HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concer ...
, König's theorem states that if the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
holds, ''I'' is a set, \kappa_i and \lambda_i are
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. Th ...
s for every ''i'' in ''I'', and \kappa_i < \lambda_i for every ''i'' in ''I'', then :\sum_\kappa_i < \prod_\lambda_i. The sum here is the cardinality of the
disjoint union In mathematics, a disjoint union (or discriminated union) of a family of sets (A_i : i\in I) is a set A, often denoted by \bigsqcup_ A_i, with an injection of each A_i into A, such that the images of these injections form a partition of A ( ...
of the sets ''mi'', and the product is the cardinality of the
Cartesian product In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets ''A'' and ''B'', denoted ''A''×''B'', is the set of all ordered pairs where ''a'' is in ''A'' and ''b'' is in ''B''. In terms of set-builder notation, that is : A\tim ...
. However, without the use of the axiom of choice, the sum and the product cannot be defined as cardinal numbers, and the meaning of the inequality sign would need to be clarified. König's theorem was introduced by in the slightly weaker form that the sum of a strictly increasing sequence of nonzero cardinal numbers is less than their product.


Details

The precise statement of the result: if ''I'' is a set, ''Ai'' and ''Bi'' are sets for every ''i'' in ''I'', and A_i for every ''i'' in ''I'', then :\sum_A_i < \prod_B_i, where < means ''strictly less than in
cardinality In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
'', i.e. there is an
injective In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contraposit ...
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-oriente ...
from ''Ai'' to ''Bi'', but not one going the other way. The union involved need not be disjoint (a non-disjoint union can't be any bigger than the disjoint version, also assuming the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
). In this formulation, König's theorem is equivalent to the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
. (Of course, König's theorem is trivial if the cardinal numbers ''mi'' and ''ni'' are
finite Finite is the opposite of infinite. It may refer to: * Finite number (disambiguation) * Finite set, a set whose cardinality (number of elements) is some natural number * Finite verb Traditionally, a finite verb (from la, fīnītus, past particip ...
and the index set ''I'' is finite. If ''I'' is empty, then the left sum is the empty sum and therefore 0, while the right product is the
empty product In mathematics, an empty product, or nullary product or vacuous product, is the result of multiplying no factors. It is by convention equal to the multiplicative identity (assuming there is an identity for the multiplication operation in questio ...
and therefore 1). König's theorem is remarkable because of the strict inequality in the conclusion. There are many easy rules for the arithmetic of infinite sums and products of cardinals in which one can only conclude a weak inequality ≤, for example: if m_i < n_i for all ''i'' in ''I'', then one can only conclude :\sum_ m_i \le \sum_ n_i, since, for example, setting m_i = 1 and n_i = 2, where the index set ''I'' is the natural numbers, yields the sum \aleph_0 for both sides, and we have an equality.


Corollaries of König's theorem

* If \kappa is a cardinal, then \kappa < 2^\kappa. If we take ''mi'' = 1, and ''ni'' = 2 for each ''i'' in κ, then the left side of the above inequality is just κ, while the right side is 2κ, the cardinality of functions from κ to , that is, the cardinality of the power set of κ. Thus, König's theorem gives us an alternate proof of
Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any set A, the set of all subsets of A, the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite sets, Cantor's theorem can b ...
. (Historically of course Cantor's theorem was proved much earlier.)


Axiom of choice

One way of stating the axiom of choice is "an arbitrary Cartesian product of non-empty sets is non-empty". Let ''Bi'' be a non-empty set for each ''i'' in ''I''. Let ''Ai'' = for each ''i'' in ''I''. Thus by König's theorem, we have: * If \forall i \in I(\ < B_i), then \ < \prod_B_i. That is, the Cartesian product of the given non-empty sets ''Bi'' has a larger cardinality than the sum of empty sets. Thus it is non-empty, which is just what the axiom of choice states. Since the axiom of choice follows from König's theorem, we will use the axiom of choice freely and implicitly when discussing consequences of the theorem.


König's theorem and cofinality

König's theorem has also important consequences for
cofinality In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf(''A'') of a partially ordered set ''A'' is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of ''A''. This definition of cofinality relies on the axiom of choice, as it uses th ...
of cardinal numbers. * If \kappa \ge \aleph_0, then \kappa < \kappa^. Choose a strictly increasing cf(κ)-sequence of ordinals approaching κ. Each of them is less than κ, so their sum, which is κ, is less than the product of cf(κ) copies of κ. According to
Easton's theorem In set theory, Easton's theorem is a result on the possible cardinal numbers of powersets. (extending a result of Robert M. Solovay) showed via forcing that the only constraints on permissible values for 2''κ'' when ''κ'' is a regular cardinal ...
, the next consequence of König's theorem is the only nontrivial constraint on the continuum function for
regular cardinal In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite ...
s. * If \kappa \geq \aleph_0 and \lambda \geq 2, then \kappa < \operatorname(\lambda^\kappa). Let \mu = \lambda^\kappa. Suppose that, contrary to this corollary, \kappa \ge \operatorname(\mu). Then using the previous corollary, \mu < \mu^ \le \mu^\kappa = (\lambda^\kappa)^\kappa = \lambda^ = \lambda^\kappa = \mu, a contradiction.


A proof of König's theorem

Assuming
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such a ...
, including especially the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
, we can prove the theorem. Remember that we are given \forall i\in I\quad A_i, and we want to show :\sum_A_i<\prod_B_i. The axiom of choice implies that the condition ''A'' < ''B'' is equivalent to the condition that there is no function from ''A'' onto ''B'' and ''B'' is nonempty. So we are given that there is no function from ''A''''i'' onto ''B''''i''≠, and we have to show that any function ''f'' from the disjoint union of the ''A''s to the product of the ''B''s is not surjective and that the product is nonempty. That the product is nonempty follows immediately from the axiom of choice and the fact that the factors are nonempty. For each ''i'' choose a ''b''''i'' in ''B''''i'' not in the image of ''A''''i'' under the composition of ''f'' with the projection to ''B''''i''. Then the product of the elements ''b''''i'' is not in the image of ''f'', so ''f'' does not map the disjoint union of the ''A''s onto the product of the ''B''s.


Notes


References

* * , reprinted as {{DEFAULTSORT:Konigs theorem Articles containing proofs Axiom of choice Cardinal numbers Mathematical logic Theorems in the foundations of mathematics