In
philosophical logic
Understood in a narrow sense, philosophical logic is the area of logic that studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems, often in the form of extended logical systems like modal logic. Some theorists conceive philosophic ...
, a slingshot argument is one of a group of
argument
An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persu ...
s claiming to show that all
true
True most commonly refers to truth, the state of being in congruence with fact or reality.
True may also refer to:
Places
* True, West Virginia, an unincorporated community in the United States
* True, Wisconsin, a town in the United States
* ...
sentences stand for the same thing.
This type of argument was dubbed the "
slingshot
A slingshot or catapult is a small hand-powered projectile weapon. The classic form consists of a Y-shaped frame, with two tubes or strips made from either a natural rubber or synthetic elastic material. These are attached to the upper two ends ...
" by
philosopher
Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
s
Jon Barwise
Kenneth Jon Barwise (; June 29, 1942 – March 5, 2000) was an American mathematician, philosopher and logician who proposed some fundamental revisions to the way that logic is understood and used.
Education and career
He was born in Indepen ...
and
John Perry (1981) due to its disarming simplicity. It is usually said that versions of the slingshot argument have been given by
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
,
Alonzo Church
Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
,
W. V. Quine
Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth centur ...
, and
Donald Davidson. However, it has been disputed by
Lorenz Krüger (1995) that there is much unity in this tradition. Moreover, Krüger rejects Davidson's claim that the argument can refute the
correspondence theory of truth
In metaphysics and philosophy of language, the correspondence theory of truth states that the truth or falsity of a statement is determined only by how it relates to the world and whether it accurately describes (i.e., corresponds with) that worl ...
.
Stephen Neale (1995) claims, controversially, that the most compelling version was suggested by
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
(1944).
These arguments are sometimes modified to support the alternative, and evidently stronger, conclusion that there is only one ''
fact
A fact is a truth, true data, datum about one or more aspects of a circumstance. Standard reference works are often used to Fact-checking, check facts. Science, Scientific facts are verified by repeatable careful observation or measurement by ...
'', or one true ''
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
'', ''
state of affairs'', ''
truth condition'', ''
truthmaker'', and so on.
The argument
One version of the argument (Perry 1996) proceeds as follows.
Assumptions:
# Substitution. If two terms designate the same thing, then substituting one for another in a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence.
# Redistribution. Rearranging the parts of a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence, provided the truth conditions of the sentence do not change.
# Every sentence is equivalent to a sentence of the form ''F''(''a''). In other words, every sentence has the same designation as some sentence that attributes a property to something. (For example, "All men are mortal" is equivalent to "The number 1 has the property of being such that all men are mortal".)
# For any two objects there is a relation that holds uniquely between them. (For example, if the objects in question are denoted by "''a''" and "''b''", the relation in question might be ''R''(''x'', ''y''), which is stipulated to hold just in case ''x'' = ''a'' and ''y'' = ''b''.)
Let ''S'' and ''T'' be arbitrary true sentences, designating ''Des''(''S'') and ''Des''(''T''), respectively. (No assumptions are made about what kinds of things ''Des''(''S'') and ''Des''(''T'') are.) It is now shown by a series of designation-preserving transformations that ''Des''(''S'') = ''Des''(''T''). Here, "
" can be read as "the ''x'' such that".
Note that (1)-(9) is not a derivation of ''T'' from ''S''. Rather, it is a series of (allegedly) designation-preserving transformation steps.
Responses to the argument
As Gödel (1944) observed, the slingshot argument does not go through if
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
's famous account of
definite description
In formal semantics and philosophy of language, a definite description is a denoting phrase in the form of "the X" where X is a noun-phrase or a singular common noun. The definite description is ''proper'' if X applies to a unique individual or ...
s is assumed. Russell claimed that the proper logical interpretation of a sentence of the form "The ''F'' is ''G''" is:
: Exactly one thing is ''F'', and that thing is also ''G''.
Or, in the language of
first-order logic
First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
:
:
When the sentences above containing
-expressions are expanded out to their proper form, the steps involving substitution are seen to be illegitimate. Consider, for example, the move from (3) to (4). On Russell's account, (3) and (4) are shorthand for:
{,
, -
, 3'.
,
, -
, 4'.
,
Clearly the substitution principle and assumption 4 do not license the move from (3') to (4'). Thus, one way to look at the slingshot is as simply another argument in favor of Russell's theory of definite descriptions.
If one is not willing to accept Russell's theory, then it seems wise to challenge either ''substitution'' or ''redistribution'', which seem to be the other weakest points in the argument. Perry (1996), for example, rejects both of these principles, proposing to replace them with certain weaker, qualified versions that do not allow the slingshot argument to go through.
See also
*
Abstraction
Abstraction is a process where general rules and concepts are derived from the use and classifying of specific examples, literal (reality, real or Abstract and concrete, concrete) signifiers, first principles, or other methods.
"An abstraction" ...
*
Logic of information The logic of information, or the logical theory of information, considers the information content of logical sign (semiotics), signs and expressions along the lines initially developed by Charles Sanders Peirce. In this line of work, the concept of ...
*
Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography
This Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography consolidates numerous references to the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, including letters, manuscripts, publications, and . For an extensive chronological list of Peirce's works (titled in English), se ...
References
*
Barwise, K. J. &
Perry, John (1981), "Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations", ''Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Language'', VI.
*
Gödel, Kurt (1944), "Russell's mathematical logic", in
Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), ''The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell'', Evanston and Chicago: Northwestern University Press, pp. 125–53.
* Krüger, Lorenz (1995), "Has the correspondence theory of truth been refuted?", ''European Journal of Philosophy'', vol. 3, 157–173, repr. in Lorenz Krüger, ''Why Does History Matter to Philosophy and the Sciences?'', ed. by Thomas Sturm, Wolfgang Carl, and Lorraine Daston. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2005, pp. 201–217.
* Licata, Gaetano (2011), ''Truth and Facts: Rejection of the Slingshot Argument in Defence of the Correspondence Theory of Truth'', Rome, Aracne.
* Neale, Stephen (1995), "The philosophical significance of Gödel's Slingshot", ''Mind'', vol. 104, no. 416, pp. 761–825.
*
Peirce, C. S. (1906), "Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism", ''The Monist'', 16, 492–546 (1906). Reprinted, ''Collected Papers'', CP 4.530–572
Eprint
* Perry, John (1996), "Evading the slingshot", in
Andy Clark et al. (eds.), ''Philosophy and Cognitive Science''
PDF
External links
Stephen Neale's ''Facing Facts'' reviewed by John Macfarlane
Philosophy of language
Philosophical arguments
Philosophical logic