HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any", "for all", "for every", or "given an arbitrary element". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other words, it is the predication of a
property Property is a system of rights that gives people legal control of valuable things, and also refers to the valuable things themselves. Depending on the nature of the property, an owner of property may have the right to consume, alter, share, re ...
or relation to every member of the domain. It asserts that a predicate within the scope of a universal quantifier is true of every value of a predicate variable. It is usually denoted by the turned A (∀) logical operator
symbol A symbol is a mark, Sign (semiotics), sign, or word that indicates, signifies, or is understood as representing an idea, physical object, object, or wikt:relationship, relationship. Symbols allow people to go beyond what is known or seen by cr ...
, which, when used together with a predicate variable, is called a universal quantifier ("", "", or sometimes by "" alone). Universal quantification is distinct from ''existential'' quantification ("there exists"), which only asserts that the property or relation holds for at least one member of the domain. Quantification in general is covered in the article on
quantification (logic) In logic, a quantifier is an operator that specifies how many individuals in the domain of discourse satisfy an open formula. For instance, the universal quantifier \forall in the first-order formula \forall x P(x) expresses that everythi ...
. The universal quantifier is encoded as in
Unicode Unicode or ''The Unicode Standard'' or TUS is a character encoding standard maintained by the Unicode Consortium designed to support the use of text in all of the world's writing systems that can be digitized. Version 16.0 defines 154,998 Char ...
, and as \forall in
LaTeX Latex is an emulsion (stable dispersion) of polymer microparticles in water. Latices are found in nature, but synthetic latices are common as well. In nature, latex is found as a wikt:milky, milky fluid, which is present in 10% of all floweri ...
and related formula editors.


Basics

Suppose it is given that
2·0 = 0 + 0, and 2·1 = 1 + 1, and , ..., and 2 · 100 = 100 + 100, and ..., etc.
This would seem to be an infinite
logical conjunction In logic, mathematics and linguistics, ''and'' (\wedge) is the Truth function, truth-functional operator of conjunction or logical conjunction. The logical connective of this operator is typically represented as \wedge or \& or K (prefix) or ...
because of the repeated use of "and". However, the "etc." cannot be interpreted as a conjunction in
formal logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, Instead, the statement must be rephrased:
For all natural numbers ''n'', one has 2·''n'' = ''n'' + ''n''.
This is a single statement using universal quantification. This statement can be said to be more precise than the original one. While the "etc." informally includes
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, and nothing more, this was not rigorously given. In the universal quantification, on the other hand, the natural numbers are mentioned explicitly. This particular example is true, because any natural number could be substituted for ''n'' and the statement "2·''n'' = ''n'' + ''n''" would be true. In contrast,
For all natural numbers ''n'', one has 2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''
is false, because if ''n'' is substituted with, for instance, 1, the statement "2·1 > 2 + 1" is false. It is immaterial that "2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''" is true for ''most'' natural numbers ''n'': even the existence of a single counterexample is enough to prove the universal quantification false. On the other hand, for all
composite number A composite number is a positive integer that can be formed by multiplying two smaller positive integers. Accordingly it is a positive integer that has at least one divisor other than 1 and itself. Every positive integer is composite, prime numb ...
s ''n'', one has 2·''n'' > 2 + ''n'' is true, because none of the counterexamples are composite numbers. This indicates the importance of the '' domain of discourse'', which specifies which values ''n'' can take.Further information on using domains of discourse with quantified statements can be found in the
Quantification (logic) In logic, a quantifier is an operator that specifies how many individuals in the domain of discourse satisfy an open formula. For instance, the universal quantifier \forall in the first-order formula \forall x P(x) expresses that everythi ...
article.
In particular, note that if the domain of discourse is restricted to consist only of those objects that satisfy a certain predicate, then for universal quantification this requires a
logical conditional Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure of ...
. For example,
For all composite numbers ''n'', one has 2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''
is logically equivalent to
For all natural numbers ''n'', if ''n'' is composite, then 2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''.
Here the "if ... then" construction indicates the logical conditional.


Notation

In
symbolic logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, the universal quantifier symbol \forall (a turned " A" in a
sans-serif In typography and lettering, a sans-serif, sans serif (), gothic, or simply sans letterform is one that does not have extending features called "serifs" at the end of strokes. Sans-serif typefaces tend to have less stroke width variation than ...
font, Unicode U+2200) is used to indicate universal quantification. It was first used in this way by Gerhard Gentzen in 1935, by analogy with
Giuseppe Peano Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much Mathematical notati ...
's \exists (turned E) notation for
existential quantification Existentialism is a family of philosophy, philosophical views and inquiry that explore the human individual's struggle to lead an Authenticity (philosophy), authentic life despite the apparent Absurdity#The Absurd, absurdity or incomprehensibili ...
and the later use of Peano's notation by
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
. For example, if ''P''(''n'') is the predicate "2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''" and N is the set of natural numbers, then : \forall n\!\in\!\mathbb\; P(n) is the (false) statement :"for all natural numbers ''n'', one has 2·''n'' > 2 + ''n''". Similarly, if ''Q''(''n'') is the predicate "''n'' is composite", then : \forall n\!\in\!\mathbb\; \bigl( Q(n) \rightarrow P(n) \bigr) is the (true) statement :"for all natural numbers ''n'', if ''n'' is composite, then ". Several variations in the notation for quantification (which apply to all forms) can be found in the '' Quantifier'' article.


Properties


Negation

The negation of a universally quantified function is obtained by changing the universal quantifier into an existential quantifier and negating the quantified formula. That is, :\lnot \forall x\; P(x)\quad\text \quad \exists x\;\lnot P(x) where \lnot denotes
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
. For example, if is the propositional function " is married", then, for the set of all living human beings, the universal quantification
Given any living person , that person is married
is written :\forall x \in X\, P(x) This statement is false. Truthfully, it is stated that
It is not the case that, given any living person , that person is married
or, symbolically: :\lnot\ \forall x \in X\, P(x). If the function is not true for ''every'' element of , then there must be at least one element for which the statement is false. That is, the negation of \forall x \in X\, P(x) is logically equivalent to "There exists a living person who is not married", or: :\exists x \in X\, \lnot P(x) It is erroneous to confuse "all persons are not married" (i.e. "there exists no person who is married") with "not all persons are married" (i.e. "there exists a person who is not married"): :\lnot\ \exists x \in X\, P(x) \equiv\ \forall x \in X\, \lnot P(x) \not\equiv\ \lnot\ \forall x\in X\, P(x) \equiv\ \exists x \in X\, \lnot P(x)


Other connectives

The universal (and existential) quantifier moves unchanged across the
logical connective In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the ...
s , , , and , as long as the other operand is not affected; that is: :\begin P(x) \land (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \land Q(y)) \\ P(x) \lor (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \lor Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \to (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \to Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \nleftarrow (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \nleftarrow Q(y)) \\ P(x) \land (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \land Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \lor (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \lor Q(y)) \\ P(x) \to (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \to Q(y)) \\ P(x) \nleftarrow (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) &\equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \nleftarrow Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \end Conversely, for the logical connectives , , , and , the quantifiers flip: :\begin P(x) \uparrow (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \uparrow Q(y)) \\ P(x) \downarrow (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \downarrow Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \nrightarrow (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \nrightarrow Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \gets (\exists\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \forall\mathbf\, (P(x) \gets Q(y)) \\ P(x) \uparrow (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \uparrow Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ P(x) \downarrow (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \downarrow Q(y)) \\ P(x) \nrightarrow (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \nrightarrow Q(y)) \\ P(x) \gets (\forall\mathbf\, Q(y)) & \equiv\ \exists\mathbf\, (P(x) \gets Q(y)),& \text \mathbf\neq \emptyset \\ \end


Rules of inference

A
rule of inference Rules of inference are ways of deriving conclusions from premises. They are integral parts of formal logic, serving as norms of the Logical form, logical structure of Validity (logic), valid arguments. If an argument with true premises follows a ...
is a rule justifying a logical step from hypothesis to conclusion. There are several rules of inference which utilize the universal quantifier. '' Universal instantiation'' concludes that, if the propositional function is known to be universally true, then it must be true for any arbitrary element of the universe of discourse. Symbolically, this is represented as : \forall\mathbf\, P(x) \to P(c) where ''c'' is a completely arbitrary element of the universe of discourse. '' Universal generalization'' concludes the propositional function must be universally true if it is true for any arbitrary element of the universe of discourse. Symbolically, for an arbitrary ''c'', : P(c) \to\ \forall\mathbf\, P(x). The element ''c'' must be completely arbitrary; else, the logic does not follow: if ''c'' is not arbitrary, and is instead a specific element of the universe of discourse, then P(''c'') only implies an existential quantification of the propositional function.


The empty set

By convention, the formula \forall\emptyset \, P(x) is always true, regardless of the formula ''P''(''x''); see
vacuous truth In mathematics and logic, a vacuous truth is a conditional or universal statement (a universal statement that can be converted to a conditional statement) that is true because the antecedent cannot be satisfied. It is sometimes said that a s ...
.


Universal closure

The universal closure of a formula φ is the formula with no free variables obtained by adding a universal quantifier for every free variable in φ. For example, the universal closure of :P(y) \land \exists x Q(x,z) is :\forall y \forall z ( P(y) \land \exists x Q(x,z)).


As adjoint

In
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
and the theory of elementary topoi, the universal quantifier can be understood as the right adjoint of a
functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a Map (mathematics), mapping between Category (mathematics), categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) ar ...
between
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
s, the inverse image functor of a function between sets; likewise, the existential quantifier is the left adjoint. Saunders Mac Lane, Ieke Moerdijk, (1992) ''Sheaves in Geometry and Logic'' Springer-Verlag. ''See page 58'' For a set X, let \mathcalX denote its
powerset In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
. For any function f:X\to Y between sets X and Y, there is an inverse image functor f^*:\mathcalY\to \mathcalX between powersets, that takes subsets of the codomain of ''f'' back to subsets of its domain. The left adjoint of this functor is the existential quantifier \exists_f and the right adjoint is the universal quantifier \forall_f. That is, \exists_f\colon \mathcalX\to \mathcalY is a functor that, for each subset S \subset X, gives the subset \exists_f S \subset Y given by :\exists_f S =\, those y in the image of S under f. Similarly, the universal quantifier \forall_f\colon \mathcalX\to \mathcalY is a functor that, for each subset S \subset X, gives the subset \forall_f S \subset Y given by :\forall_f S =\, those y whose preimage under f is contained in S. The more familiar form of the quantifiers as used in first-order logic is obtained by taking the function ''f'' to be the unique function !:X \to 1 so that \mathcal(1) = \ is the two-element set holding the values true and false, a subset ''S'' is that subset for which the predicate S(x) holds, and :\begin\mathcal(!)\colon \mathcal(1) & \to \mathcal(X)\\ T &\mapsto X \\ F &\mapsto \\end :\exists_! S = \exists x. S(x), which is true if S is not empty, and :\forall_! S = \forall x. S(x), which is false if S is not X. The universal and existential quantifiers given above generalize to the presheaf category.


See also

*
Existential quantification Existentialism is a family of philosophy, philosophical views and inquiry that explore the human individual's struggle to lead an Authenticity (philosophy), authentic life despite the apparent Absurdity#The Absurd, absurdity or incomprehensibili ...
* First-order logic *
List of logic symbols In logic, a set of symbols is commonly used to express logical representation. The following table lists many common symbols, together with their name, how they should be read out loud, and the related field of mathematics. Additionally, the sub ...
—for the Unicode symbol ∀


Notes


References

* * (ch. 2)


External links

* {{Mathematical logic Logic symbols Logical expressions Quantifier (logic)