Zermelo set theory (sometimes denoted by Z
-), as set out in a seminal paper in 1908 by
Ernst Zermelo
Ernst Friedrich Ferdinand Zermelo (; ; 27 July 187121 May 1953) was a German logician and mathematician, whose work has major implications for the foundations of mathematics. He is known for his role in developing Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, Z ...
, is the ancestor of modern
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZF) and its extensions, such as
von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory
In the foundations of mathematics, von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG) is an axiomatic set theory that is a conservative extension of Zermelo–Fraenkel–choice set theory (ZFC). NBG introduces the notion of class, which is a collec ...
(NBG). It bears certain differences from its descendants, which are not always understood, and are frequently misquoted. This article sets out the original
axiom
An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s, with the original text (translated into English) and original numbering.
The axioms of Zermelo set theory
The
axiom
An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s of Zermelo set theory are stated for objects, some of which (but not necessarily all) are sets, and the remaining objects are
urelements and not sets. Zermelo's language implicitly includes a membership relation ∈, an equality relation = (if it is not included in the underlying logic), and a unary predicate saying whether an object is a set. Later versions of set theory often assume that all objects are sets so there are no urelements and there is no need for the unary predicate.
# AXIOM I.
Axiom of extensionality
The axiom of extensionality, also called the axiom of extent, is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. The axiom defines what a Set (mathematics), set is. Informally, the axiom means that the ...
(''Axiom der Bestimmtheit'') "If every element of a set ''M'' is also an element of ''N'' and vice versa ... then ''M''
''N''. Briefly, every set is determined by its elements."
# AXIOM II. Axiom of elementary sets (''Axiom der Elementarmengen'') "There exists a set, the
null set
In mathematical analysis, a null set is a Lebesgue measurable set of real numbers that has measure zero. This can be characterized as a set that can be covered by a countable union of intervals of arbitrarily small total length.
The notio ...
, ∅, that contains no element at all. If ''a'' is any object of the domain, there exists a set containing ''a'' and only ''a'' as an element. If ''a'' and ''b'' are any two objects of the domain, there always exists a set containing as elements ''a'' and ''b'' but no object ''x'' distinct from them both." See
Axiom of empty set
In axiomatic set theory, the axiom of empty set, also called the axiom of null set and the axiom of existence, is a statement that asserts the existence of a set with no elements. It is an axiom of Kripke–Platek set theory and the variant of g ...
and
Axiom of pairing
In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It was introduced by as a special case of his axiom of elementary sets ...
.
# AXIOM III.
Axiom of separation (''Axiom der Aussonderung'') "Whenever the
propositional function In propositional calculus, a propositional function or a predicate is a sentence expressed in a way that would assume the value of true or false, except that within the sentence there is a variable (''x'') that is not defined or specified (thus be ...
–(''x'') is defined for all elements of a set ''M'', ''M'' possesses a subset ''M' '' containing as elements precisely those elements ''x'' of ''M'' for which –(''x'') is true."
# AXIOM IV.
Axiom of the power set (''Axiom der Potenzmenge'') "To every set ''T'' there corresponds a set ''T' '', the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of ''T'', that contains as elements precisely all subsets of ''T'' ."
# AXIOM V.
Axiom of the union (''Axiom der Vereinigung'') "To every set ''T'' there corresponds a set ''∪T'', the union of ''T'', that contains as elements precisely all elements of the elements of ''T'' ."
# AXIOM VI.
Axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(''Axiom der Auswahl'') "If ''T'' is a set whose elements all are sets that are different from ∅ and mutually disjoint, its union ''∪T'' includes at least one subset ''S''
1 having one and only one element in common with each element of ''T'' ."
# AXIOM VII.
Axiom of infinity
In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
(''Axiom des Unendlichen'') "There exists in the domain at least one set ''Z'' that contains the null set as an element and is so constituted that to each of its elements ''a'' there corresponds a further element of the form , in other words, that with each of its elements ''a'' it also contains the corresponding set as element."
Connection with standard set theory
The most widely used and accepted set theory is known as ZFC, which consists of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
including the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC). The links show where the axioms of Zermelo's theory correspond. There is no exact match for "elementary sets". (It was later shown that the singleton set could be derived from what is now called the "Axiom of pairs". If ''a'' exists, ''a'' and ''a'' exist, thus exists, and so by extensionality = .) The empty set axiom is already assumed by axiom of infinity, and is now included as part of it.
Zermelo set theory does not include the axioms of
replacement and
regularity. The axiom of replacement was first published in 1922 by
Abraham Fraenkel
Abraham Fraenkel (; 17 February, 1891 – 15 October, 1965) was a German-born Israeli mathematician. He was an early Zionist and the first Dean of Mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. He is known for his contributions to axiomatic ...
and
Thoralf Skolem
Thoralf Albert Skolem (; 23 May 1887 – 23 March 1963) was a Norwegian mathematician who worked in mathematical logic and set theory.
Life
Although Skolem's father was a primary school teacher, most of his extended family were farmers. Skole ...
, who had independently discovered that Zermelo's axioms cannot prove the existence of the set where ''Z''
0 is the set of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s and ''Z''
''n''+1 is the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of ''Z''
''n''. They both realized that the axiom of replacement is needed to prove this. The following year,
John von Neumann
John von Neumann ( ; ; December 28, 1903 – February 8, 1957) was a Hungarian and American mathematician, physicist, computer scientist and engineer. Von Neumann had perhaps the widest coverage of any mathematician of his time, in ...
pointed out that the axiom of regularity is necessary to build
his theory of ordinals. The axiom of regularity was stated by von Neumann in 1925.
In the modern ZFC system, the "propositional function" referred to in the axiom of separation is interpreted as "any property definable by a first-order
formula
In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
with parameters", so the separation axiom is replaced by an
axiom schema
In mathematical logic, an axiom schema (plural: axiom schemata or axiom schemas) generalizes the notion of axiom.
Formal definition
An axiom schema is a formula in the metalanguage of an axiomatic system, in which one or more schematic variabl ...
. The notion of "first order formula" was not known in 1908 when Zermelo published his axiom system, and he later rejected this interpretation as being too restrictive. Zermelo set theory is usually taken to be a first-order theory with the separation axiom replaced by an axiom scheme with an axiom for each first-order formula. It can also be considered as a theory in
second-order logic
In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory.
First-order logic quantifies on ...
, where now the separation axiom is just a single axiom. The second-order interpretation of Zermelo set theory is probably closer to Zermelo's own conception of it, and is stronger than the first-order interpretation.
Since
—where
is the rank-
set in the
cumulative hierarchy—forms a model of second-order Zermelo set theory within ZFC whenever
is a
limit ordinal
In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
greater than the smallest infinite ordinal
, it follows that the consistency of second-order Zermelo set theory (and therefore also that of first-order Zermelo set theory) is a theorem of ZFC. If we let
, the existence of an
uncountable
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger tha ...
strong limit cardinal
In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number ''λ'' is a weak limit cardinal if ''λ'' is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" ''λ'' from another cardinal by repeated success ...
is not satisfied in such a model; thus the existence of
''ℶω'' (the smallest uncountable strong limit cardinal) cannot be proved in second-order Zermelo set theory. Similarly, the set
(where ''L'' is the
constructible universe
In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by L, is a particular Class (set theory), class of Set (mathematics), sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. L is the un ...
) forms a model of first-order Zermelo set theory wherein the existence of an uncountable weak limit cardinal is not satisfied, showing that first-order Zermelo set theory cannot even prove the existence of the smallest
singular cardinal
Singular may refer to:
* Singular, the grammatical number that denotes a unit quantity, as opposed to the plural and other forms
* Singular or sounder, a group of boar, see List of animal names
* Singular (band), a Thai jazz pop duo
*'' Singular ...
,
. Within such a model, the only infinite cardinals are the
aleph numbers restricted to finite index ordinals.
The
axiom of infinity
In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
is usually now modified to assert the existence of the first infinite von Neumann
ordinal ; the original Zermelo axioms cannot prove the existence of this set, nor can the modified Zermelo axioms prove Zermelo's axiom of infinity.
Zermelo's axioms (original or modified) cannot prove the existence of
as a set nor of any rank of the cumulative hierarchy of sets with infinite index. In any formulation, Zermelo set theory cannot prove the existence of the von Neumann ordinal
, despite proving the existence of such an order type; thus the von Neumann definition of ordinals is not employed for Zermelo set theory.
Zermelo allowed for the existence of
urelements that are not sets and contain no elements; these are now usually omitted from set theories.
Mac Lane set theory
Mac Lane set theory, introduced by , is Zermelo set theory with the axiom of separation restricted to first-order formulas in which every quantifier is bounded.
Mac Lane set theory is similar in strength to
topos theory
In mathematics, a topos (, ; plural topoi or , or toposes) is a category that behaves like the category of sheaves of sets on a topological space (or more generally, on a site). Topoi behave much like the category of sets and possess a notion ...
with a
natural number object In category theory, a natural numbers object (NNO) is an object endowed with a Recursion (computer science), recursive Mathematical structure, structure similar to natural numbers. More precisely, in a Category (mathematics), category E with a termi ...
, or to the system in
Principia mathematica
The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by the mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1 ...
. It is strong enough to carry out almost all ordinary mathematics not directly connected with set theory or logic.
The aim of Zermelo's paper
The introduction states that the very existence of the discipline of set theory "seems to be threatened by certain contradictions or "antinomies", that can be derived from its principles – principles necessarily governing our thinking, it seems – and to which no entirely satisfactory solution has yet been found". Zermelo is of course referring to the "
Russell antinomy".
He says he wants to show how the original theory of
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ; – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
and
Richard Dedekind
Julius Wilhelm Richard Dedekind (; ; 6 October 1831 – 12 February 1916) was a German mathematician who made important contributions to number theory, abstract algebra (particularly ring theory), and the axiomatic foundations of arithmetic. H ...
can be reduced to a few definitions and seven principles or axioms. He says he has ''not'' been able to prove that the axioms are consistent.
A non-constructivist argument for their consistency goes as follows. Define ''V''
α for α one of the
ordinals 0, 1, 2, ...,ω, ω+1, ω+2,..., ω·2 as follows:
* V
0 is the empty set.
* For α a successor of the form β+1, ''V''
α is defined to be the collection of all subsets of ''V''
β.
* For α a limit (e.g. ω, ω·2) then ''V''
α is defined to be the union of ''V''
β for β<α.
Then the axioms of Zermelo set theory are consistent because they are true in the model ''V''
ω·2. While a non-constructivist might regard this as a valid argument, a constructivist would probably not: while there are no problems with the construction of the sets up to ''V''
ω, the construction of ''V''
ω+1 is less clear because one cannot constructively define every subset of ''V''
ω. This argument can be turned into a valid proof with the addition of a single new axiom of infinity to Zermelo set theory, simply that ''V''
ω·2 ''exists''. This is presumably not convincing for a constructivist, but it shows that the consistency of Zermelo set theory can be proved with a theory which is not very different from Zermelo theory itself, only a little more powerful.
The axiom of separation
Zermelo comments that Axiom III of his system is the one responsible for eliminating the antinomies. It differs from the original definition by Cantor, as follows.
Sets cannot be independently defined by any arbitrary logically definable notion. They must be constructed in some way from previously constructed sets. For example, they can be constructed by taking powersets, or they can be ''separated'' as subsets of sets already "given". This, he says, eliminates contradictory ideas like "the set of all sets" or "the set of all ordinal numbers".
He disposes of the
Russell paradox by means of this Theorem: "Every set
possesses at least one subset
that is not an element of
". Let
be the subset of
which, by AXIOM III, is separated out by the notion "
". Then
cannot be in
. For
# If
is in
, then
contains an element ''x'' for which ''x'' is in ''x'' (i.e.
itself), which would contradict the definition of
.
# If
is not in
, and assuming
is an element of ''M'', then
is an element of ''M'' that satisfies the definition "
", and so is in
which is a contradiction.
Therefore, the assumption that
is in
is wrong, proving the theorem. Hence not all objects of the universal domain ''B'' can be elements of one and the same set. "This disposes of the Russell
antinomy
In philosophy, an antinomy (Ancient Greek: 'against' + 'law') is a real or apparent contradiction between two conclusions, both of which seem justified. It is a term used in logic and epistemology, particularly in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant. ...
as far as we are concerned".
This left the problem of "the domain ''B''" which seems to refer to something. This led to the idea of a
proper class
Proper may refer to:
Mathematics
* Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact
* Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
.
Cantor's theorem
Zermelo's paper may be the first to mention the name "
Cantor's theorem
In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself.
For finite s ...
".
Cantor's theorem: "If ''M'' is an arbitrary set, then always ''M'' < P(''M'')
he power set of ''M'' Every set is of lower cardinality than the set of its subsets".
Zermelo proves this by considering a function φ: ''M'' → P(''M''). By Axiom III this defines the following set ''M' '':
:''M' '' = .
But no element ''m' '' of ''M '' could correspond to ''M' '', i.e. such that φ(''m' '') = ''M' ''. Otherwise we can construct a contradiction:
# If ''m' '' is in ''M' '' then by definition ''m' '' ∉ φ(''m' '') = ''M' '', which is the first part of the contradiction
# If ''m' '' is not in ''M' '' but in ''M '' then by definition ''m' '' ∉ ''M' '' = φ(''m' '') which by definition implies that ''m' '' is in ''M' '', which is the second part of the contradiction.
so by contradiction ''m' '' does not exist. Note the close resemblance of this proof to the way Zermelo disposes of Russell's paradox.
See also
*
S (set theory)
S is an axiomatic set theory set out by George Boolos in his 1989 article, "Iteration Again". S, a first-order theory, is two-sorted because its ontology includes "stages" as well as sets. Boolos designed S to embody his understanding of the " ...
References
Works cited
* .
General references
*.
*. English translation: .
{{Set theory
Systems of set theory