HOME





Implication (information Science)
In formal concept analysis (FCA) ''implications'' relate sets of properties (or, synonymously, of attributes). An implication  ''A''→''B''  ''holds'' in a given domain when every object having all attributes in ''A'' also has all attributes in ''B''. Such implications characterize the concept hierarchy in an intuitive manner. Moreover, they are "well-behaved" with respect to algorithms. The knowledge acquisition method called ''attribute exploration'' uses implications.Ganter, Bernhard and Obiedkov, Sergei (2016) ''Conceptual Exploration''. Springer, Definitions An implication  ''A''→''B''  is simply a pair of sets ''A''⊆''M'', ''B''⊆''M'', where ''M'' is the set of attributes under consideration. ''A'' is the ''premise'' and ''B'' is the ''conclusion'' of the implication  ''A''→''B'' . A set C respects the implication  ''A''→''B''  when ¬(''C''⊆''A'') or ''C''⊆''B''. A ''formal context'' is a triple ''(G,M,I)'', where '' ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


picture info

Formal Concept Analysis
In information science, formal concept analysis (FCA) is a principled way of deriving a ''concept hierarchy'' or formal ontology from a collection of objects and their properties. Each concept in the hierarchy represents the objects sharing some set of properties; and each sub-concept in the hierarchy represents a subset of the objects (as well as a superset of the properties) in the concepts above it. The term was introduced by Rudolf Wille in 1981, and builds on the mathematical theory of lattices and ordered sets that was developed by Garrett Birkhoff and others in the 1930s. Formal concept analysis finds practical application in fields including data mining, text mining, machine learning, knowledge management, semantic web, software development, chemistry and biology. Overview and history The original motivation of formal concept analysis was the search for real-world meaning of mathematical order theory. One such possibility of very general nature is that data tables ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


picture info

Closure Operator
In mathematics, a closure operator on a Set (mathematics), set ''S'' is a Function (mathematics), function \operatorname: \mathcal(S)\rightarrow \mathcal(S) from the power set of ''S'' to itself that satisfies the following conditions for all sets X,Y\subseteq S : Closure operators are determined by their closed sets, i.e., by the sets of the form cl(''X''), since the closure cl(''X'') of a set ''X'' is the smallest closed set containing ''X''. Such families of "closed sets" are sometimes called closure systems or "Moore families". A set together with a closure operator on it is sometimes called a closure space. Closure operators are also called "hull operators", which prevents confusion with the "closure operators" studied in point-set topology, topology. History E. H. Moore studied closure operators in his 1910 ''Introduction to a form of general analysis'', whereas the concept of the closure of a subset originated in the work of Frigyes Riesz in connection with topological sp ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


Armstrong Axioms
Armstrong's axioms are a set of axioms (or, more precisely, inference rules) used to infer all the functional dependencies on a relational database. They were developed by William W. Armstrong in his 1974 paper. The axioms are sound in generating only functional dependencies in the closure of a set of functional dependencies (denoted as F^) when applied to that set (denoted as F). They are also complete in that repeated application of these rules will generate all functional dependencies in the closure F^+. More formally, let \langle R(U), F \rangle denote a relational scheme over the set of attributes U with a set of functional dependencies F. We say that a functional dependency f is logically implied by F, and denote it with F \models f if and only if for every instance r of R that satisfies the functional dependencies in F, r also satisfies f. We denote by F^ the set of all functional dependencies that are logically implied by F. Furthermore, with respect to a set of inferen ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]