in Modal Logic.
Biannual international conference and book series in modal logic.
S4prover
A tableaux prover for S4 logic *
Some Remarks on Logic and Topology
– by Richard Moot; exposits a
topological Topology (from the Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, wit ...
semantics Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
for the modal logic S4.
LoTREC
The most generic prover for modal logics from IRIT/Toulouse University {{Authority control Logic Philosophical logic Mathematical logic Semantics