Number Of Elements
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the cardinality of a
finite set In mathematics, particularly set theory, a finite set is a set that has a finite number of elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example, is a finite set with five elements. Th ...
is the number of its elements, and is therefore a measure of size of the set. Since the discovery by
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
, in the late 19th century, of different sizes of
infinite set In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
s, the term ''cardinality'' was coined for generalizing to
infinite sets In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set tha ...
the concept of the number of elements. More precisely, two sets have the same cardinality if there exists a
one-to-one correspondence In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equivale ...
between them. In the case of finite sets, the common operation of ''counting'' consists of establishing a one-to-one correspondence between a given set and the set of the first
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, for some natural number . In this case, is the cardinality of the set. A set is ''infinite'' if the counting operation never finishes, that is, if its cardinality is not a natural number. The basic example of an infinite set is the set of all natural numbers. The great discovery of Cantor is that infinite sets of apparently different size may have the same cardinality, and, nevertheless, there are infinitely many different cardinalities. For example, the
even number In mathematics, parity is the property of an integer of whether it is even or odd. An integer is even if it is divisible by 2, and odd if it is not.. For example, −4, 0, and 82 are even numbers, while −3, 5, 23, and 69 are odd numbers. The ...
s, the
prime number A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a Product (mathematics), product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime ...
s and the
polynomial In mathematics, a polynomial is a Expression (mathematics), mathematical expression consisting of indeterminate (variable), indeterminates (also called variable (mathematics), variables) and coefficients, that involves only the operations of addit ...
s whose coefficients are
rational number In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example, The set of all ...
have the same cardinality as the natural numbers. The set of the
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s has a greater cardinality than the natural numbers, and has the same cardinality as the interval and as every
Euclidean space Euclidean space is the fundamental space of geometry, intended to represent physical space. Originally, in Euclid's ''Elements'', it was the three-dimensional space of Euclidean geometry, but in modern mathematics there are ''Euclidean spaces ...
of any dimension. For every set, its
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
(the set of all its subsets) has a greater cardinality. Cardinalities are represented with
cardinal number In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
s, which are specific sets of a given cardinality, which have been chosen once for all. Some infinite cardinalities have been given a specific name, such as for the cardinality of the natural numbers and , the
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
, for the cardinality of the real numbers.


Etymology

In English, the term ''cardinality'' originates from the post-classical Latin ''cardinalis'', meaning "principal" or "chief", which derives from ''cardo'', a noun meaning "hinge". In Latin, ''cardo'' referred to something central or pivotal, both literally and metaphorically. This concept of centrality passed into
medieval Latin Medieval Latin was the form of Literary Latin used in Roman Catholic Church, Roman Catholic Western Europe during the Middle Ages. It was also the administrative language in the former Western Roman Empire, Roman Provinces of Mauretania, Numidi ...
and then into English, where ''cardinal'' came to describe things considered to be, in some sense, fundamental, such as ''
cardinal virtues The cardinal virtues are four virtues of mind and character in classical philosophy. They are prudence, Justice (virtue), justice, Courage, fortitude, and Temperance (virtue), temperance. They form a Virtue ethics, virtue theory of ethics. The t ...
'', '' cardinal sins'', ''
cardinal directions The four cardinal directions or cardinal points are the four main compass directions: north (N), south (S), east (E), and west (W). The corresponding azimuths ( clockwise horizontal angle from north) are 0°, 90°, 180°, and 270°. The four ...
'', and (in the grammatical sense) ''
cardinal numbers In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the case ...
.'' The last of which referred to numbers used for counting (e.g., one, two, three), as opposed to ''
ordinal numbers In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
'', which express order (e.g., first, second, third), and ''nominal numbers'' used for labeling without meaning (e.g., jersey numbers and
serial numbers A serial number (SN) is a unique identifier used to ''uniquely'' identify an item, and is usually assigned incrementally or sequentially. Despite being called serial "numbers", they do not need to be strictly numerical and may contain letter ...
). In mathematics, the notion of cardinality was first introduced by
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
in the late 19th century, wherein he used the used the term ''Mächtigkeit'', which may be translated as "magnitude" or "power", though Cantor credited the term to a work by
Jakob Steiner Jakob Steiner (18 March 1796 – 1 April 1863) was a Swiss mathematician who worked primarily in geometry. Life Steiner was born in the village of Utzenstorf, Canton of Bern. At 18, he became a pupil of Heinrich Pestalozzi and afterwards st ...
on
projective geometry In mathematics, projective geometry is the study of geometric properties that are invariant with respect to projective transformations. This means that, compared to elementary Euclidean geometry, projective geometry has a different setting (''p ...
. The terms ''cardinality'' and ''cardinal number'' were eventually adopted from the grammatical sense, and later translations would use these terms.


History


Prehistory

A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago. Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells. The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerian
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.


Ancient history

From the 6th century BCE, the writings of
Greek philosophers Ancient Greek philosophy arose in the 6th century BC. Philosophy was used to make sense of the world using reason. It dealt with a wide variety of subjects, including astronomy, epistemology, mathematics, political philosophy, ethics, metaphysics ...
, such as
Anaximander Anaximander ( ; ''Anaximandros''; ) was a Pre-Socratic philosophy, pre-Socratic Ancient Greek philosophy, Greek philosopher who lived in Miletus,"Anaximander" in ''Chambers's Encyclopædia''. London: George Newnes Ltd, George Newnes, 1961, Vol. ...
, show hints of comparing infinite sets or shapes. While the Greeks considered notions of infinity, they viewed it as paradoxical and imperfect (cf. ''
Zeno's paradoxes Zeno's paradoxes are a series of philosophical arguments presented by the ancient Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea (c. 490–430 BC), primarily known through the works of Plato, Aristotle, and later commentators like Simplicius of Cilicia. Zeno de ...
''), often associating good and evil with finite and infinite.
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
distinguished between the notions of
actual infinity In the philosophy of mathematics, the abstraction of actual infinity, also called completed infinity, involves infinite entities as given, actual and completed objects. The concept of actual infinity was introduced into mathematics near the en ...
and potential infinity, arguing that Greek mathematicians understood the difference, and that they "do not need the ctualinfinite and do not use it." The greek notion of number (''αριθμός'', ''arithmos'') was used exclusively for a definite number of definite objects (i.e. finite numbers). This would be codified in Euclid's ''Elements'', where the fifth common notion states "The whole is greater than the part", often called the ''Euclidean principle''. This principle would be the dominating philosophy in mathematics until the 19th century. Around the 4th century BCE, Jaina mathematics would be the first to discuss different sizes of infinity. They defined three major classes of number: enumerable (finite numbers), unenumerable (''asamkhyata'', roughly,
countably infinite In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
), and infinite (''ananta''). Then they had five classes of infinite numbers: infinite in one direction, infinite in both directions, infinite in area, infinite everywhere, and infinite perpetually. One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded in Aristotle's ''Mechanics'' (), known as Aristotle's wheel paradox. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as two
concentric circles In geometry, two or more objects are said to be ''concentric'' when they share the same center. Any pair of (possibly unalike) objects with well-defined centers can be concentric, including circles, spheres, regular polygons, regular polyhe ...
. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: the
circumference In geometry, the circumference () is the perimeter of a circle or ellipse. The circumference is the arc length of the circle, as if it were opened up and straightened out to a line segment. More generally, the perimeter is the curve length arou ...
of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length. Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.


Pre-Cantorian set theory

Galileo Galilei Galileo di Vincenzo Bonaiuti de' Galilei (15 February 1564 – 8 January 1642), commonly referred to as Galileo Galilei ( , , ) or mononymously as Galileo, was an Italian astronomer, physicist and engineer, sometimes described as a poly ...
presented what was later coined
Galileo's paradox Galileo's paradox is a demonstration of one of the surprising properties of infinite sets. In his final scientific work, '' Two New Sciences'', Galileo Galilei made apparently contradictory statements about the positive integers. First, a square is ...
in his book ''
Two New Sciences The ''Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences'' ( ) published in 1638 was Galileo Galilei's final book and a scientific testament covering much of his work in physics over the preceding thirty years. It was writ ...
'' (1638), where he attempts to show that infinite quantities cannot be called greater or less than one another. He presents the paradox roughly as follows: a
square number In mathematics, a square number or perfect square is an integer that is the square (algebra), square of an integer; in other words, it is the multiplication, product of some integer with itself. For example, 9 is a square number, since it equals ...
is one which is the product of another number with itself, such as 4 and 9, which are the squares of 2 and 3, respectively. Then the
square root In mathematics, a square root of a number is a number such that y^2 = x; in other words, a number whose ''square'' (the result of multiplying the number by itself, or y \cdot y) is . For example, 4 and −4 are square roots of 16 because 4 ...
of a square number is that multiplicand. He then notes that there are as many square numbers as there are square roots, since every square has its own root and every root its own square, while no square has more than one root and no root more than one square. But there are as many square roots as there are numbers, since every number is the square root of some square. He, denied that this was fundamentally contradictory, however, he concluded that this meant we could not compare the sizes of infinite sets, missing the opportunity to discover cardinality.
Bernard Bolzano Bernard Bolzano (, ; ; ; born Bernardus Placidus Johann Nepomuk Bolzano; 5 October 1781 – 18 December 1848) was a Bohemian mathematician, logician, philosopher, theologian and Catholic priest of Italian extraction, also known for his liberal ...
's ''
Paradoxes of the Infinite ''Paradoxes of the Infinite'' (German title: ''Paradoxien des Unendlichen'') is a mathematical work by Bernard Bolzano on the theory of sets. It was published by a friend and student, František Přihonský, in 1851, three years after Bolzano's d ...
'' (''Paradoxien des Unendlichen'', 1851) is often considered the first systematic attempt to introduce the concept of sets into
mathematical analysis Analysis is the branch of mathematics dealing with continuous functions, limit (mathematics), limits, and related theories, such as Derivative, differentiation, Integral, integration, measure (mathematics), measure, infinite sequences, series ( ...
. In this work, Bolzano defended the notion of
actual infinity In the philosophy of mathematics, the abstraction of actual infinity, also called completed infinity, involves infinite entities as given, actual and completed objects. The concept of actual infinity was introduced into mathematics near the en ...
, examined various properties of infinite collections, including an early formulation of what would later be recognized as one-to-one correspondence between infinite sets, and proposed to base mathematics on a notion similar to sets. He discussed examples such as the pairing between the intervals ,5/math> and ,12/math> by the relation 5y = 12x. Bolzano also revisited and extended Galileo's paradox. However, he too resisted saying that these sets were, in that sense, the same size. Thus, while ''Paradoxes of the Infinite'' anticipated several ideas central to later set theory, the work had little influence on contemporary mathematics, in part due to its
posthumous publication Posthumous publication refers to publishing of creative work after the creator's death. This can be because the creator died during the publishing process or before the work was completed. It can also be because the creator chose to delay publica ...
and limited circulation. Other, more minor contributions include
David Hume David Hume (; born David Home; – 25 August 1776) was a Scottish philosopher, historian, economist, and essayist who was best known for his highly influential system of empiricism, philosophical scepticism and metaphysical naturalism. Beg ...
in ''
A Treatise of Human Nature '' A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects'' (1739–40) is a book by Scottish philosopher David Hume, considered by many to be Hume's most important work and one of the ...
'' (1739), who said ''"When two numbers are so combined, as that the one has always a unit answering to every unit of the other, we pronounce them equal",'' now called ''
Hume's principle Hume's principle or HP says that, given two collections of objects \mathcal F and \mathcal G with properties F and G respectively, the number of objects with property F is equal to the number of objects with property G if and only if there is a ...
'', which was used extensively by
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
later during the rise of set theory.
Jakob Steiner Jakob Steiner (18 March 1796 – 1 April 1863) was a Swiss mathematician who worked primarily in geometry. Life Steiner was born in the village of Utzenstorf, Canton of Bern. At 18, he became a pupil of Heinrich Pestalozzi and afterwards st ...
, whom
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
credits the original term, ''Mächtigkeit'', for cardinality (1867).
Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet Johann Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet (; ; 13 February 1805 – 5 May 1859) was a German mathematician. In number theory, he proved special cases of Fermat's last theorem and created analytic number theory. In analysis, he advanced the theory o ...
is commonly credited for being the first to explicitly formulate the
pigeonhole principle In mathematics, the pigeonhole principle states that if items are put into containers, with , then at least one container must contain more than one item. For example, of three gloves, at least two must be right-handed or at least two must be l ...
in 1834, though it was used at least two centuries earlier by
Jean Leurechon Jean Leurechon (c. 1591 – 17 January 1670) was a French Jesuit priest, astronomer, and mathematician, known for inventing the pigeonhole principle and naming the thermometer. Life Leurechon was born in Bar-le-Duc where his father, also named ...
in 1624.


Early set theory


Georg Cantor

The concept of cardinality, as a formal measure of the size of a set, emerged nearly fully formed in the work of Georg Cantor during the 1870s and 1880s, in the context of
mathematical analysis Analysis is the branch of mathematics dealing with continuous functions, limit (mathematics), limits, and related theories, such as Derivative, differentiation, Integral, integration, measure (mathematics), measure, infinite sequences, series ( ...
. In a series of papers beginning with ''
On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers Cantor's first set theory article contains Georg Cantor's first theorems of transfinite set theory, which studies infinite sets and their properties. One of these theorems is his "revolutionary discovery" that the set of all real numbers is uncou ...
'' (1874), Cantor introduced the idea of comparing the sizes of infinite sets, through the notion of one-to-one correspondence. He showed that the set of
real numbers In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measurement, measure a continuous variable, continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a time, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbi ...
was, in this sense, strictly larger than the set of natural numbers using a nested intervals argument. This result was later refined into the more widely known
diagonal argument Diagonal argument can refer to: * Diagonal argument (proof technique), proof techniques used in mathematics. A diagonal argument, in mathematics, is a technique employed in the proofs of the following theorems: *Cantor's diagonal argument (the ea ...
of 1891, published in ''Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,'' where he also proved the more general result (now called
Cantor's Theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
) that the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of any set is strictly larger than the set itself. Cantor introduced the notion
cardinal numbers In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the case ...
in terms of
ordinal numbers In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
. He viewed cardinal numbers as an abstraction of sets, introduced the notations, where, for a given set M, the
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
of that set was written \overline, and the cardinal number was M, a double abstraction. He also introduced the Aleph sequence for infinite cardinal numbers. These notations appeared in correspondence and were formalized in his later writings, particularly the series ''Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre'' (18951897). In these works, Cantor developed an arithmetic of cardinal numbers, defining addition, multiplication, and exponentiation of cardinal numbers based on set-theoretic constructions. This led to the formulation of the
Continuum Hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
(CH), the proposition that no set has cardinality strictly between \aleph_0 and the
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
, that is , \R, = \aleph_1. Cantor was unable to resolve CH and left it as an
open problem In science and mathematics, an open problem or an open question is a known problem which can be accurately stated, and which is assumed to have an objective and verifiable solution, but which has not yet been solved (i.e., no solution for it is kno ...
.


Other contributors

Parallel to Cantor’s development,
Richard Dedekind Julius Wilhelm Richard Dedekind (; ; 6 October 1831 – 12 February 1916) was a German mathematician who made important contributions to number theory, abstract algebra (particularly ring theory), and the axiomatic foundations of arithmetic. H ...
independently formulated a definition of infinite set as one that can be placed in bijection with a proper subset of itself, which was shown to be equivalent with Cantor’s definition of cardinality (given the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
). Dedekind’s '' Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?'' (1888) emphasized structural properties over extensional definitions, and supported the bijective formulation of size and number. Dedekind was in correspondence with Cantor during the development of set theory; he supplied Cantor with a proof of the countability of the
algebraic numbers In mathematics, an algebraic number is a number that is a root of a non-zero polynomial in one variable with integer (or, equivalently, rational) coefficients. For example, the golden ratio (1 + \sqrt)/2 is an algebraic number, because it is a ...
, and gave feedback and modifications on Cantor's proofs before publishing. After Cantor's 1883 proof that all finite-dimensional spaces (\R^n) have the same cardinality, in 1890,
Giuseppe Peano Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much Mathematical notati ...
introduced the
Peano curve In geometry, the Peano curve is the first example of a space-filling curve to be discovered, by Giuseppe Peano in 1890. Peano's curve is a surjective, continuous function from the unit interval onto the unit square, however it is not injective. ...
, which was a more visual proof that the
unit interval In mathematics, the unit interval is the closed interval , that is, the set of all real numbers that are greater than or equal to 0 and less than or equal to 1. It is often denoted ' (capital letter ). In addition to its role in real analysi ...
,1/math> has the same cardinality as the
unit square In mathematics, a unit square is a square whose sides have length . Often, ''the'' unit square refers specifically to the square in the Cartesian plane with corners at the four points ), , , and . Cartesian coordinates In a Cartesian coordinat ...
on \R^2. This created a new area of mathematical analysis studying what is now called space-filling curves. German logician
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
attempted to ground the concepts of number and arithmetic in logic using Cantor's theory of cardinality and
Hume's principle Hume's principle or HP says that, given two collections of objects \mathcal F and \mathcal G with properties F and G respectively, the number of objects with property F is equal to the number of objects with property G if and only if there is a ...
in ''
Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik ''The Foundations of Arithmetic'' () is a book by Gottlob Frege, published in 1884, which investigates the Philosophy, philosophical foundations of arithmetic. Frege refutes other Idealism, idealist and Materialism, materialist theories of number ...
'' (1884) and the subsequent ''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'' (1893, 1903). Frege defined cardinal numbers as
equivalence classes In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
of sets under equinumerosity. However, Frege's approach to set theory was later shown to be flawed. His approach was eventually reformalized by
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
and Alfred Whitehead in ''
Principia Mathematica The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by the mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1 ...
'' (19101913, vol. II) using a theory of types. Though Russell initially had difficulties understanding Cantor's and Frege’s intuitions of cardinality. This definition of cardinal numbers is now referred to as the ''Frege-Russell'' definition.


Axiomatic set theory

In 1908,
Ernst Zermelo Ernst Friedrich Ferdinand Zermelo (; ; 27 July 187121 May 1953) was a German logician and mathematician, whose work has major implications for the foundations of mathematics. He is known for his role in developing Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, Z ...
proposed the first
axiomatization In mathematics and logic, an axiomatic system is a set of formal statements (i.e. axioms) used to logically derive other statements such as lemmas or theorems. A proof within an axiom system is a sequence of deductive steps that establishes ...
of set theory, now called
Zermelo set theory Zermelo set theory (sometimes denoted by Z-), as set out in a seminal paper in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo, is the ancestor of modern Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) and its extensions, such as von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). It be ...
, primarily to support his earlier (1904) proof of the
Well-ordering theorem In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set ''X'' is ''well-ordered'' by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of ''X'' has a least element under the order ...
, which showed that all cardinal numbers could be represented as Alephs, though the proof required a controversial principle now known as the
Axiom of Choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC). Zermelo's system would later be extended by
Abraham Fraenkel Abraham Fraenkel (; 17 February, 1891 – 15 October, 1965) was a German-born Israeli mathematician. He was an early Zionist and the first Dean of Mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. He is known for his contributions to axiomatic ...
and
Thoralf Skolem Thoralf Albert Skolem (; 23 May 1887 – 23 March 1963) was a Norwegian mathematician who worked in mathematical logic and set theory. Life Although Skolem's father was a primary school teacher, most of his extended family were farmers. Skole ...
in the 1920s to create the standard foundation of set theory, called
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZFC, "C" for the Axiom of Choice). ZFC provided a rigorous, albeit non- categorical, foundation through which infinite cardinals could be systematically studied while avoiding the
paradoxes of naive set theory A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true or apparently true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictor ...
. In 1940,
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
showed that CH cannot be ''disproved'' from ZF set theory (ZFC without Choice), even if the axiom of choice is adopted, i.e. from ZFC. Gödel's proof shows that both CH and AC hold in the
constructible universe In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by L, is a particular Class (set theory), class of Set (mathematics), sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. L is the un ...
, an
inner model In set theory, a branch of mathematical logic, an inner model for a theory ''T'' is a substructure of a model ''M'' of a set theory that is both a model for ''T'' and contains all the ordinals of ''M''. Definition Let ''L'' = ⟨∈� ...
of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are (relatively)
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent. In 1963,
Paul Cohen Paul Joseph Cohen (April 2, 1934 – March 23, 2007) was an American mathematician, best known for his proofs that the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice are independent from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, for which he was awarded a F ...
showed that CH cannot be ''proven'' from the ZFC axioms, which showed that CH was
independent Independent or Independents may refer to: Arts, entertainment, and media Artist groups * Independents (artist group), a group of modernist painters based in Pennsylvania, United States * Independentes (English: Independents), a Portuguese artist ...
from ZFC. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of forcing, which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZFC in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the
Fields Medal The Fields Medal is a prize awarded to two, three, or four mathematicians under 40 years of age at the International Congress of Mathematicians, International Congress of the International Mathematical Union (IMU), a meeting that takes place e ...
in 1966 for his proof.


Comparing sets


Introduction

The basic notions of sets and functions are used to develop the concept of cardinality, and technical terms therein are used throughout this article. A
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
can be understood as any collection of objects, usually represented with
curly braces A bracket is either of two tall fore- or back-facing punctuation marks commonly used to isolate a segment of text or data from its surroundings. They come in four main pairs of shapes, as given in the box to the right, which also gives their n ...
. For example, S = \ specifies a set, called S, which contains the numbers 1, 2, and 3. The symbol \in represents set membership, for example 1 \in S says "1 is a member of the set S" which is true by the definition of S above. A
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-orie ...
is an association that maps elements of one set to the elements of another, often represented with an arrow diagram. For example, the adjacent image depicts a function which maps the set of
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
to the set of
even numbers In mathematics, parity is the property of an integer of whether it is even or odd. An integer is even if it is divisible by 2, and odd if it is not.. For example, −4, 0, and 82 are even numbers, while −3, 5, 23, and 69 are odd numbers. The ...
by multiplying by 2. If a function does not map two elements to the same place, it is called
injective In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function ) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements of its codomain; that is, implies (equivalently by contraposition, impl ...
. If a function covers every element in the output space, it is called
surjective In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function ) is a function such that, for every element of the function's codomain, there exists one element in the function's domain such that . In other words, for a f ...
. If a function is both injective and surjective, it is called
bijective In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
. (For further clarification, see ''Bijection, injection and surjection''.)


Equinumerosity

The intuitive property of two sets having the "same size" is that their objects can be paired one-to-one. For example, in the image above, a set of apples is paired with a set of oranges, proving the sets are the same size without referring to these sets' "number of elements" at all. A one-to-one pairing between two sets defines a bijective function between them by mapping each object to its pair. Similarly, a bijection between two sets defines a pairing of their elements by pairing each object with the one it maps to. Therefore, these notions of "pairing" and "bijection" are intuitively equivalent. In fact, it is often the case that functions are defined literally as this set of pairings (see '). Thus, the following definition is given: Two sets A and B are said to have the ''same cardinality'' if their elements can be paired one-to-one. That is, if there exists a function f:A \mapsto B which is bijective. This is written as A \sim B, A \approx B, A \equiv B, and eventually , A, = , B, , once , A, has been defined. Alternatively, these sets, A and B, may be said to be ''similar'', ''equinumerous'', or ''equipotent''. For example, the set E = \ of non-negative
even number In mathematics, parity is the property of an integer of whether it is even or odd. An integer is even if it is divisible by 2, and odd if it is not.. For example, −4, 0, and 82 are even numbers, while −3, 5, 23, and 69 are odd numbers. The ...
s has the same cardinality as the set \N = \ of
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
, since the function f(n) = 2n is a bijection from to (see picture above). For finite sets and , if ''some'' bijection exists from to , then ''each'' injective or surjective function from to is a bijection. This property is no longer true for infinite and . For example, the function from to , defined by g(n) = 4n is injective, but not surjective since 2, for instance, is not mapped to, and from to , defined by h(n) = 2 \operatorname(n/2) (see: ''
floor function In mathematics, the floor function is the function that takes as input a real number , and gives as output the greatest integer less than or equal to , denoted or . Similarly, the ceiling function maps to the least integer greater than or eq ...
'') is surjective, but not injective, since 0 and 1 for instance both map to 0. Neither nor can challenge , E, = , \N, , which was established by the existence of .


Equivalence

A fundamental result necessary in developing a theory of cardinality is relating it to an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
. A binary
relation Relation or relations may refer to: General uses * International relations, the study of interconnection of politics, economics, and law on a global level * Interpersonal relationship, association or acquaintance between two or more people * ...
is an equivalence relation if it satisfies the three basic properties of equality: reflexivity,
symmetry Symmetry () in everyday life refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, the term has a more precise definition and is usually used to refer to an object that is Invariant (mathematics), invariant und ...
, and transitivity. * Reflexivity: For any set A, A \sim A. ** Given any set A, there is a bijection from A to itself by the
identity function Graph of the identity function on the real numbers In mathematics, an identity function, also called an identity relation, identity map or identity transformation, is a function that always returns the value that was used as its argument, unc ...
, therefore equinumerosity is reflexive. * Symmetry: If A \sim B then B \sim A. ** Given any sets A and B, such that there is a bijection f from A to B, then there is an
inverse function In mathematics, the inverse function of a function (also called the inverse of ) is a function that undoes the operation of . The inverse of exists if and only if is bijective, and if it exists, is denoted by f^ . For a function f\colon ...
f^ from B to A, which is also bijective, therefore equinumerosity is symmetric. * Transitivity: If A \sim B and B \sim C then A \sim B. ** Given any sets A, B, and C such that there is a bijection f from A to B, and g from B to C, then their
composition Composition or Compositions may refer to: Arts and literature *Composition (dance), practice and teaching of choreography * Composition (language), in literature and rhetoric, producing a work in spoken tradition and written discourse, to include ...
g \circ f is a bijection from A to C, and so cardinality is transitive. Since equinumerosity satisfies these three properties, it forms an equivalence relation. This means that cardinality, in some sense, partitions sets into
equivalence classes In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
, and one may assign a representative to denote this class. This motivates the notion of a
cardinal number In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
. Somewhat more formally, a relation must be a certain set of
ordered pairs In mathematics, an ordered pair, denoted (''a'', ''b''), is a pair of objects in which their order is significant. The ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a''), unless ''a'' = ''b''. In contrast, the '' unord ...
. Since there is no
set of all sets In set theory, a universal set is a set which contains all objects, including itself. In set theory as usually formulated, it can be proven in multiple ways that a universal set does not exist. However, some non-standard variants of set theory inc ...
in standard set theory (see: '), equinumerosity is not a relation in the usual sense, but a
predicate Predicate or predication may refer to: * Predicate (grammar), in linguistics * Predication (philosophy) * several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic: **Predicate (mathematical logic) **Propositional function **Finitary relation, o ...
or a relation over classes.


Inequality

A set A is not larger than a set B if it can be mapped into B without overlap. That is, the cardinality of A is less than or equal to the cardinality of B if there is an
injective function In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function ) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements of its codomain; that is, implies (equivalently by contraposition, impl ...
from A to B. This is written A \preceq B, A \lesssim B and eventually , A, \leq , B, . If A \preceq B, but there is no injection from B to A, then A is said to be ''strictly'' smaller than B, written without the underline as A \prec B or , A, < , B, . For example, if A has four elements and B has five, then the following are true A \preceq A, A \preceq B, and A \prec B. The basic properties of an inequality are reflexivity (for any a, a \leq a), transitivity (if a \leq b and b \leq c, then a \leq c) and
antisymmetry In linguistics, antisymmetry, is a theory of syntax described in Richard S. Kayne's 1994 book ''The Antisymmetry of Syntax''. Building upon X-bar theory, it proposes a universal, fundamental word order for phrases (Branching (linguistics), branchin ...
(if a \leq b and b \leq a, then a = b) (See ''Inequality § Formal definitions''). Cardinal inequality (\preceq) as defined above is reflexive since the
identity function Graph of the identity function on the real numbers In mathematics, an identity function, also called an identity relation, identity map or identity transformation, is a function that always returns the value that was used as its argument, unc ...
is injective, and is transitive by function composition. Antisymmetry is established by the
Schröder–Bernstein theorem In set theory, the Schröder–Bernstein theorem states that, if there exist injective functions and between the sets and , then there exists a bijective function . In terms of the cardinality of the two sets, this classically implies that if ...
. The proof roughly goes as follows. Given sets A and B, where f:A \mapsto B is the function that proves A \preceq B and g: B \mapsto A proves B \preceq A, then consider the sequence of points given by applying f then g over and over. Then we can define a bijection h: A \mapsto B as follows: If a sequence forms a cycle, begins with an element a \in A not mapped to by g, or extends infinitley in both directions, define h(x) = f(x) for each x \in A in those sequences. The last case, if a sequence begins with an element b \in B, not mapped to by f, define h(x) = g^(x) for each x \in A in that sequence. Then h is a bijection. The above shows that cardinal inequality is a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable ...
. A
total order In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( re ...
has the additional property that, for any a and b, either a \leq b or b \leq a. This can be established by the
well-ordering theorem In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set ''X'' is ''well-ordered'' by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of ''X'' has a least element under the order ...
. Every well-ordered set is
isomorphic In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping or morphism between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between the ...
to a unique
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
, called the
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
of the set. Then, by comparing their order types, one can show that A \preceq B or B \preceq A. This result is equivalent to the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
.


Countable sets

A set is called ''
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
'' if it is
finite Finite may refer to: * Finite set, a set whose cardinality (number of elements) is some natural number * Finite verb, a verb form that has a subject, usually being inflected or marked for person and/or tense or aspect * "Finite", a song by Sara Gr ...
or has a bijection with the set of
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s (\N), in which case it is called ''countably infinite''. The term '' denumerable'' is also sometimes used for countably infinite sets. For example, the set of all even natural numbers is countable, and therefore has the same cardinality as the whole set of natural numbers, even though it is a
proper subset In mathematics, a set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset ...
. Similarly, the set of
square numbers In mathematics, a square number or perfect square is an integer that is the square of an integer; in other words, it is the product of some integer with itself. For example, 9 is a square number, since it equals and can be written as . The us ...
is countable, which was considered paradoxical for hundreds of years before modern set theory (see: '). However, several other examples have historically been considered surprising or initially unintuitive since the rise of set theory. The
rational numbers In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction (mathematics), fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for examp ...
(\Q) are those which can be expressed as the
quotient In arithmetic, a quotient (from 'how many times', pronounced ) is a quantity produced by the division of two numbers. The quotient has widespread use throughout mathematics. It has two definitions: either the integer part of a division (in th ...
or
fraction A fraction (from , "broken") represents a part of a whole or, more generally, any number of equal parts. When spoken in everyday English, a fraction describes how many parts of a certain size there are, for example, one-half, eight-fifths, thre ...
of two
integer An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s. The rational numbers can be shown to be countable by considering the set of fractions as the set of all
ordered pairs In mathematics, an ordered pair, denoted (''a'', ''b''), is a pair of objects in which their order is significant. The ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a''), unless ''a'' = ''b''. In contrast, the '' unord ...
of integers, denoted \Z\times\Z, which can be visualized as the set of all integer points on a grid. Then, an intuitive function can be described by drawing a line in a repeating pattern, or spiral, which eventually goes through each point in the grid. For example, going through each diagonal on the grid for positive fractions, or through a lattice spiral for all integer pairs. These technically over cover the rationals, since, for example, the rational number \frac gets mapped to by all the fractions \frac,\, \frac, \, \frac, \, \dots , as the grid method treats these all as distinct ordered pairs. So this function shows , \Q, \leq , \N, not , \Q, = , \N, . This can be corrected by "skipping over" these numbers in the grid, or by designing a function which does this naturally, for example using the Calkin–Wilf tree. A number is called algebraic if it is a solution of some
polynomial In mathematics, a polynomial is a Expression (mathematics), mathematical expression consisting of indeterminate (variable), indeterminates (also called variable (mathematics), variables) and coefficients, that involves only the operations of addit ...
equation (with integer
coefficient In mathematics, a coefficient is a Factor (arithmetic), multiplicative factor involved in some Summand, term of a polynomial, a series (mathematics), series, or any other type of expression (mathematics), expression. It may be a Dimensionless qu ...
s). For example, the
square root of two The square root of 2 (approximately 1.4142) is the positive real number that, when multiplied by itself or squared, equals the number 2. It may be written as \sqrt or 2^. It is an algebraic number, and therefore not a transcendental number. T ...
\sqrt2 is a solution to x^2 - 2 = 0, and the rational number p/q is the solution to qx - p = 0. Conversely, a number which cannot be the root of any polynomial is called transcendental. Two examples include
Euler's number The number is a mathematical constant approximately equal to 2.71828 that is the base of the natural logarithm and exponential function. It is sometimes called Euler's number, after the Swiss mathematician Leonhard Euler, though this can ...
(') and pi (). In general, proving a number is transcendental is considered to be very difficult, and only a few classes of transcendental numbers are known. However, it can be shown that the set of algebraic numbers is countable (for example, see '). Since the set of algebraic numbers is countable while the real numbers are uncountable (shown in the following section), the transcendental numbers must form the vast majority of real numbers, even though they are individually much harder to identify. That is to say,
almost all In mathematics, the term "almost all" means "all but a negligible quantity". More precisely, if X is a set (mathematics), set, "almost all elements of X" means "all elements of X but those in a negligible set, negligible subset of X". The meaning o ...
real numbers are transcendental.


Uncountable sets

A set is called ''
uncountable In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger tha ...
'' if it is not countable. That is, it is infinite and strictly larger than the set of natural numbers. The usual first example of this is the set of
real numbers In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measurement, measure a continuous variable, continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a time, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbi ...
(\R), which can be understood as the set of all numbers on the
number line A number line is a graphical representation of a straight line that serves as spatial representation of numbers, usually graduated like a ruler with a particular origin point representing the number zero and evenly spaced marks in either dire ...
. One method of proving that the reals are uncountable is called
Cantor's diagonal argument Cantor's diagonal argument (among various similar namesthe diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof) is a mathematical proof that there are infin ...
, credited to Cantor for his 1891 proof, English translation: though his differs from the more common presentation. It begins by assuming, by contradiction, that there is some one-to-one mapping between the natural numbers and the set of real numbers between 0 and 1 (the interval ,1/math>). Then, take the
decimal expansion A decimal representation of a non-negative real number is its expression as a sequence of symbols consisting of decimal digits traditionally written with a single separator: r = b_k b_\cdots b_0.a_1a_2\cdots Here is the decimal separator ...
s of each real number, which looks like 0.d_1d_2d_3... Considering these real numbers in a column, create a new number such that the first digit of the new number is different from that of the first number in the column, the second digit is different from the second number in the column and so on. We also need to make sure that the number we create has a unique decimal representation, that is, it cannot end in repeating nines or repeating zeros. For example, if the digit isn't a 7, make the digit of the new number a 7, and if it was a seven, make it a 3. Then, this new number will be different from each of the numbers in the list by at least one digit, and therefore must not be in the list. This shows that the real numbers cannot be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the naturals, and thus must be strictly larger. Another classical example of an uncountable set, established using a related reasoning, is the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of the natural numbers, denoted \mathcal(\N). This is the set of all
subsets In mathematics, a set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subse ...
of \N, including the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
and \N itself. The method is much closer to Cantor's original diagonal argument. Again, assume by contradiction that there exists a one-to-one correspondence f between \N and \mathcal(\N), so that every subset of \N is assigned to some natural number. These subsets are then placed in a column, in the order defined by f (see image). Now, one may define a subset T of \N which is not in the list by taking the negation of the "diagonal" of this column as follows: If 1 \in f(1), then 1 \notin T, that is, if 1 is in the first subset of the list, then 1 is ''not'' in the subset T. Further, if 2 \notin f(2) , then 2 \in T, that is if the number 2 is not in the second subset of the column, then 2 ''is'' in the subset T. Then in general, for each natural number n, n \in T if and only if n \notin f(n) , meaning n is put in the subset T only if the nth subset in the column does not contain the number n. Then, for each natural number n, T \neq f(n), meaning, T is not the nth subset in the list, for any number n, and so it cannot appear anywhere in the list defined by f. Since f was chosen arbitrarily, this shows that every function from \N to \mathcal(\N) must be missing at least one element, therefore no such bijection can exist, and so \mathcal(\N) must be not be countable. These two sets, \R and \mathcal(\N) can be shown to have the same cardinality (by, for example, assigning each subset to a decimal expansion). Whether there exists a set A with cardinality between these two sets , \N, < , A, < , \R, is known as the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
.
Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
generalizes the second theorem above, showing that every set is strictly smaller than its powerset. The proof roughly goes as follows: Given a set A, assume by contradiction that there is a bijection f from A to \mathcal(A). Then, the subset T \subseteq A given by taking the negation of the "diagonal", formally, T = \, cannot be in the list. Therefore, every function is missing at least one element, and so , A, < , \mathcal(A), . Further, since \mathcal(A) is itself a set, the argument can be repeated to show , A, < , \mathcal(A), < , \mathcal(\mathcal(A)), . Taking A = \N, this shows that \mathcal(\mathcal(\N)) is even larger than \mathcal(\N) , which was already shown to be uncountable. Repeating this argument shows that there are infinitely many "sizes" of infinity.


Cardinal numbers

In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined relationally. In other words, while it was closely tied to the concept of number, the meaning of "number of elements" has not yet been defined. This can be formalized from basic set-theoretic principles, relying on some number-like structures. For finite sets, this is simply the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
found by counting the elements. This number is called the ''cardinal number'' of that set, or simply ''the cardinality'' of that set. The cardinal number of a set A is generally denoted by , A, , with a
vertical bar The vertical bar, , is a glyph with various uses in mathematics, computing, and typography. It has many names, often related to particular meanings: Sheffer stroke (in logic), pipe, bar, or (literally, the word "or"), vbar, and others. Usage ...
on each side, though it may also be denoted by n(A), A, \operatorname(A), or \#A. For infinite sets, "cardinal number" is somewhat more difficult to define formally. However, cardinal numbers are not usually thought of in terms of their formal definition, but immaterially in terms of their arithmetic/algebraic properties. For example, defining , \N, = \aleph_0, and A \sim B if and only if , A, = , B, . Then 2^ = , \mathcal(\N), \sim , \R, .


Finite sets

Given a basic sense of
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
, a set is said to have cardinality n if it can be put in one-to-one correspondence with the set \. For example, the set S = \ has a natural correspondence with the set \, and therefore is said to have cardinality 4. Other terminologies include "Its cardinality is 4" or "Its cardinal number is 4". While this definition uses a basic sense of natural numbers, it may be that cardinality is used to define the natural numbers, in which case, a simple construction of objects satisfying the
Peano axioms In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (, ), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nea ...
can be used as a substitute. Most commonly, the
Von Neumann ordinal In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the least ...
s. Showing that such a correspondence exists is not always trivial, which is the subject matter of
combinatorics Combinatorics is an area of mathematics primarily concerned with counting, both as a means and as an end to obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. It is closely related to many other areas of mathematics and has many ...
.


Uniqueness

An intuitive property of finite sets is that, for example, if a set has cardinality 4, then it cannot also have cardinality 5. Intuitively meaning that a set cannot have both exactly 4 elements and exactly 5 elements. However, it is not so obviously proven. The following proof is adapted from ''Analysis I'' by Terence Tao. Lemma: If a set X has cardinality n \geq 1, and x_0 \in X, then the set X - \ (i.e. X with the element x_0 removed) has cardinality n-1. Proof: Given X as above, since X has cardinality n, there is a bijection f from X to \. Then, since x_0 \in X, there must be some number f(x_0) in \. We need to find a bijection from X - \ to \ (which may be empty). Define a function g such that g(x) = f(x) for all x \neq n and g(n) = f(x_0) . Then g is a bijection from X - \ to \. Theorem: If a set X has cardinality n, then it cannot have any other cardinality. That is, X cannot also have cardinality m \neq n. Proof: If X is empty (has cardinality 0), then there cannot exist a bijection from X to any nonempty set Y, since nothing mapped to y_0 \in Y. Assume, by induction that the result has been proven up to some cardinality n. If X, has cardinality n+1, assume it also has cardinality m. We want to show that m = n+1. By the lemma above, X - \ must have cardinality n and m-1. Since, by induction, cardinality is unique for sets with cardinality n, it must be that m-1 = n, and thus m = n+1.


Combinatorics

Combinatorics Combinatorics is an area of mathematics primarily concerned with counting, both as a means and as an end to obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. It is closely related to many other areas of mathematics and has many ...
is the area of mathematics primarily concerned with
counting Counting is the process of determining the number of elements of a finite set of objects; that is, determining the size of a set. The traditional way of counting consists of continually increasing a (mental or spoken) counter by a unit for ever ...
, both as a means and as an end to obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. The notion cardinality of finite sets is closely tied to many basic
combinatorial principles In proving results in combinatorics several useful combinatorial rules or combinatorial principles are commonly recognized and used. The rule of sum, rule of product, and inclusion–exclusion principle are often used for Enumerative combinatorics ...
, and provides a set-theoretic foundation to prove them. The above shows uniqueness of finite cardinal numbers, and therefore, A \sim B if and only if , A, = , B, , formalizing the notion of a
bijective proof In combinatorics, bijective proof is a proof technique for proving that two sets have equally many elements, or that the sets in two combinatorial classes have equal size, by finding a bijective function that maps one set one-to-one onto the other ...
. The addition principle asserts that given disjoint sets A and B, , A \cup B, = , A, + , B, , intuitively meaning that the sum of parts is equal to the sum of the whole. The multiplication principle asserts that given two sets A and B, , A \times B, = , A, \cdot , B, , intuitively meaning that there are , A, \cdot , B, ways to pair objects from these sets. Both of these can be proven by a bijective proof, together with induction. The more general result is the
inclusion–exclusion principle In combinatorics, the inclusion–exclusion principle is a counting technique which generalizes the familiar method of obtaining the number of elements in the union (set theory), union of two finite sets; symbolically expressed as : , A \cup B, ...
, which defines how to count the number of elements in overlapping sets.


Aleph numbers

The aleph numbers are a sequence of cardinal numbers that denote the size of
infinite sets In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set tha ...
, denoted with an
aleph Aleph (or alef or alif, transliterated ʾ) is the first Letter (alphabet), letter of the Semitic abjads, including Phoenician alphabet, Phoenician ''ʾālep'' 𐤀, Hebrew alphabet, Hebrew ''ʾālef'' , Aramaic alphabet, Aramaic ''ʾālap'' � ...
\aleph, the first letter of the
Hebrew alphabet The Hebrew alphabet (, ), known variously by scholars as the Ktav Ashuri, Jewish script, square script and block script, is a unicase, unicameral abjad script used in the writing of the Hebrew language and other Jewish languages, most notably ...
. The first aleph number is \aleph_0, called "aleph-nought", "aleph-zero", or "aleph-null", which represents the cardinality of the set of all
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
: \aleph_0 = , \N, = , \, . Then, \aleph_1 represents the next largest cardinality. The most common way this is formalized in set theory is through
Von Neumann ordinal In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the least ...
s, known as
Von Neumann cardinal assignment The von Neumann cardinal assignment is a cardinal assignment that uses ordinal numbers. For a well-orderable set ''U'', we define its cardinal number to be the smallest ordinal number equinumerous to ''U'', using the von Neumann definition of a ...
.
Ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s generalize the notion of ''order'' to infinite sets. For example, 2 comes after 1, denoted 1 < 2, and 3 comes after both, denoted 1 < 2 < 3. Then, one defines a new number, \omega, which comes after every natural number, denoted 1 < 2 < 3 < \cdots < \omega. Further \omega < \omega+1 , and so on. More formally, these ordinal numbers can be defined as follows: 0 := \, the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
, 1 := \ , 2 := \, 3 := \, and so on. Then one can define m < n \text \, m \in n, for examlpe, 2 \in \ = 3, therefore 2 < 3. Defining \omega := \ (a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
) gives \omega the desired property of being the smallest ordinal greater than all finite ordinal numbers. Further, \omega+1 := \, and so on. Since \omega \sim \N by the natural correspondence, one may define \aleph_0 as the set of all finite ordinals. That is, \aleph_0 := \omega. Then, \aleph_1 is the set of all countable ordinals (all ordinals \kappa with cardinality , \kappa, \leq \aleph_0), the
first uncountable ordinal In mathematics, the first uncountable ordinal, traditionally denoted by \omega_1 or sometimes by \Omega, is the smallest ordinal number that, considered as a set, is uncountable. It is the supremum (least upper bound) of all countable ordinals. Whe ...
. Since a set cannot contain itself, \aleph_1 must have a strictly larger cardinality: \aleph_0 < \aleph_1. Furthermore, \aleph_2 is the set of all ordinals with cardinality \aleph_1, and so on. By the
well-ordering theorem In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set ''X'' is ''well-ordered'' by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of ''X'' has a least element under the order ...
, there cannot exist any set with cardinality between \aleph_0 and \aleph_1, and every infinite set has some cardinality corresponding to some aleph \aleph_\alpha, for some ordinal \alpha.


Cardinality of the continuum

The
number line A number line is a graphical representation of a straight line that serves as spatial representation of numbers, usually graduated like a ruler with a particular origin point representing the number zero and evenly spaced marks in either dire ...
is a geometric construct of the intuitive notions of "
space Space is a three-dimensional continuum containing positions and directions. In classical physics, physical space is often conceived in three linear dimensions. Modern physicists usually consider it, with time, to be part of a boundless ...
" and "
distance Distance is a numerical or occasionally qualitative measurement of how far apart objects, points, people, or ideas are. In physics or everyday usage, distance may refer to a physical length or an estimation based on other criteria (e.g. "two co ...
" wherein each point corresponds to a distinct quantity or position along a continuous path. The terms "continuum" and "continuous" refer to the totality of this line, having some space (other points) between any two points on the line (
dense Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the ratio of a substance's mass to its volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' (or ''d'') can also be use ...
and archimedian) and the absence of any gaps ( completeness), This intuitive construct is formalized by the set of
real numbers In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measurement, measure a continuous variable, continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a time, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbi ...
(\R) which model the continuum as a complete, densely ordered, uncountable set. The cardinality of the continuum, denoted by "\mathfrak c" (a lowercase fraktur script "c"), remains invariant under various transformations and mappings, many considered surprising. For example, all intervals on the real line e.g. ,1/math>, and ,2/math>, have the same cardinality as the entire set \R. First, f(x) = 2x is a bijection from ,1/math> to ,2/math>. Then, the
tangent function In mathematics, the trigonometric functions (also called circular functions, angle functions or goniometric functions) are real functions which relate an angle of a right-angled triangle to ratios of two side lengths. They are widely used in all ...
is a bijection from the interval \left( \frac \, , \frac \right) to the whole real line. A more surprising example is the
Cantor set In mathematics, the Cantor set is a set of points lying on a single line segment that has a number of unintuitive properties. It was discovered in 1874 by Henry John Stephen Smith and mentioned by German mathematician Georg Cantor in 1883. Throu ...
, which is defined as follows: take the interval ,1/math> and remove the middle third \left( \frac, \frac \right), then remove the middle third of each of the two remaining segments, and continue removing middle thirds (see image). The Cantor set is the set of points that survive this process. This set that remains is all of the points whose decimal expansion can be written in ternary without a 1. Reinterpreting these decimal expansions as
binary Binary may refer to: Science and technology Mathematics * Binary number, a representation of numbers using only two values (0 and 1) for each digit * Binary function, a function that takes two arguments * Binary operation, a mathematical op ...
(e.g. by replacing the 2s with 1s) gives a bijection between the Cantor set and the interval ,1/math>. Space-filling curves are continuous surjective maps from the
unit interval In mathematics, the unit interval is the closed interval , that is, the set of all real numbers that are greater than or equal to 0 and less than or equal to 1. It is often denoted ' (capital letter ). In addition to its role in real analysi ...
,1/math> onto the
unit square In mathematics, a unit square is a square whose sides have length . Often, ''the'' unit square refers specifically to the square in the Cartesian plane with corners at the four points ), , , and . Cartesian coordinates In a Cartesian coordinat ...
on \R^2, with classical examples such as the
Peano curve In geometry, the Peano curve is the first example of a space-filling curve to be discovered, by Giuseppe Peano in 1890. Peano's curve is a surjective, continuous function from the unit interval onto the unit square, however it is not injective. ...
and
Hilbert David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
curve In mathematics, a curve (also called a curved line in older texts) is an object similar to a line, but that does not have to be straight. Intuitively, a curve may be thought of as the trace left by a moving point. This is the definition that ...
. Although such maps are not injective, they are indeed surjective, and thus suffice to demonstrate cardinal equivalence. They can be reused at each dimension to show that , \R, = , \R^n, = \mathfrak for any dimension n \geq 1. The infinite
cartesian product In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets and , denoted , is the set of all ordered pairs where is an element of and is an element of . In terms of set-builder notation, that is A\times B = \. A table c ...
\R^\infty, can also be shown to have cardinality \mathfrak c. This can be established by cardinal exponentiation: , \R^\infty, = \mathfrak^ = \left(2^ \right)^ = 2^ = 2^ = \mathfrak = , \R, . Thus, the real numbers, all finite-dimensional real spaces, and the countable cartesian product share the same cardinality. As shown in , the set of real numbers is strictly larger than the set of natural numbers. Specifically, , \R, = , \mathcal(\N), . The
Continuum Hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
(CH) asserts that the real numbers have the next largest cardinality after the natural numbers, that is , \R, = \aleph_1. As shown by Gödel and Cohen, the continuum hypothesis is
independent Independent or Independents may refer to: Arts, entertainment, and media Artist groups * Independents (artist group), a group of modernist painters based in Pennsylvania, United States * Independentes (English: Independents), a Portuguese artist ...
of ZFC, a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
. The
Generalized Continuum Hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
(GCH) extends this to all infinite cardinals, stating that 2^ = \aleph_ for every ordinal \alpha. Without GHC, the cardinality of \R cannot be written in terms of alephs. The Beth numbers provide a concise notation for powersets of the real numbers starting from \beth_1 = , \R, , then \beth_2 = , \mathcal(\R), = 2^, and in general \beth_ = 2^.


Paradoxes

During the rise of set theory, several
paradoxes A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true or apparently true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictor ...
(see: ''
Paradoxes of set theory This article contains a discussion of paradoxes of set theory. As with most mathematical paradoxes, they generally reveal surprising and counter-intuitive mathematical results, rather than actual logical contradictions within modern axiomatic set ...
''). These can be divided into two kinds: ''real paradoxes'' and ''apparent paradoxes''. Apparent paradoxes are those which follow a series of reasonable steps and arrive at a conclusion which seems impossible or incorrect according to one's
intuition Intuition is the ability to acquire knowledge without recourse to conscious reasoning or needing an explanation. Different fields use the word "intuition" in very different ways, including but not limited to: direct access to unconscious knowledg ...
, but aren't necessarily logically impossible. Two historical examples have been given, ''Galileo's Paradox'' and ''Aristotle's Wheel'', in . Real paradoxes are those which, through reasonable steps, prove a logical contradiction. The real paradoxes here apply to
naive set theory Naive set theory is any of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics. Unlike axiomatic set theories, which are defined using formal logic, naive set theory is defined informally, in natural language. It de ...
or otherwise informal statements, and have been resolved by restating the problem in terms of a formalized set theory, such as
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
.


Apparent paradoxes


Hilbert's hotel

Hilbert's Hotel is a
thought experiment A thought experiment is an imaginary scenario that is meant to elucidate or test an argument or theory. It is often an experiment that would be hard, impossible, or unethical to actually perform. It can also be an abstract hypothetical that is ...
devised by the German mathematician
David Hilbert David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental idea ...
to illustrate a counterintuitive property of countably infinite sets, allowing them to have the same cardinality as a
proper subset In mathematics, a set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset ...
of themselves. The scenario begins by imagining a hotel with an infinite number of rooms, all of which are occupied. But then a new guest walks in asking for a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the occupant of room 1 to room 2, the occupant of room 2 to room 3, room three to room 4, and in general, room n to room n+1. Then every guest still has a room, but room 1 opens up for the new guest.Archived
on 2016-01-06
Then, the scenario continues by imagining an infinite bus of new guests seeking a room. The hotel accommodates by moving the person in room 1 to room 2, room 2 to room 4, and in general, room n to room 2n. Thus, all the even-numbered rooms are occupied, but all the odd-numbered rooms are vacant, leaving room for the infinite bus of new guests. The scenario continues by assuming an infinite number of these infinite buses arrive at the hotel, and showing that the hotel is still able to accommodate. Finally, an infinite bus which has a seat for every
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
arrives, and the hotel is no longer able to accommodate.


Skolem's paradox

In
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
, a
model A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided in ...
corresponds to a specific interpretation of a
formal language In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbols that concatenate into strings (also c ...
or
theory A theory is a systematic and rational form of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the conclusions derived from such thinking. It involves contemplative and logical reasoning, often supported by processes such as observation, experimentation, ...
. It consists of a domain (a set of objects) and an interpretation of the symbols and formulas in the language, such that the axioms of the theory are satisfied within this structure. The
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
shows that any model of set theory in
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
, if it is
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
, has an equivalent
model A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided in ...
which is countable. This appears contradictory, because
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
proved that there exist sets which are not countable. Thus the seeming contradiction is that a model that is itself countable, and which therefore contains only countable sets, satisfies the first-order sentence that intuitively states "there are uncountable sets". A mathematical explanation of the paradox, showing that it is not a true contradiction in mathematics, was first given in 1922 by
Thoralf Skolem Thoralf Albert Skolem (; 23 May 1887 – 23 March 1963) was a Norwegian mathematician who worked in mathematical logic and set theory. Life Although Skolem's father was a primary school teacher, most of his extended family were farmers. Skole ...
. He explained that the countability of a set is not absolute, but relative to the model in which the cardinality is measured. Skolem's work was harshly received by
Ernst Zermelo Ernst Friedrich Ferdinand Zermelo (; ; 27 July 187121 May 1953) was a German logician and mathematician, whose work has major implications for the foundations of mathematics. He is known for his role in developing Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, Z ...
, who argued against the limitations of first-order logic and Skolem's notion of "relativity", but the result quickly came to be accepted by the mathematical community.


Real paradoxes


Cantor's paradox

Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
state's that, for any set A, possibly infinite, its
powerset In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
\mathcal(A) has a strictly greater cardinality. For example, this means there is no bijection from \N to \mathcal(\N) \sim \R.
Cantor's paradox In set theory, Cantor's paradox states that there is no set of all cardinalities. This is derived from the theorem that there is no greatest cardinal number. In informal terms, the paradox is that the collection of all possible "infinite sizes" i ...
is a paradox in
naive set theory Naive set theory is any of several theories of sets used in the discussion of the foundations of mathematics. Unlike axiomatic set theories, which are defined using formal logic, naive set theory is defined informally, in natural language. It de ...
, which shows that there cannot exist a "set of all sets" or " universe set". It starts by assuming there is some set of all sets, U := \, then it must be that U is strictly smaller than \mathcal(U), thus , U, \leq , \mathcal(U), . But since U contains all sets, we must have that \mathcal(U) \subseteq U, and thus , \mathcal(U), \leq , U, . Therefore , \mathcal(U), = , U, , contradicting Cantor's theorem. This was one of the original paradoxes that added to the need for a formalized set theory to avoid these paradoxes. This paradox is usually resolved in formal set theories by disallowing
unrestricted comprehension In many popular versions of axiomatic set theory, the axiom schema of specification, also known as the axiom schema of separation (''Aussonderungsaxiom''), subset axiom, axiom of class construction, or axiom schema of restricted comprehension is ...
and the existence of a universe set.


Set of all cardinal numbers

Similar to Cantor's paradox, the paradox of the set of all cardinal numbers is a result due to unrestricted comprehension. It often uses the definition of cardinal numbers as ordinal numbers for representatives. It is related to the Burali-Forti paradox. It begins by assuming there is some set S := \. Then, if there is some largest element \aleph \in S , then the powerset \mathcal(\aleph) is strictly greater, and thus not in S. Conversly, if there is no largest element, then the union \bigcup S contains the elements of all elements of S, and is therefore greater than or equal to each element. Since there is no largest element in S, for any element x \in S, there is another element y \in S such that , x, < , y, and , y, \leq \Bigl, \bigcup S \Bigr, . Thus, for any x \in S, , x, < \Bigl, \bigcup S \Bigr, , and so \Bigl, \bigcup S \Bigr, \notin S.


See also

*
Cardinal function In mathematics, a cardinal function (or cardinal invariant) is a function that returns cardinal numbers. Cardinal functions in set theory * The most frequently used cardinal function is the function that assigns to a set ''A'' its cardinality, ...
*
Inaccessible cardinal In set theory, a cardinal number is a strongly inaccessible cardinal if it is uncountable, regular, and a strong limit cardinal. A cardinal is a weakly inaccessible cardinal if it is uncountable, regular, and a weak limit cardinal. Since abou ...
* Infinitary combinatorics *
Large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least ...
**
List of large cardinal properties This page includes a list of large cardinal properties in the mathematical field of set theory. It is arranged roughly in order of the consistency strength of the axiom asserting the existence of cardinals with the given property. Existence of a ...
* Numerosity (mathematics) *
Regular cardinal In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite ...
*
Scott's trick In set theory, Scott's trick is a method for giving a definition of equivalence classes for equivalence relations on a proper class (Jech 2003:65) by referring to levels of the cumulative hierarchy. The method relies on the axiom of regularity bu ...
* ''The Higher Infinite'' *
Von Neumann universe In set theory and related branches of mathematics, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the class of hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ( ...
*
Zero sharp In the mathematical discipline of set theory, 0# (zero sharp, also 0#) is the set of true formulae about indiscernibles and order-indiscernibles in the Gödel constructible universe. It is often encoded as a subset of the natural numbers (using ...


References


Citations


Bibliography

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * {{Authority control Basic concepts in infinite set theory