Veblen Function
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous
strictly increasing In mathematical writing, the term strict refers to the property of excluding equality and equivalence and often occurs in the context of inequality and monotonic functions. It is often attached to a technical term to indicate that the exclusiv ...
functions from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by Oswald Veblen in . If ''φ''0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal ''α'', ''φ''''α'' is the function enumerating the common fixed points of ''φ''''β'' for ''β''<''α''. These functions are all normal.


Veblen hierarchy

In the special case when ''φ''0(''α'')=ω''α'' this family of functions is known as the Veblen hierarchy. The function ''φ''1 is the same as the ε function: ''φ''1(''α'')= ε''α''. If \alpha < \beta \,, then \varphi_(\varphi_(\gamma)) = \varphi_(\gamma).M. Rathjen
Ordinal notations based on a weakly Mahlo cardinal
(1990, p.251). Accessed 16 August 2022.
From this and the fact that φ''β'' is strictly increasing we get the ordering: \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) if and only if either (\alpha = \gamma and \beta < \delta ) or (\alpha < \gamma and \beta < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) ) or (\alpha > \gamma and \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \delta ).


Fundamental sequences for the Veblen hierarchy

The fundamental sequence for an ordinal with cofinality ω is a distinguished strictly increasing ω-sequence that has the ordinal as its limit. If one has fundamental sequences for ''α'' and all smaller limit ordinals, then one can create an explicit constructive bijection between ω and ''α'', (i.e. one not using the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
). Here we will describe fundamental sequences for the Veblen hierarchy of ordinals. The image of ''n'' under the fundamental sequence for ''α'' will be indicated by ''α'' 'n'' A variation of Cantor normal form used in connection with the Veblen hierarchy is: every nonzero ordinal number ''α'' can be uniquely written as \alpha = \varphi_(\gamma_1) + \varphi_(\gamma_2) + \cdots + \varphi_(\gamma_k), where ''k''>0 is a natural number and each term after the first is less than or equal to the previous term, \varphi_(\gamma_m) \geq \varphi_(\gamma_) \,, and each \gamma_m < \varphi_(\gamma_m). If a fundamental sequence can be provided for the last term, then that term can be replaced by such a sequence to get \alpha = \varphi_(\gamma_1) + \cdots + \varphi_(\gamma_) + (\varphi_(\gamma_k) \,. For any ''β'', if ''γ'' is a limit with \gamma < \varphi_ (\gamma) \,, then let \varphi_(\gamma) = \varphi_(\gamma \,. No such sequence can be provided for \varphi_0(0) = ω0 = 1 because it does not have cofinality ω. For \varphi_0(\gamma+1) = \omega ^ = \omega^ \gamma \cdot \omega \,, we choose \varphi_0(\gamma+1) = \varphi_0(\gamma) \cdot n = \omega^ \cdot n \,. For \varphi_(0) \,, we use \varphi_(0) = 0 and \varphi_(0) +1= \varphi_(\varphi_(0) \,, i.e. 0, \varphi_(0), \varphi_(\varphi_(0)), etc.. For \varphi_(\gamma+1), we use \varphi_(\gamma+1) = \varphi_(\gamma)+1 and \varphi_(\gamma+1) +1= \varphi_ (\varphi_(\gamma+1) \,. Now suppose that ''β'' is a limit: If \beta < \varphi_(0), then let \varphi_(0) = \varphi_(0) \,. For \varphi_(\gamma+1), use \varphi_(\gamma+1) = \varphi_(\varphi_(\gamma)+1) \,. Otherwise, the ordinal cannot be described in terms of smaller ordinals using \varphi and this scheme does not apply to it.


The Γ function

The function Γ enumerates the ordinals ''α'' such that φ''α''(0) = ''α''. Γ0 is the Feferman–Schütte ordinal, i.e. it is the smallest ''α'' such that ''φ''''α''(0) = ''α''. For Γ0, a fundamental sequence could be chosen to be \Gamma_0 = 0 and \Gamma_0 +1= \varphi_ (0) \,. For Γβ+1, let \Gamma_ = \Gamma_ + 1 and \Gamma_ +1= \varphi_ (0) \,. For Γ''β'' where \beta < \Gamma_ is a limit, let \Gamma_ = \Gamma_ \,.


Generalizations


Finitely many variables

To build the Veblen function of a finite number of arguments (finitary Veblen function), let the binary function \varphi(\alpha, \gamma) be \varphi_\alpha(\gamma) as defined above. Let z be an empty string or a string consisting of one or more comma-separated zeros 0,0,...,0 and s be an empty string or a string consisting of one or more comma-separated ordinals \alpha _,\alpha _,...,\alpha _ with \alpha _>0. The binary function \varphi (\beta ,\gamma ) can be written as \varphi (s,\beta ,z,\gamma ) where both s and z are empty strings. The finitary Veblen functions are defined as follows: * \varphi (\gamma )=\omega ^ * \varphi (z,s,\gamma )=\varphi (s,\gamma ) * if \beta >0, then \varphi (s,\beta ,z,\gamma ) denotes the (1+\gamma )-th common fixed point of the functions \xi \mapsto \varphi (s,\delta ,\xi ,z) for each \delta <\beta For example, \varphi(1,0,\gamma) is the (1+\gamma)-th fixed point of the functions \xi\mapsto\varphi(\xi,0), namely \Gamma_\gamma; then \varphi(1,1,\gamma) enumerates the fixed points of that function, i.e., of the \xi\mapsto\Gamma_\xi function; and \varphi(2,0,\gamma) enumerates the fixed points of all the \xi\mapsto\varphi(1,\xi,0). Each instance of the generalized Veblen functions is continuous in the ''last nonzero'' variable (i.e., if one variable is made to vary and all later variables are kept constantly equal to zero). The ordinal \varphi(1,0,0,0) is sometimes known as the Ackermann ordinal. The limit of the \varphi(1,0,...,0) where the number of zeroes ranges over ω, is sometimes known as the "small" Veblen ordinal. Every non-zero ordinal \alpha less than the small Veblen ordinal (SVO) can be uniquely written in normal form for the finitary Veblen function: \alpha =\varphi (s_)+\varphi (s_)+\cdots +\varphi (s_) where * k is a positive integer * \varphi (s_)\geq \varphi (s_)\geq \cdots \geq \varphi (s_) * s_ is a string consisting of one or more comma-separated ordinals \alpha _,\alpha _,...,\alpha _ where \alpha _>0 and each \alpha _<\varphi (s_)


Fundamental sequences for limit ordinals of finitary Veblen function

For limit ordinals \alpha, written in normal form for the finitary Veblen function: * (\varphi(s_1)+\varphi(s_2)+\cdots+\varphi(s_k)) \varphi(s_1)+\varphi(s_2)+\cdots+\varphi(s_k) /math>, * \varphi(\gamma) \left\{\begin{array}{lcr} n \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma=1\\ \varphi(\gamma-1)\cdot n \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma \quad \text{is a successor ordinal}\\ \varphi(\gamma \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma \quad \text{is a limit ordinal}\\ \end{array}\right. , * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) 0 and \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) +1\varphi(s,\beta-1,\varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) z) if \gamma=0 and \beta is a successor ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma-1)+1 and \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) +1\varphi(s,\beta-1,\varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) z) if \gamma and \beta are successor ordinals, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma if \gamma is a limit ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta z,\gamma) if \gamma=0 and \beta is a limit ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma-1)+1,z) if \gamma is a successor ordinal and \beta is a limit ordinal.


Transfinitely many variables

More generally, Veblen showed that φ can be defined even for a transfinite sequence of ordinals αβ, provided that all but a finite number of them are zero. Notice that if such a sequence of ordinals is chosen from those less than an uncountable regular cardinal κ, then the sequence may be encoded as a single ordinal less than κκ (ordinal exponentiation). So one is defining a function φ from κκ into κ. The definition can be given as follows: let α be a transfinite sequence of ordinals (i.e., an ordinal function with finite support) ''that ends in zero'' (i.e., such that α0=0), and let α ³@0denote the same function where the final 0 has been replaced by γ. Then γ↦φ(α ³@0 is defined as the function enumerating the common fixed points of all functions ξ↦φ(β) where β ranges over all sequences that are obtained by decreasing the smallest-indexed nonzero value of α and replacing some smaller-indexed value with the indeterminate ξ (i.e., β=α ¶@ι0,ξ@ιmeaning that for the smallest index ι0 such that αι0 is nonzero the latter has been replaced by some value ζ<αι0 and that for some smaller index ι<ι0, the value αι=0 has been replaced with ξ). For example, if α=(1@ω) denotes the transfinite sequence with value 1 at ω and 0 everywhere else, then φ(1@ω) is the smallest fixed point of all the functions ξ↦φ(ξ,0,...,0) with finitely many final zeroes (it is also the limit of the φ(1,0,...,0) with finitely many zeroes, the small Veblen ordinal). The smallest ordinal ''α'' such that ''α'' is greater than ''φ'' applied to any function with support in ''α'' (i.e., that cannot be reached "from below" using the Veblen function of transfinitely many variables) is sometimes known as the "large" Veblen ordinal, or "great" Veblen number.


Further extensions

In , the Veblen function was extended further to a somewhat technical system known as ''dimensional Veblen''. In this, one may take fixed points or row numbers, meaning expressions such as ''φ''(1@(1,0)) are valid (representing the large Veblen ordinal), visualised as multi-dimensional arrays. It was proven that all ordinals below the Bachmann–Howard ordinal could be represented in this system, and that the representations for all ordinals below the large Veblen ordinal were aesthetically the same as in the original system.


Values

The function takes on several prominent values: * \varphi(1,0) = \varepsilon_0 is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Peano arithmetic and the limit of what ordinals can be represented in terms of Cantor normal form and smaller ordinals. * \varphi(\omega,0), a bound on the order types of the recursive path orderings with finitely many function symbols, and the smallest ordinal closed under primitive recursive ordinal functions. * The Feferman–Schütte ordinal \Gamma_0 is equal to \varphi(1,0,0). * The small Veblen ordinal is equal to \varphi\begin{pmatrix}1 \\ \omega\end{pmatrix}.


References

* Hilbert Levitz,
Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated
', expository article (8 pages, in
PostScript PostScript (PS) is a page description language and dynamically typed, stack-based programming language. It is most commonly used in the electronic publishing and desktop publishing realm, but as a Turing complete programming language, it c ...
) * * * * contains an informal description of the Veblen hierarchy. * * *


Citations

{{Reflist Ordinal numbers Proof theory Hierarchy of functions