Well-partial-order
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, specifically
order theory Order theory is a branch of mathematics that investigates the intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as "this is less than that" or "this precedes that". This article intr ...
, a well-quasi-ordering or wqo on a set X is a quasi-ordering of X for which every infinite sequence of elements x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots from X contains an increasing pair x_i \leq x_j with i < j.


Motivation

Well-founded induction In mathematics, a binary relation is called well-founded (or wellfounded or foundational) on a set or, more generally, a class if every non-empty subset has a minimal element with respect to ; that is, there exists an such that, for every , ...
can be used on any set with a
well-founded relation In mathematics, a binary relation is called well-founded (or wellfounded or foundational) on a set or, more generally, a class if every non-empty subset has a minimal element with respect to ; that is, there exists an such that, for every , ...
, thus one is interested in when a quasi-order is well-founded. (Here, by abuse of terminology, a quasiorder \le is said to be well-founded if the corresponding strict order x\le y\land y\nleq x is a well-founded relation.) However the class of well-founded quasiorders is not closed under certain operations—that is, when a quasi-order is used to obtain a new quasi-order on a set of structures derived from our original set, this quasiorder is found to be not well-founded. By placing stronger restrictions on the original well-founded quasiordering one can hope to ensure that our derived quasiorderings are still well-founded. An example of this is the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
operation. Given a quasiordering \le for a set X one can define a quasiorder \le^ on X's power set P(X) by setting A \le^ B if and only if for each element of A one can find some element of B that is larger than it with respect to \le. One can show that this quasiordering on P(X) needn't be well-founded, but if one takes the original quasi-ordering to be a well-quasi-ordering, then it is.


Formal definition

A well-quasi-ordering on a set X is a quasi-ordering (i.e., a reflexive, transitive
binary relation In mathematics, a binary relation associates some elements of one Set (mathematics), set called the ''domain'' with some elements of another set called the ''codomain''. Precisely, a binary relation over sets X and Y is a set of ordered pairs ...
) such that any infinite sequence of elements x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots from X contains an increasing pair x_i \le x_j with i< j. The set X is said to be well-quasi-ordered, or shortly wqo. A well partial order, or a wpo, is a wqo that is a proper ordering relation, i.e., it is antisymmetric. Among other ways of defining wqo's, one is to say that they are quasi-orderings which do not contain infinite ''strictly decreasing'' sequences (of the form x_0> x_1> x_2> \cdots) nor infinite sequences of ''pairwise incomparable'' elements. Hence a quasi-order (''X'', ≤) is wqo if and only if (''X'', <) is
well-founded In mathematics, a binary relation is called well-founded (or wellfounded or foundational) on a set (mathematics), set or, more generally, a Class (set theory), class if every non-empty subset has a minimal element with respect to ; that is, t ...
and has no infinite
antichain In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable. The size of the largest antichain in a partially ordered set is known as its wid ...
s.


Ordinal type

Let X be well partially ordered. A (necessarily finite) sequence (x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n) of elements of X that contains no pair x_i \le x_j with i< j is usually called a ''bad sequence''. The ''tree of bad sequences'' T_X is the tree that contains a vertex for each bad sequence, and an edge joining each nonempty bad sequence (x_1, \ldots, x_, x_n) to its parent (x_1, \ldots, x_). The root of T_X corresponds to the empty sequence. Since X contains no infinite bad sequence, the tree T_X contains no infinite path starting at the root. Therefore, each vertex v of T_X has an ordinal height o(v), which is defined by transfinite induction as o(v) = \lim_ (o(w)+1). The ''ordinal type'' of X, denoted o(X), is the ordinal height of the root of T_X. A ''linearization'' of X is an extension of the partial order into a total order. It is easy to verify that o(X) is an upper bound on the ordinal type of every linearization of X. De Jongh and Parikh proved that in fact there always exists a linearization of X that achieves the maximal ordinal type o(X).


Examples

* (\N, \le), the set of natural numbers with standard ordering, is a well partial order (in fact, a
well-order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then calle ...
). However, (\Z, \le), the set of positive and negative integers, is not a well-quasi-order, because it is not well-founded (see Pic.1). * (\N, , ), the set of natural numbers ordered by divisibility, is not a well-quasi-order: the prime numbers are an infinite antichain (see Pic.2). * (\N^k, \le), the set of vectors of k natural numbers (where k is finite) with component-wise ordering, is a well partial order (
Dickson's lemma In mathematics, Dickson's lemma states that every set of n-tuples of natural numbers has finitely many minimal elements. This simple fact from combinatorics has become attributed to the American algebraist L. E. Dickson, who used it to prove a resu ...
; see Pic.3). More generally, if (X, \le) is well-quasi-order, then (X^k,\le^k) is also a well-quasi-order for all k. * Let X be an arbitrary finite set with at least two elements. The set X^* of words over X ordered lexicographically (as in a dictionary) is not a well-quasi-order because it contains the infinite decreasing sequence b, ab, aab, aaab, \ldots. Similarly, X^* ordered by the
prefix A prefix is an affix which is placed before the stem of a word. Particularly in the study of languages, a prefix is also called a preformative, because it alters the form of the word to which it is affixed. Prefixes, like other affixes, can b ...
relation is not a well-quasi-order, because the previous sequence is an infinite antichain of this partial order. However, X^* ordered by the
subsequence In mathematics, a subsequence of a given sequence is a sequence that can be derived from the given sequence by deleting some or no elements without changing the order of the remaining elements. For example, the sequence \langle A,B,D \rangle is a ...
relation is a well partial order. (If X has only one element, these three partial orders are identical.) * More generally, (X^*,\le), the set of finite X-sequences ordered by
embedding In mathematics, an embedding (or imbedding) is one instance of some mathematical structure contained within another instance, such as a group (mathematics), group that is a subgroup. When some object X is said to be embedded in another object Y ...
is a well-quasi-order if and only if (X, \le) is a well-quasi-order ( Higman's lemma). Recall that one embeds a sequence u into a sequence v by finding a subsequence of v that has the same length as u and that dominates it term by term. When (X,=) is an unordered set, u\le v if and only if u is a subsequence of v. * (X^\omega,\le), the set of infinite sequences over a well-quasi-order (X, \le), ordered by embedding, is not a well-quasi-order in general. That is, Higman's lemma does not carry over to infinite sequences.
Better-quasi-ordering In order theory a better-quasi-ordering or bqo is a quasi-ordering that does not admit a certain type of bad array. Every better-quasi-ordering is a well-quasi-ordering. Motivation Though ''well-quasi-ordering'' is an appealing notion, many impo ...
s have been introduced to generalize Higman's lemma to sequences of arbitrary lengths. * Embedding between finite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X, \le) is a wqo ( Kruskal's tree theorem). * Embedding between infinite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X, \le) is a wqo ( Nash-Williams' theorem). * Embedding between countable scattered
linear order In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( ref ...
types is a well-quasi-order ( Laver's theorem). * Embedding between countable boolean algebras is a well-quasi-order. This follows from Laver's theorem and a theorem of Ketonen. * Finite graphs ordered by a notion of embedding called "
graph minor In graph theory, an undirected graph is called a minor of the graph if can be formed from by deleting edges, vertices and by contracting edges. The theory of graph minors began with Wagner's theorem that a graph is planar if and only if ...
" is a well-quasi-order (
Robertson–Seymour theorem In graph theory, the Robertson–Seymour theorem (also called the graph minors theorem) states that the undirected graphs, partially ordered by the graph minor relationship, form a well-quasi-ordering. Equivalently, every family of graphs that is ...
). * Graphs of finite tree-depth ordered by the
induced subgraph In graph theory, an induced subgraph of a graph is another graph, formed from a subset of the vertices of the graph and ''all'' of the edges, from the original graph, connecting pairs of vertices in that subset. Definition Formally, let G=(V,E) ...
relation form a well-quasi-order, as do the
cograph In graph theory, a cograph, or complement-reducible graph, or ''P''4-free graph, is a graph that can be generated from the single-vertex graph ''K''1 by complementation and disjoint union. That is, the family of cographs is the smallest class of ...
s ordered by induced subgraphs.


Constructing new wpo's from given ones

Let X_1 and X_2 be two disjoint wpo sets. Let Y=X_1\cup X_2, and define a partial order on Y by letting y_1\le_Y y_2 if and only if y_1,y_2\in X_i for the same i\in\ and y_1 \le_ y_2. Then Y is wpo, and o(Y) = o(X_1) \oplus o(X_2), where \oplus denotes natural sum of ordinals. Given wpo sets X_1 and X_2, define a partial order on the Cartesian product Y=X_1\times X_2, by letting (a_1,a_2)\le_Y (b_1,b_2) if and only if a_1\le_ b_1 and a_2\le_ b_2. Then Y is wpo (this is a generalization of
Dickson's lemma In mathematics, Dickson's lemma states that every set of n-tuples of natural numbers has finitely many minimal elements. This simple fact from combinatorics has become attributed to the American algebraist L. E. Dickson, who used it to prove a resu ...
), and o(Y) = o(X_1)\otimes o(X_2), where \otimes denotes
natural product A natural product is a natural compound or substance produced by a living organism—that is, found in nature. In the broadest sense, natural products include any substance produced by life. Natural products can also be prepared by chemical s ...
of ordinals. Given a wpo set X, let X^* be the set of finite sequences of elements of X, partially ordered by the subsequence relation. Meaning, let (x_1,\ldots,x_n)\le_ (y_1,\ldots,y_m) if and only if there exist indices 1\le i_1<\cdots such that x_j \le_X y_ for each 1\le j\le n. By Higman's lemma, X^* is wpo. The ordinal type of X^* is Republished in: o(X^*)=\begin\omega^,&o(X) \text;\\ \omega^,&o(X)=\varepsilon_\alpha+n \text\alpha\textn;\\ \omega^,&\text.\end Given a wpo set X, let T(X) be the set of all finite rooted trees whose vertices are labeled by elements of X. Partially order T(X) by the tree embedding relation. By Kruskal's tree theorem, T(X) is wpo. This result is nontrivial even for the case , X, =1 (which corresponds to unlabeled trees), in which case o(T(X)) equals the small Veblen ordinal. In general, for o(X) countable, we have the upper bound o(T(X))\le\vartheta(\Omega^\omega o(X)) in terms of the \vartheta
ordinal collapsing function In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining (Ordinal notation, notations for) certain Recursive ordinal, recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give n ...
. (The small Veblen ordinal equals \vartheta(\Omega^\omega) in this ordinal notation.)


Wqo's versus well partial orders

In practice, the wqo's one manipulates are quite often not orderings (see examples above), and the theory is technically smoother if we do not require antisymmetry, so it is built with wqo's as the basic notion. On the other hand, according to Milner 1985, ''no real gain in generality is obtained by considering quasi-orders rather than partial orders... it is simply more convenient to do so.'' Observe that a wpo is a wqo, and that a wqo gives rise to a wpo between equivalence classes induced by the kernel of the wqo. For example, if we order \Z by divisibility, we end up with n\equiv m if and only if n=\pm m, so that (\Z,, )\approx(\N,, ).


Infinite increasing subsequences

If (X, \le) is wqo then every infinite sequence x_0, x_1, x_2, \ldots, contains an infinite increasing subsequence x_ \le x_\le x_ \le \cdots (with n_0< n_1< n_2< \cdots). Such a subsequence is sometimes called perfect. This can be proved by a Ramsey argument: given some sequence (x_i)_i, consider the set I of indexes i such that x_i has no larger or equal x_j to its right, i.e., with i. If I is infinite, then the I-extracted subsequence contradicts the assumption that X is wqo. So I is finite, and any x_n with n larger than any index in I can be used as the starting point of an infinite increasing subsequence. The existence of such infinite increasing subsequences is sometimes taken as a definition for well-quasi-ordering, leading to an equivalent notion.


Properties of wqos

* Given a quasiordering (X,\le) the quasiordering (P(X), \le^+) defined by A \le^+ B \iff \forall a \in A, \exists b \in B, a \le b is well-founded if and only if (X,\le) is a wqo. * A quasiordering is a wqo if and only if the corresponding partial order (obtained by quotienting by x \sim y \iff x\le y \land y \le x) has no infinite descending sequences or
antichain In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable. The size of the largest antichain in a partially ordered set is known as its wid ...
s. (This can be proved using a Ramsey argument as above.) * Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,\le), any sequence of upward-closed subsets S_0 \subseteq S_1 \subseteq \cdots \subseteq X eventually stabilises (meaning there exists n \in \N such that S_n = S_ = \cdots; a subset S \subseteq X is called ''upward- closed'' if \forall x,y \in X, x \le y \wedge x \in S \Rightarrow y \in S): assuming the contrary \forall i \in \N, \exists j \in \N, j > i, \exists x \in S_j \setminus S_i, a contradiction is reached by extracting an infinite non-ascending subsequence. * Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,\le), any subset S of X has a finite number of minimal elements with respect to \le, for otherwise the minimal elements of S would constitute an infinite antichain.


See also

* * *


Notes

Here ''x'' < ''y'' means: x\le y and x \neq y.


References

* * * * * * {{Order theory Order theory Wellfoundedness