HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In set theory, a regular cardinal is a
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. Th ...
that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite well-ordered cardinals that are not regular are called singular cardinals. Finite cardinal numbers are typically not called regular or singular. In the presence of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
, any cardinal number can be well-ordered, and then the following are equivalent for a cardinal \kappa: # \kappa is a regular cardinal. # If \kappa = \sum_ \lambda_i and \lambda_i < \kappa for all i, then , I, \ge \kappa. # If S = \bigcup_ S_i, and if , I, < \kappa and , S_i, < \kappa for all i, then , S, < \kappa. # The
category Category, plural categories, may refer to: Philosophy and general uses *Categorization, categories in cognitive science, information science and generally *Category of being * ''Categories'' (Aristotle) *Category (Kant) *Categories (Peirce) *C ...
\operatorname_ of sets of cardinality less than \kappa and all functions between them is closed under
colimit In category theory, a branch of mathematics, the abstract notion of a limit captures the essential properties of universal constructions such as products, pullbacks and inverse limits. The dual notion of a colimit generalizes constructions suc ...
s of cardinality less than \kappa. # \kappa is a regular ordinal (see below) Crudely speaking, this means that a regular cardinal is one that cannot be broken down into a small number of smaller parts. The situation is slightly more complicated in contexts where the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
might fail, as in that case not all cardinals are necessarily the cardinalities of well-ordered sets. In that case, the above equivalence holds for well-orderable cardinals only. An infinite ordinal \alpha is a regular ordinal if it is a limit ordinal that is not the limit of a set of smaller ordinals that as a set has
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y suc ...
less than \alpha. A regular ordinal is always an initial ordinal, though some initial ordinals are not regular, e.g., \omega_\omega (see the example below).


Examples

The ordinals less than \omega are finite. A finite sequence of finite ordinals always has a finite maximum, so \omega cannot be the limit of any sequence of type less than \omega whose elements are ordinals less than \omega, and is therefore a regular ordinal. \aleph_0 (
aleph-null In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets that can be well-ordered. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named a ...
) is a regular cardinal because its initial ordinal, \omega, is regular. It can also be seen directly to be regular, as the cardinal sum of a finite number of finite cardinal numbers is itself finite. \omega+1 is the next ordinal number greater than \omega. It is singular, since it is not a limit ordinal. \omega+\omega is the next limit ordinal after \omega. It can be written as the limit of the sequence \omega, \omega+1, \omega+2, \omega+3, and so on. This sequence has order type \omega, so \omega+\omega is the limit of a sequence of type less than \omega+\omega whose elements are ordinals less than \omega+\omega; therefore it is singular. \aleph_1 is the next cardinal number greater than \aleph_0, so the cardinals less than \aleph_1 are
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers ...
(finite or denumerable). Assuming the axiom of choice, the union of a countable set of countable sets is itself countable. So \aleph_1 cannot be written as the sum of a countable set of countable cardinal numbers, and is regular. \aleph_\omega is the next cardinal number after the sequence \aleph_0, \aleph_1, \aleph_2, \aleph_3, and so on. Its initial ordinal \omega_\omega is the limit of the sequence \omega, \omega_1, \omega_2, \omega_3, and so on, which has order type \omega, so \omega_\omega is singular, and so is \aleph_\omega. Assuming the axiom of choice, \aleph_\omega is the first infinite cardinal that is singular (the first infinite ''ordinal'' that is singular is \omega+1, and the first infinite ''limit ordinal'' that is singular is \omega+\omega). Proving the existence of singular cardinals requires the
axiom of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
, and in fact the inability to prove the existence of \aleph_\omega in
Zermelo set theory Zermelo set theory (sometimes denoted by Z-), as set out in a seminal paper in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo, is the ancestor of modern Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) and its extensions, such as von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). It be ...
is what led Fraenkel to postulate this axiom. Uncountable (weak)
limit cardinal In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number ''λ'' is a weak limit cardinal if ''λ'' is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" ''λ'' from another cardinal by repeated succes ...
s that are also regular are known as (weakly)
inaccessible cardinals In set theory, an uncountable cardinal is inaccessible if it cannot be obtained from smaller cardinals by the usual operations of cardinal arithmetic. More precisely, a cardinal is strongly inaccessible if it is uncountable, it is not a sum of ...
. They cannot be proved to exist within ZFC, though their existence is not known to be inconsistent with ZFC. Their existence is sometimes taken as an additional axiom. Inaccessible cardinals are necessarily fixed points of the aleph function, though not all fixed points are regular. For instance, the first fixed point is the limit of the \omega-sequence \aleph_0, \aleph_, \aleph_, ... and is therefore singular.


Properties

If the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
holds, then every successor cardinal is regular. Thus the regularity or singularity of most aleph numbers can be checked depending on whether the cardinal is a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal. Some cardinalities cannot be proven to be equal to any particular aleph, for instance the
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \mathfrak c (lowercase fraktur "c") or , \mathb ...
, whose value in ZFC may be any uncountable cardinal of uncountable cofinality (see
Easton's theorem In set theory, Easton's theorem is a result on the possible cardinal numbers of powersets. (extending a result of Robert M. Solovay) showed via forcing that the only constraints on permissible values for 2''κ'' when ''κ'' is a regular cardinal ...
). The
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
postulates that the cardinality of the continuum is equal to \aleph_1, which is regular assuming choice. Without the axiom of choice, there would be cardinal numbers that were not well-orderable. Moreover, the cardinal sum of an arbitrary collection could not be defined. Therefore, only the
aleph number In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets that can be well-ordered. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named a ...
s can meaningfully be called regular or singular cardinals. Furthermore, a successor aleph need not be regular. For instance, the union of a countable set of countable sets need not be countable. It is consistent with ZF that \omega_1 be the limit of a countable sequence of countable ordinals as well as the set of real numbers be a countable union of countable sets. Furthermore, it is consistent with ZF that every aleph bigger than \aleph_0 is singular (a result proved by
Moti Gitik Moti Gitik () is a mathematician, working in set theory, who is professor at the Tel-Aviv University. He was an invited speaker at the 2002 International Congresses of Mathematicians, and became a fellow of the American Mathematical Society in ...
). If \kappa is a limit ordinal, \kappa is regular iff the set of \alpha<\kappa that are critical points of \Sigma_1- elementary embeddings j with j(\alpha)=\kappa is
club Club may refer to: Arts, entertainment, and media * ''Club'' (magazine) * Club, a ''Yie Ar Kung-Fu'' character * Clubs (suit), a suit of playing cards * Club music * "Club", by Kelsea Ballerini from the album ''kelsea'' Brands and enterprises ...
in \kappa.T. Arai, "Bounds on provability in set theories" (2012, p.2). Accessed 4 August 2022.


See also

* Inaccessible cardinal


References

* , ''Elements of Set Theory'', * , ''Set Theory, An Introduction to Independence Proofs'', {{Set theory Cardinal numbers Ordinal numbers