
In the
mathematical
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
field of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, an ultrafilter on a
set is a ''maximal filter'' on the set
In other words, it is a collection of subsets of
that satisfies the definition of a
filter on
and that is maximal with respect to inclusion, in the sense that there does not exist a strictly larger collection of subsets of
that is also a filter. (In the above, by definition a filter on a set does not contain the empty set.) Equivalently, an ultrafilter on the set
can also be characterized as a filter on
with the property that for every
subset
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
of
either
or its complement
belongs to the ultrafilter.
Ultrafilters on sets are an important special instance of
ultrafilters on partially ordered sets, where the
partially ordered set
In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
consists of the
power set and the partial order is
subset inclusion This article deals specifically with ultrafilters on a set and does not cover the more general notion.
There are two types of ultrafilter on a set. A principal ultrafilter on
is the collection of all subsets of
that contain a fixed element
. The ultrafilters that are not principal are the free ultrafilters. The existence of free ultrafilters on any infinite set is implied by the
ultrafilter lemma, which can be proven in
ZFC. On the other hand, there exists models of
ZF where every ultrafilter on a set is principal.
Ultrafilters have many applications in set theory,
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
, and
topology
Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
.
Usually, only free ultrafilters lead to non-trivial constructions. For example, an
ultraproduct modulo a principal ultrafilter is always isomorphic to one of the factors, while an ultraproduct modulo a free ultrafilter usually has a more complex structure.
Definitions
Given an arbitrary set
an ultrafilter on
is a non-empty
family
Family (from ) is a Social group, group of people related either by consanguinity (by recognized birth) or Affinity (law), affinity (by marriage or other relationship). It forms the basis for social order. Ideally, families offer predictabili ...
of subsets of
such that:
# or : The empty set is not an element of
#: If
and if
is any superset of
(that is, if
) then
#: If
and
are elements of
then so is their
intersection
In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their ...
#If
then either
or its complement
is an element of
[Properties 1 and 3 imply that and cannot be elements of ]
Properties (1), (2), and (3) are the defining properties of a Some authors do not include non-degeneracy (which is property (1) above) in their definition of "filter". However, the definition of "ultrafilter" (and also of "prefilter" and "filter subbase") always includes non-degeneracy as a defining condition. This article requires that all filters be proper although a filter might be described as "proper" for emphasis.
A filter base is a non-empty family of sets that has the
finite intersection property (i.e. all finite intersections are non-empty). Equivalently, a filter subbase is a non-empty family of sets that is contained in (proper) filter. The smallest (relative to
) filter containing a given filter subbase is said to be generated by the filter subbase.
The upward closure in
of a family of sets
is the set
:
A or is a non-empty and proper (i.e.
) family of sets
that is downward directed, which means that if
then there exists some
such that
Equivalently, a prefilter is any family of sets
whose upward closure
is a filter, in which case this filter is called the filter generated by
and
is said to be a filter base
The dual in
of a family of sets
is the set
For example, the dual of the
power set is itself:
A family of sets is a proper filter on
if and only if its dual is a proper
ideal on
("" means not equal to the power set).
Generalization to ultra prefilters
A family
of subsets of
is called if
and any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
- For every set there exists some set such that or (or equivalently, such that equals or ).
- For every set there exists some set such that equals or
* Here, is defined to be the union of all sets in
* This characterization of " is ultra" does not depend on the set so mentioning the set is optional when using the term "ultra."
- For set (not necessarily even a subset of ) there exists some set such that equals or
* If satisfies this condition then so does superset In particular, a set is ultra if and only if and contains as a subset some ultra family of sets.
A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter.
[Suppose is filter subbase that is ultra. Let and define Because is ultra, there exists some such that equals or The finite intersection property implies that so necessarily which is equivalent to ]
The ultra property can now be used to define both ultrafilters and ultra prefilters:
:An is a prefilter that is ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra.
:An on
is a (proper) filter on
that is ultra. Equivalently, it is any filter on
that is generated by an ultra prefilter.
Ultra prefilters as maximal prefilters
To characterize ultra prefilters in terms of "maximality," the following relation is needed.
:Given two families of sets
and
the family
is said to be coarser than
and
is finer than and subordinate to
written
or , if for every
there is some
such that
The families
and
are called equivalent if
and
The families
and
are comparable if one of these sets is finer than the other.
The subordination relationship, i.e.
is a
preorder so the above definition of "equivalent" does form an
equivalence relation.
If
then
but the converse does not hold in general.
However, if
is upward closed, such as a filter, then
if and only if
Every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates. This shows that it is possible for filters to be equivalent to sets that are not filters.
If two families of sets
and
are equivalent then either both
and
are ultra (resp. prefilters, filter subbases) or otherwise neither one of them is ultra (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase).
In particular, if a filter subbase is not also a prefilter, then it is equivalent to the filter or prefilter that it generates. If
and
are both filters on
then
and
are equivalent if and only if
If a proper filter (resp. ultrafilter) is equivalent to a family of sets
then
is necessarily a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter).
Using the following characterization, it is possible to define prefilters (resp. ultra prefilters) using only the concept of filters (resp. ultrafilters) and subordination:
:An arbitrary family of sets is a prefilter if and only it is equivalent to a (proper) filter.
:An arbitrary family of sets is an ultra prefilter if and only it is equivalent to an ultrafilter.
:A on
is a prefilter
that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is ultra.
- is maximal on with respect to meaning that if satisfies then
- There is no prefilter properly subordinate to
- If a (proper) filter on satisfies then
- The filter on generated by is ultra.
Characterizations
There are no ultrafilters on the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
, so it is henceforth assumed that
is nonempty.
A filter base
on
is an ultrafilter on
if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- for any either or
- is a maximal filter subbase on meaning that if is any filter subbase on then implies
A (proper) filter
on
is an ultrafilter on
if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- is ultra;
- is generated by an ultra prefilter;
- For any subset or
* So an ultrafilter decides for every whether is "large" (i.e. ) or "small" (i.e. ).
- For each subset either
[ is in or () is.]
- This condition can be restated as: is partitioned by and its dual
* The sets and are disjoint for all prefilters on
- is an ideal on
- For any finite family of subsets of (where ), if then for some index
* In words, a "large" set cannot be a finite union of sets none of which is large.
- For any if then or
- For any if then or (a filter with this property is called a ).
- For any if and then or
- is a maximal filter; that is, if is a filter on such that then Equivalently, is a maximal filter if there is no filter on that contains as a proper subset (that is, no filter is strictly finer than ).
Grills and filter-grills
If
then its is the family
where
may be written if
is clear from context.
If
is a filter then
is the set of positive sets with respect to
and is usually written as
.
For example,
and if
then
If
then
and moreover, if
is a filter subbase then
The grill
is upward closed in
if and only if
which will henceforth be assumed. Moreover,
so that
is upward closed in
if and only if
The grill of a filter on
is called a For any
is a filter-grill on
if and only if (1)
is upward closed in
and (2) for all sets
and
if
then
or
The grill operation
induces a bijection
:
whose inverse is also given by
If
then
is a filter-grill on
if and only if
or equivalently, if and only if
is an ultrafilter on
That is, a filter on
is a filter-grill if and only if it is ultra. For any non-empty
is both a filter on
and a filter-grill on
if and only if (1)
and (2) for all
the following equivalences hold:
:
if and only if
if and only if
Free or principal
If
is any non-empty family of sets then the
Kernel of
is the intersection of all sets in
A non-empty family of sets
is called:
* if
and otherwise (that is, if
).
* if
* if
and
is a singleton set; in this case, if
then
is said to be principal at
If a family of sets
is fixed then
is ultra if and only if some element of
is a singleton set, in which case
will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter
is ultra if and only if
is a singleton set. A singleton set is ultra if and only if its sole element is also a singleton set.
The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point.
Every filter on
that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition
is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on
other than these. In particular, if a set
has finite cardinality
then there are exactly
ultrafilters on
and those are the ultrafilters generated by each singleton subset of
Consequently, free ultrafilters can only exist on an infinite set.
Examples, properties, and sufficient conditions
If
is an infinite set then there are as many ultrafilters over
as there are families of subsets of
explicitly, if
has infinite cardinality
then the set of ultrafilters over
has the same cardinality as
that cardinality being
If
and
are families of sets such that
is ultra,
and
then
is necessarily ultra.
A filter subbase
that is not a prefilter cannot be ultra; but it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter and filter generated by
to be ultra.
Suppose
is ultra and
is a set.
The trace
is ultra if and only if it does not contain the empty set.
Furthermore, at least one of the sets
and
will be ultra (this result extends to any finite partition of
).
If
are filters on
is an ultrafilter on
and
then there is some
that satisfies
This result is not necessarily true for an infinite family of filters.
The image under a map
of an ultra set
is again ultra and if
is an ultra prefilter then so is
The property of being ultra is preserved under bijections. However, the preimage of an ultrafilter is not necessarily ultra, not even if the map is surjective. For example, if
has more than one point and if the range of
consists of a single point
then
is an ultra prefilter on
but its preimage is not ultra. Alternatively, if
is a principal filter generated by a point in
then the preimage of
contains the empty set and so is not ultra.
The elementary filter induced by an infinite sequence, all of whose points are distinct, is an ultrafilter. If
then
denotes the set consisting all subsets of
having cardinality
and if
contains at least
(
) distinct points, then
is ultra but it is not contained in any prefilter. This example generalizes to any integer
and also to
if
contains more than one element. Ultra sets that are not also prefilters are rarely used.
For every
and every
let
If
is an ultrafilter on
then the set of all
such that
is an ultrafilter on
Monad structure
The
functor
In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a Map (mathematics), mapping between Category (mathematics), categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) ar ...
associating to any set
the set of
of all ultrafilters on
forms a
monad called the . The unit map
sends any element
to the principal ultrafilter given by
This
ultrafilter monad is the
codensity monad of the inclusion of the
category of finite sets into the
category of all sets,
which gives a conceptual explanation of this monad.
Similarly, the
ultraproduct monad is the codensity monad of the inclusion of the category of finite
families of sets into the category of all families of set. So in this sense,
ultraproducts are categorically inevitable.
The ultrafilter lemma
The ultrafilter lemma was first proved by
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
in 1930.
The ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements:
# For every prefilter on a set
there exists a maximal prefilter on
subordinate to it.
# Every proper filter subbase on a set
is contained in some ultrafilter on
A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.
[Let be a filter on that is not an ultrafilter. If is such that then has the finite intersection property (because if then if and only if ) so that by the ultrafilter lemma, there exists some ultrafilter on such that (so in particular ). It follows that ]
The following results can be proven using the ultrafilter lemma.
A free ultrafilter exists on a set
if and only if
is infinite. Every proper filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it. Since there are filters that are not ultra, this shows that the intersection of a family of ultrafilters need not be ultra. A family of sets
can be extended to a free ultrafilter if and only if the intersection of any finite family of elements of
is infinite.
Relationships to other statements under ZF
Throughout this section, ZF refers to
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
and ZFC refers to ZF with the
Axiom of Choice (AC). The ultrafilter lemma is independent of ZF. That is, there exist
models
A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , .
Models can be divided int ...
in which the axioms of ZF hold but the ultrafilter lemma does not. There also exist models of ZF in which every ultrafilter is necessarily principal.
Every filter that contains a singleton set is necessarily an ultrafilter and given
the definition of the discrete ultrafilter
does not require more than ZF.
If
is finite then every ultrafilter is a discrete filter at a point; consequently, free ultrafilters can only exist on infinite sets.
In particular, if
is finite then the ultrafilter lemma can be proven from the axioms ZF.
The existence of free ultrafilter on infinite sets can be proven if the axiom of choice is assumed.
More generally, the ultrafilter lemma can be proven by using the
axiom of choice, which in brief states that any
Cartesian product
In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets and , denoted , is the set of all ordered pairs where is an element of and is an element of . In terms of set-builder notation, that is
A\times B = \.
A table c ...
of non-empty sets is non-empty. Under ZF, the axiom of choice is, in particular,
equivalent to (a)
Zorn's lemma
Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain (that is, every totally ordered subset) necessarily contains at least on ...
, (b)
Tychonoff's theorem, (c) the weak form of the vector basis theorem (which states that every vector space has a
basis), (d) the strong form of the vector basis theorem, and other statements.
However, the ultrafilter lemma is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice.
While free ultrafilters can be proven to exist, it is possible to construct an explicit example of a free ultrafilter (using only ZF and the ultrafilter lemma); that is, free ultrafilters are intangible.
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
proved that under ZFC, the cardinality of the set of all free ultrafilters on an infinite set
is equal to the cardinality of
where
denotes the power set of
Other authors attribute this discovery to Bedřich Pospíšil (following a combinatorial argument from
Fichtenholz, and
Kantorovitch, improved by
Hausdorff).
Under ZF, the
axiom of choice can be used to prove both the ultrafilter lemma and the
Krein–Milman theorem; conversely, under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma together with the Krein–Milman theorem can prove the axiom of choice.
Statements that cannot be deduced
The ultrafilter lemma is a relatively weak axiom. For example, each of the statements in the following list can be deduced from ZF together with the ultrafilter lemma:
- A countable union of
countable set
In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
s is a countable set.
- The axiom of countable choice (ACC).
- The
axiom of dependent choice
In mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. T ...
(ADC).
Equivalent statements
Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements:
- The Boolean prime ideal theorem (BPIT).
- Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras.
- Any product of Boolean spaces is a Boolean space.
- Boolean Prime Ideal Existence Theorem: Every nondegenerate Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.
- Tychonoff's theorem for
Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), T2 space or separated space, is a topological space where distinct points have disjoint neighbourhoods. Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on a topologi ...
s: Any product of compact Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), T2 space or separated space, is a topological space where distinct points have disjoint neighbourhoods. Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on a topologi ...
s is compact.
- If is endowed with the
discrete topology
In topology, a discrete space is a particularly simple example of a topological space or similar structure, one in which the points form a , meaning they are '' isolated'' from each other in a certain sense. The discrete topology is the finest to ...
then for any set the product space is compact.
- Each of the following versions of the Banach-Alaoglu theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
- Any equicontinuous set of scalar-valued maps on a
topological vector space
In mathematics, a topological vector space (also called a linear topological space and commonly abbreviated TVS or t.v.s.) is one of the basic structures investigated in functional analysis.
A topological vector space is a vector space that is als ...
(TVS) is relatively compact in the weak-* topology (that is, it is contained in some weak-* compact set).
- The polar of any neighborhood of the origin in a TVS is a weak-* compact subset of its continuous dual space.
- The closed unit ball in the continuous dual space of any normed space is weak-* compact.
* If the normed space is separable then the ultrafilter lemma is sufficient but not necessary to prove this statement.
- A topological space is compact if every ultrafilter on converges to some limit.
- A topological space is compact if every ultrafilter on converges to some limit.
* The addition of the words "and only if" is the only difference between this statement and the one immediately above it.
- The Alexander subbase theorem.
- The Ultranet lemma: Every net has a universal subnet.
* By definition, a net in is called an or an if for every subset the net is eventually in or in
- A topological space is compact if and only if every ultranet on converges to some limit.
* If the words "and only if" are removed then the resulting statement remains equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma.
- A
convergence space
In mathematics, a convergence space, also called a generalized convergence, is a set together with a relation called a that satisfies certain properties relating elements of ''X'' with the Family of sets, family of Filter (set theory), filters on ...
is compact if every ultrafilter on converges.
- A
uniform space
In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a topological space, set with additional mathematical structure, structure that is used to define ''uniform property, uniform properties'', such as complete space, completeness, uniform con ...
is compact if it is complete and totally bounded.
- The Stone–Čech compactification Theorem.
- Each of the following versions of the compactness theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
- If is a set of first-order sentences such that every finite subset of has a
model
A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , .
Models can be divided in ...
, then has a model.
- If is a set of zero-order sentences such that every finite subset of has a model, then has a model.
- The completeness theorem: If is a set of zero-order sentences that is syntactically consistent, then it has a model (that is, it is semantically consistent).
Weaker statements
Any statement that can be deduced from the ultrafilter lemma (together with ZF) is said to be than the ultrafilter lemma.
A weaker statement is said to be if under ZF, it is not equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma.
Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma implies each of the following statements:
- The Axiom of Choice for Finite sets (ACF): Given and a family of non-empty sets, their product is not empty.
- A
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
union of finite sets is a countable set.
* However, ZF with the ultrafilter lemma is too weak to prove that a countable union of sets is a countable set.
- The
Hahn–Banach theorem
In functional analysis, the Hahn–Banach theorem is a central result that allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a vector subspace of some vector space to the whole space. The theorem also shows that there are sufficient ...
.
* In ZF, the Hahn–Banach theorem is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
- The Banach–Tarski paradox.
* In fact, under ZF, the Banach–Tarski paradox can be deduced from the
Hahn–Banach theorem
In functional analysis, the Hahn–Banach theorem is a central result that allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a vector subspace of some vector space to the whole space. The theorem also shows that there are sufficient ...
, which is strictly weaker than the Ultrafilter Lemma.
- Every set can be linearly ordered.
- Every field has a unique algebraic closure.
- Non-trivial ultraproducts exist.
- The weak ultrafilter theorem: A free ultrafilter exists on
* Under ZF, the weak ultrafilter theorem does not imply the ultrafilter lemma; that is, it is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
- There exists a free ultrafilter on every infinite set;
* This statement is actually strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
* ZF alone does not even imply that there exists a non-principal ultrafilter on set.
Completeness
The completeness of an ultrafilter
on a powerset is the smallest
cardinal
Cardinal or The Cardinal most commonly refers to
* Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds
**''Cardinalis'', genus of three species in the family Cardinalidae
***Northern cardinal, ''Cardinalis cardinalis'', the common cardinal of ...
κ such that there are κ elements of
whose intersection is not in
The definition of an ultrafilter implies that the completeness of any powerset ultrafilter is at least
. An ultrafilter whose completeness is than
—that is, the intersection of any countable collection of elements of
is still in
—is called countably complete or σ-complete.
The completeness of a countably complete
nonprincipal ultrafilter on a powerset is always a
measurable cardinal.
The (named after Mary Ellen Rudin and Howard Jerome Keisler) is a preorder on the class of powerset ultrafilters defined as follows: if is an ultrafilter on and an ultrafilter on then if there exists a function such that
: if and only if
for every subset
Ultrafilters and are called , denoted , if there exist sets and and a
bijection
In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
that satisfies the condition above. (If
and
have the same cardinality, the definition can be simplified by fixing
)
It is known that ≡
RK is the
kernel of ≤
RK, i.e., that if and only if
and
Ultrafilters on ℘(ω)
There are several special properties that an ultrafilter on
where
extends the natural numbers, may possess, which prove useful in various areas of set theory and topology.
* A non-principal ultrafilter
is called a P-point (or ) if for every
partition of
such that for all
there exists some
such that
is a finite set for each
* A non-principal ultrafilter
is called Ramsey (or selective) if for every partition
of
such that for all
there exists some
such that
is a
singleton set for each
It is a trivial observation that all Ramsey ultrafilters are P-points.
Walter Rudin proved that the
continuum hypothesis implies the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters.
In fact, many hypotheses imply the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters, including
Martin's axiom.
Saharon Shelah later showed that it is consistent that there are no P-point ultrafilters.
Therefore, the existence of these types of ultrafilters is
independent of
ZFC.
P-points are called as such because they are topological
P-points in the usual topology of the space
of non-principal ultrafilters. The name Ramsey comes from
Ramsey's theorem. To see why, one can prove that an ultrafilter is Ramsey if and only if for every 2-coloring of
there exists an element of the ultrafilter that has a homogeneous color.
An ultrafilter on
is Ramsey if and only if it is
minimal in the Rudin–Keisler ordering of non-principal powerset ultrafilters.
See also
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Notes
Proofs
References
Bibliography
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Further reading
*
*
*
{{Mathematical logic
Families of sets
Nonstandard analysis
Order theory