HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, specifically order theory, a well-quasi-ordering or wqo is a quasi-ordering such that any infinite sequence of elements x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots from X contains an increasing pair x_i \leq x_j with i < j.


Motivation

Well-founded induction can be used on any set with a well-founded relation, thus one is interested in when a quasi-order is well-founded. (Here, by abuse of terminology, a quasiorder \le is said to be well-founded if the corresponding strict order x\le y\land y\nleq x is a well-founded relation.) However the class of well-founded quasiorders is not closed under certain operations—that is, when a quasi-order is used to obtain a new quasi-order on a set of structures derived from our original set, this quasiorder is found to be not well-founded. By placing stronger restrictions on the original well-founded quasiordering one can hope to ensure that our derived quasiorderings are still well-founded. An example of this is the power set operation. Given a quasiordering \le for a set X one can define a quasiorder \le^ on X's power set P(X) by setting A \le^ B if and only if for each element of A one can find some element of B that is larger than it with respect to \le. One can show that this quasiordering on P(X) needn't be well-founded, but if one takes the original quasi-ordering to be a well-quasi-ordering, then it is.


Formal definition

A well-quasi-ordering on a set X is a quasi-ordering (i.e., a reflexive, transitive
binary relation In mathematics, a binary relation associates elements of one set, called the ''domain'', with elements of another set, called the ''codomain''. A binary relation over Set (mathematics), sets and is a new set of ordered pairs consisting of ele ...
) such that any infinite sequence of elements x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots from X contains an increasing pair x_i \le x_j with i< j. The set X is said to be well-quasi-ordered, or shortly wqo. A well partial order, or a wpo, is a wqo that is a proper ordering relation, i.e., it is antisymmetric. Among other ways of defining wqo's, one is to say that they are quasi-orderings which do not contain infinite ''strictly decreasing'' sequences (of the form x_0> x_1> x_2> \cdots) nor infinite sequences of ''pairwise incomparable'' elements. Hence a quasi-order (''X'', ≤) is wqo if and only if (''X'', <) is well-founded and has no infinite
antichain In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable. The size of the largest antichain in a partially ordered set is known as its w ...
s.


Examples

* (\N, \le), the set of natural numbers with standard ordering, is a well partial order (in fact, a well-order). However, (\Z, \le), the set of positive and negative integers, is not a well-quasi-order, because it is not well-founded (see Pic.1). * (\N, , ), the set of natural numbers ordered by divisibility, is not a well-quasi-order: the prime numbers are an infinite antichain (see Pic.2). * (\N^k, \le), the set of vectors of k natural numbers (where k is finite) with component-wise ordering, is a well partial order ( Dickson's lemma; see Pic.3). More generally, if (X, \le) is well-quasi-order, then (X^k,\le^k) is also a well-quasi-order for all k. * Let X be an arbitrary finite set with at least two elements. The set X^* of words over X ordered lexicographically (as in a dictionary) is not a well-quasi-order because it contains the infinite decreasing sequence b, ab, aab, aaab, \ldots. Similarly, X^* ordered by the
prefix A prefix is an affix which is placed before the Word stem, stem of a word. Adding it to the beginning of one word changes it into another word. For example, when the prefix ''un-'' is added to the word ''happy'', it creates the word ''unhappy'' ...
relation is not a well-quasi-order, because the previous sequence is an infinite antichain of this partial order. However, X^* ordered by the subsequence relation is a well partial order. (If X has only one element, these three partial orders are identical.) * More generally, (X^*,\le), the set of finite X-sequences ordered by embedding is a well-quasi-order if and only if (X, \le) is a well-quasi-order ( Higman's lemma). Recall that one embeds a sequence u into a sequence v by finding a subsequence of v that has the same length as u and that dominates it term by term. When (X,=) is an unordered set, u\le v if and only if u is a subsequence of v. * (X^\omega,\le), the set of infinite sequences over a well-quasi-order (X, \le), ordered by embedding, is not a well-quasi-order in general. That is, Higman's lemma does not carry over to infinite sequences.
Better-quasi-ordering In order theory a better-quasi-ordering or bqo is a quasi-ordering that does not admit a certain type of bad array. Every better-quasi-ordering is a well-quasi-ordering. Motivation Though ''well-quasi-ordering'' is an appealing notion, many impo ...
s have been introduced to generalize Higman's lemma to sequences of arbitrary lengths. * Embedding between finite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X, \le) is a wqo ( Kruskal's tree theorem). * Embedding between infinite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X, \le) is a wqo ( Nash-Williams' theorem). * Embedding between countable
scattered Scattered may refer to: Music * ''Scattered'' (album), a 2010 album by The Handsome Family * "Scattered" (The Kinks song), 1993 * "Scattered", a song by Ace Young * "Scattered", a song by Lauren Jauregui * "Scattered", a song by Green Day from ' ...
linear order types is a well-quasi-order ( Laver's theorem). * Embedding between countable boolean algebras is a well-quasi-order. This follows from Laver's theorem and a theorem of Ketonen. * Finite graphs ordered by a notion of embedding called " graph minor" is a well-quasi-order ( Robertson–Seymour theorem). * Graphs of finite
tree-depth In graph theory, the tree-depth of a connected undirected graph G is a numerical invariant of G, the minimum height of a Trémaux tree for a supergraph of G. This invariant and its close relatives have gone under many different names in the l ...
ordered by the induced subgraph relation form a well-quasi-order, as do the cographs ordered by induced subgraphs..


Wqo's versus well partial orders

In practice, the wqo's one manipulates are quite often not orderings (see examples above), and the theory is technically smoother if we do not require antisymmetry, so it is built with wqo's as the basic notion. On the other hand, according to Milner 1985, ''no real gain in generality is obtained by considering quasi-orders rather than partial orders... it is simply more convenient to do so.'' Observe that a wpo is a wqo, and that a wqo gives rise to a wpo between equivalence classes induced by the kernel of the wqo. For example, if we order \Z by divisibility, we end up with n\equiv m if and only if n=\pm m, so that (\Z,, )\approx(\N,, ).


Infinite increasing subsequences

If (X, \le) is wqo then every infinite sequence x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots, contains an infinite increasing subsequence x_ \le x_\le x_ \le \cdots (with n_0< n_1< n_2< \cdots). Such a subsequence is sometimes called perfect. This can be proved by a Ramsey argument: given some sequence (x_i)_i, consider the set I of indexes i such that x_i has no larger or equal x_j to its right, i.e., with i. If I is infinite, then the I-extracted subsequence contradicts the assumption that X is wqo. So I is finite, and any x_n with n larger than any index in I can be used as the starting point of an infinite increasing subsequence. The existence of such infinite increasing subsequences is sometimes taken as a definition for well-quasi-ordering, leading to an equivalent notion.


Properties of wqos

* Given a quasiordering (X,\le) the quasiordering (P(X), \le^+) defined by A \le^+ B \iff \forall a \in A, \exists b \in B, a \le b is well-founded if and only if (X,\le) is a wqo. * A quasiordering is a wqo if and only if the corresponding partial order (obtained by quotienting by x \sim y \iff x\le y \land y \le x) has no infinite descending sequences or
antichain In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable. The size of the largest antichain in a partially ordered set is known as its w ...
s. (This can be proved using a Ramsey argument as above.) * Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,\le), any sequence of upward-closed subsets S_0 \subseteq S_1 \subseteq \cdots \subseteq X eventually stabilises (meaning there exists n \in \N such that S_n = S_ = \cdots; a subset S \subseteq X is called ''upward-
closed Closed may refer to: Mathematics * Closure (mathematics), a set, along with operations, for which applying those operations on members always results in a member of the set * Closed set, a set which contains all its limit points * Closed interval, ...
'' if \forall x,y \in X, x \le y \wedge x \in S \Rightarrow y \in S): assuming the contrary \forall i \in \N, \exists j \in \N, j > i, \exists x \in S_j \setminus S_i, a contradiction is reached by extracting an infinite non-ascending subsequence. * Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,\le), any subset S of X has a finite number of minimal elements with respect to \le, for otherwise the minimal elements of S would constitute an infinite antichain.


See also

* * *


Notes

Here ''x'' < ''y'' means: x\le y and y \nleq x.


References

* * * * * * {{Order theory Binary relations Order theory Wellfoundedness