
In the
mathematical
Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
field of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concer ...
, an ultrafilter is a ''maximal proper filter'': it is a
filter on a given non-empty
set which is a certain type of non-empty
family of subsets of
that is not equal to the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is ...
of
(such filters are called ) and that is also "maximal" in that there does not exist any other proper filter on
that contains it as a
proper subset
In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset o ...
.
Said differently, a proper filter
is called an ultrafilter if there exists proper filter that contains it as a subset, that proper filter (necessarily) being
itself.
More formally, an ultrafilter
on
is a proper filter that is also a
maximal filter on
with respect to
set inclusion, meaning that there does not exist any
proper filter on
that contains
as a
proper subset
In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset o ...
.
Ultrafilters on sets are an important special instance of
ultrafilters on partially ordered sets, where the
partially ordered set
In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a binar ...
consists of the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is ...
and the partial order is
subset inclusion
Ultrafilters have many applications in set theory,
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the ...
, and
topology
In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ho ...
.
Definitions
Given an arbitrary set
an ultrafilter on
is a non-empty
family
Family (from la, familia) is a group of people related either by consanguinity (by recognized birth) or affinity (by marriage or other relationship). The purpose of the family is to maintain the well-being of its members and of society. Idea ...
of subsets of
such that:
# or : The empty set is not an element of
#: If
and if
is any superset of
(that is, if
) then
#: If
and
are elements of
then so is their
intersection
#If
then either
[Properties 1 and 3 imply that and cannot be elements of ] or its relative complement
is an element of
Properties (1), (2), and (3) are the defining properties of a Some authors do not include non-degeneracy (which is property (1) above) in their definition of "filter". However, the definition of "ultrafilter" (and also of "prefilter" and "filter subbase") always includes non-degeneracy as a defining condition. This article requires that all filters be proper although a filter might be described as "proper" for emphasis.
For a filter
that is not an ultrafilter, one would say
if
and
if
leaving
undefined elsewhere.
A filter base is a non-empty family of sets that has the
finite intersection property (i.e. all finite intersections are non-empty). Equivalently, a filter subbase is a non-empty family of sets that is contained in (proper) filter. The smallest (relative to
) filter containing a given filter subbase is said to be generated by the filter subbase.
The upward closure in
of a family of sets
is the set
:
A or is a non-empty and proper (i.e.
) family of sets
that is downward directed, which means that if
then there exists some
such that
Equivalently, a prefilter is any family of sets
whose upward closure
is a filter, in which case this filter is called the filter generated by
and
is said to be a filter base
The dual in
of a family of sets
is the set
For example, the dual of the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is ...
is itself:
A family of sets is a proper filter on
if and only if its dual is a proper
ideal on
("" means not equal to the power set).
Interpretation as sets
The elements of a proper filter
on
may be thought of as being "large sets (relative to
)" and the complements in
of a large sets can be thought of as being "small" sets (the "small sets" are exactly the elements in the
ideal ).
To see why filters and ideals should respectively be associated with "large" and "small" sets (rather than vice versa), we begin by explaining why sets in an ideal should be interpreted as "small" by considering the notion of "bounded subsets" (such as in a
metric space
In mathematics, a metric space is a set together with a notion of '' distance'' between its elements, usually called points. The distance is measured by a function called a metric or distance function. Metric spaces are the most general sett ...
or a
normed space
In mathematics, a normed vector space or normed space is a vector space over the real or complex numbers, on which a norm is defined. A norm is the formalization and the generalization to real vector spaces of the intuitive notion of "lengt ...
like
).
The following properties should be expected of any reasonable generalization of "bounded subsets": subsets of bounded sets should be bounded, the empty set should be bounded, the union of two bounded sets should be bounded, and every point (singleton subset) should be bounded. These are the defining properties of a on
although the term is more common, and elements of a given bornology are called . Explicitly (and equivalently), a on
is an
ideal that
covers
Bounded sets, especially singleton and finite sets, are naturally interpreted as "small sets". Thus we are led to associate ideals with "small sets". Assuming that
is not a bounded/"small set" (that is, if
or said differently, if
is a proper ideal) then it is reasonable to interpret complements of "small sets" as being "large sets". In other words, "large sets" are those belonging to the dual
of the ideal
Recalling that a family of subsets of
is a proper ideal if and only if its dual is a filter on
we are thus led to associate filters with "large sets".
In general, there may be subsets of
that are large nor small (e.g. a set not in
nor its dual
), or possibly large and small (e.g.
if
is not a proper ideal). A dual ideal is a filter (i.e. proper) if there is no set that is both large and small, or equivalently, if the
is not large. A filter is ultra if and only if subset of
is either large or else small. With this terminology, the defining properties of a filter can be restarted as: (1) any superset of a large set is large set, (2) the intersection of any two (or finitely many) large sets is large, (3)
is a large set (i.e.
), (4) the empty set is not large. Different dual ideals give different notions of "large" sets.
Another way of looking at ultrafilters on a power set
is as follows: for a given ultrafilter
define a function
on
by setting
if
is an element of
and
otherwise. Such a function is called a
2-valued morphism In mathematics, a 2-valued morphism. is a homomorphism that sends a Boolean algebra ''B'' onto the two-element Boolean algebra 2 = . It is essentially the same thing as an ultrafilter on ''B'', and, in a different way, also the same things as a max ...
. Then
is
finitely additive, and hence a on
and every property of elements of
is either true
almost everywhere or false almost everywhere. However,
is usually not , and hence does not define a
measure in the usual sense.
Generalization to ultra prefilters
A family
of subsets of
is called if
and any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
- For every set there exists some set such that or (or equivalently, such that equals or ).
- For every set there exists some set such that equals or
* Here, is defined to be the union of all sets in
* This characterization of " is ultra" does not depend on the set so mentioning the set is optional when using the term "ultra."
- For set (not necessarily even a subset of ) there exists some set such that equals or
* If satisfies this condition then so does superset In particular, a set is ultra if and only if and contains as a subset some ultra family of sets.
A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter.
[Suppose is filter subbase that is ultra. Let and define Because is ultra, there exists some such that equals or The finite intersection property implies that so necessarily which is equivalent to ]
The ultra property can now be used to define both ultrafilters and ultra prefilters:
:An is a prefilter that is ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra.
:An on
is a (proper) filter on
that is ultra. Equivalently, it is any filter on
that is generated by an ultra prefilter.
Ultra prefilters as maximal prefilters
To characterize ultra prefilters in terms of "maximality," the following relation is needed.
:Given two families of sets
and
the family
is said to be coarser than
and
is finer than and subordinate to
written
or , if for every
there is some
such that
The families
and
are called equivalent if
and
The families
and
are comparable if one of these sets is finer than the other.
The subordination relationship, i.e.
is a
preorder so the above definition of "equivalent" does form an
equivalence relation
In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation.
Each equivalence relatio ...
.
If
then
but the converse does not hold in general.
However, if
is upward closed, such as a filter, then
if and only if
Every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates. This shows that it is possible for filters to be equivalent to sets that are not filters.
If two families of sets
and
are equivalent then either both
and
are ultra (resp. prefilters, filter subbases) or otherwise neither one of them is ultra (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase).
In particular, if a filter subbase is not also a prefilter, then it is equivalent to the filter or prefilter that it generates. If
and
are both filters on
then
and
are equivalent if and only if
If a proper filter (resp. ultrafilter) is equivalent to a family of sets
then
is necessarily a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter).
Using the following characterization, it is possible to define prefilters (resp. ultra prefilters) using only the concept of filters (resp. ultrafilters) and subordination:
:An arbitrary family of sets is a prefilter if and only it is equivalent to a (proper) filter.
:An arbitrary family of sets is an ultra prefilter if and only it is equivalent to an ultrafilter.
:A on
is a prefilter
that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is ultra.
- is maximal on with respect to meaning that if satisfies then
- There is no prefilter properly subordinate to
- If a (proper) filter on satisfies then
- The filter on generated by is ultra.
Characterizations
There are no ultrafilters on the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in oth ...
, so it is henceforth assumed that
is nonempty.
A filter base
on
is an ultrafilter on
if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- for any either or
- is a maximal filter subbase on meaning that if is any filter subbase on then implies
A (proper) filter
on
is an ultrafilter on
if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- is ultra;
- is generated by an ultra prefilter;
- For any subset or
* So an ultrafilter decides for every whether is "large" (i.e. ) or "small" (i.e. ).
- For each subset either
[ is in or () is.]
- This condition can be restated as: is partitioned by and its dual
* The sets and are disjoint for all prefilters on
- is an ideal on
- For any finite family of subsets of (where ), if then for some index
* In words, a "large" set cannot be a finite union of sets that aren't large.
- For any if then or
- For any if then or (a filter with this property is called a ).
- For any if and then or
- is a maximal filter; that is, if is a filter on such that then Equivalently, is a maximal filter if there is no filter on that contains as a
proper subset
In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset o ...
(that is, no filter is strictly finer than ).
Grills and Filter-Grills
If
then its is the family
where
may be written if
is clear from context.
For example,
and if
then
If
then
and moreover, if
is a filter subbase then
The grill
is upward closed in
if and only if
which will henceforth be assumed. Moreover,
so that
is upward closed in
if and only if
The grill of a filter on
is called a For any
is a filter-grill on
if and only if (1)
is upward closed in
and (2) for all sets
and
if
then
or
The grill operation
induces a bijection
:
whose inverse is also given by
If
then
is a filter-grill on
if and only if
or equivalently, if and only if
is an ultrafilter on
That is, a filter on
is a filter-grill if and only if it is ultra. For any non-empty
is both a filter on
and a filter-grill on
if and only if (1)
and (2) for all
the following equivalences hold:
:
if and only if
if and only if
Free or principal
If
is any non-empty family of sets then the
Kernel
Kernel may refer to:
Computing
* Kernel (operating system), the central component of most operating systems
* Kernel (image processing), a matrix used for image convolution
* Compute kernel, in GPGPU programming
* Kernel method, in machine lea ...
of
is the intersection of all sets in
A non-empty family of sets
is called:
* if
and otherwise (that is, if
).
* if
* if
and
is a singleton set; in this case, if
then
is said to be principal at
If a family of sets
is fixed then
is ultra if and only if some element of
is a singleton set, in which case
will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter
is ultra if and only if
is a singleton set. A singleton set is ultra if and only if its sole element is also a singleton set.
Every filter on
that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition
is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on
other than these. If there exists a free ultrafilter (or even filter subbase) on a set
then
must be infinite.
The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point.
Examples, properties, and sufficient conditions
If
and
are families of sets such that
is ultra,
and
then
is necessarily ultra.
A filter subbase
that is not a prefilter cannot be ultra; but it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter and filter generated by
to be ultra.
Suppose
is ultra and
is a set.
The trace
is ultra if and only if it does not contain the empty set.
Furthermore, at least one of the sets
and
will be ultra (this result extends to any finite partition of
).
If
are filters on
is an ultrafilter on
and
then there is some
that satisfies
This result is not necessarily true for an infinite family of filters.
The image under a map
of an ultra set
is again ultra and if
is an ultra prefilter then so is
The property of being ultra is preserved under bijections. However, the preimage of an ultrafilter is not necessarily ultra, not even if the map is surjective. For example, if
has more than one point and if the range of
consists of a single point
then
is an ultra prefilter on
but its preimage is not ultra. Alternatively, if
is a principal filter generated by a point in
then the preimage of
contains the empty set and so is not ultra.
The elementary filter induced by an infinite sequence, all of whose points are distinct, is an ultrafilter. If
then
denotes the set consisting all subsets of
having cardinality
and if
contains at least
(
) distinct points, then
is ultra but it is not contained in any prefilter. This example generalizes to any integer
and also to
if
contains more than one element. Ultra sets that are not also prefilters are rarely used.
For every
and every
let
If
is an ultrafilter on
then the set of all
such that
is an ultrafilter on
Monad structure
The
functor
In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a mapping between categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) are associated to topological spaces, an ...
associating to any set
the set of
of all ultrafilters on
forms a
monad called the
ultrafilter monad
In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter is a ''maximal proper filter'': it is a filter U on a given non-empty set X which is a certain type of non-empty family of subsets of X, that is not equal to the power set \wp(X) of X (such ...
. The unit map
:
sends any element
to the principal ultrafilter given by
This monad admits a conceptual explanation as the
codensity monad
In mathematics, especially in category theory, the codensity monad is a fundamental construction associating a monad (category theory), monad to a wide class of functors.
Definition
The codensity monad of a functor G: D \to C is defined to be ...
of the inclusion of the
category of finite sets In the mathematical field of category theory, FinSet is the category whose objects are all finite sets and whose morphisms are all functions between them. FinOrd is the category whose objects are all finite ordinal numbers and whose morphisms are a ...
into the
category of all sets.
The ultrafilter lemma
The ultrafilter lemma was first proved by
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
in 1930.
The ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements:
# For every prefilter on a set
there exists a maximal prefilter on
subordinate to it.
# Every proper filter subbase on a set
is contained in some ultrafilter on
A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.
[Let be a filter on that is not an ultrafilter. If is such that then has the finite intersection property (because if then if and only if ) so that by the ultrafilter lemma, there exists some ultrafilter on such that (so in particular ). It follows that ]
The following results can be proven using the ultrafilter lemma.
A free ultrafilter exists on a set
if and only if
is infinite. Every proper filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it. Since there are filters that are not ultra, this shows that the intersection of a family of ultrafilters need not be ultra. A family of sets
can be extended to a free ultrafilter if and only if the intersection of any finite family of elements of
is infinite.
Relationships to other statements under ZF
Throughout this section, ZF refers to
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory and ZFC refers to ZF with the Axiom of Choice (AC). The ultrafilter lemma is independent of ZF. That is, there exist
models in which the axioms of ZF hold but the ultrafilter lemma does not. There also exist models of ZF in which every ultrafilter is necessarily principal.
Every filter that contains a singleton set is necessarily an ultrafilter and given
the definition of the discrete ultrafilter
does not require more than ZF.
If
is finite then every ultrafilter is a discrete filter at a point; consequently, free ultrafilters can only exist on infinite sets.
In particular, if
is finite then the ultrafilter lemma can be proven from the axioms ZF.
The existence of free ultrafilter on infinite sets can be proven if the axiom of choice is assumed.
More generally, the ultrafilter lemma can be proven by using the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
, which in brief states that any
Cartesian product
In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets ''A'' and ''B'', denoted ''A''×''B'', is the set of all ordered pairs where ''a'' is in ''A'' and ''b'' is in ''B''. In terms of set-builder notation, that is
: A\ ...
of non-empty sets is non-empty. Under ZF, the axiom of choice is, in particular,
equivalent to (a)
Zorn's lemma, (b)
Tychonoff's theorem, (c) the weak form of the vector basis theorem (which states that every vector space has a
basis), (d) the strong form of the vector basis theorem, and other statements.
However, the ultrafilter lemma is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice.
While free ultrafilters can be proven to exist, it is possible to construct an explicit example of a free ultrafilter; that is, free ultrafilters are intangible.
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
proved that under ZFC, the cardinality of the set of all free ultrafilters on an infinite set
is equal to the cardinality of
where
denotes the power set of
Other authors attribute this discovery to Bedřich Pospíšil (following a combinatorial argument from
Fichtenholz, and
Kantorovitch, improved by
Hausdorff).
Under ZF, the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
can be used to prove both the ultrafilter lemma and the
Krein–Milman theorem; conversely, under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma together with the Krein–Milman theorem can prove the axiom of choice.
Statements that cannot be deduced
The ultrafilter lemma is a relatively weak axiom. For example, each of the statements in the following list can be deduced from ZF together with the ultrafilter lemma:
- A countable union of
countable set
In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural number ...
s is a countable set.
- The axiom of countable choice (ACC).
- The
axiom of dependent choice In mathematics, the axiom of dependent choice, denoted by \mathsf , is a weak form of the axiom of choice ( \mathsf ) that is still sufficient to develop most of real analysis. It was introduced by Paul Bernays in a 1942 article that explores w ...
(ADC).
Equivalent statements
Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements:
- The Boolean prime ideal theorem (BPIT).
* This equivalence is provable in ZF set theory without the Axiom of Choice (AC).
Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras
In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first ...
.
- Any product of Boolean spaces is a Boolean space.
- Boolean Prime Ideal Existence Theorem: Every nondegenerate
Boolean algebra
In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas ...
has a prime ideal.
- Tychonoff's theorem for
Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), separated space or T2 space is a topological space where, for any two distinct points, there exist neighbourhoods of each which are disjoint from each other. Of the many ...
s: Any product of compact Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), separated space or T2 space is a topological space where, for any two distinct points, there exist neighbourhoods of each which are disjoint from each other. Of the many ...
s is compact.
- If is endowed with the discrete topology then for any set the
product space
In topology and related areas of mathematics, a product space is the Cartesian product of a family of topological spaces equipped with a natural topology called the product topology. This topology differs from another, perhaps more natural-see ...
is compact.
- Each of the following versions of the Banach-Alaoglu theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
- Any equicontinuous set of scalar-valued maps on a topological vector space (TVS) is relatively compact in the weak-* topology (that is, it is contained in some weak-* compact set).
- The polar of any neighborhood of the origin in a TVS is a weak-* compact subset of its
continuous dual space
In mathematics, any vector space ''V'' has a corresponding dual vector space (or just dual space for short) consisting of all linear forms on ''V'', together with the vector space structure of pointwise addition and scalar multiplication by con ...
.
- The closed unit ball in the
continuous dual space
In mathematics, any vector space ''V'' has a corresponding dual vector space (or just dual space for short) consisting of all linear forms on ''V'', together with the vector space structure of pointwise addition and scalar multiplication by con ...
of any normed space
In mathematics, a normed vector space or normed space is a vector space over the real or complex numbers, on which a norm is defined. A norm is the formalization and the generalization to real vector spaces of the intuitive notion of "lengt ...
is weak-* compact.
* If the normed space is separable then the ultrafilter lemma is sufficient but not necessary to prove this statement.
- A topological space is compact if every ultrafilter on converges to some limit.
- A topological space is compact if every ultrafilter on converges to some limit.
* The addition of the words "and only if" is the only difference between this statement and the one immediately above it.
- The Ultranet lemma: Every net has a universal subnet.
* By definition, a net in is called an or an if for every subset the net is eventually in or in
- A topological space is compact if and only if every ultranet on converges to some limit.
* If the words "and only if" are removed then the resulting statement remains equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma.
- A convergence space is compact if every ultrafilter on converges.
- A
uniform space
In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a set with a uniform structure. Uniform spaces are topological spaces with additional structure that is used to define uniform properties such as completeness, uniform continuity and uni ...
is compact if it is complete and totally bounded In topology and related branches of mathematics, total-boundedness is a generalization of compactness for circumstances in which a set is not necessarily closed. A totally bounded set can be covered by finitely many subsets of every fixed “si ...
.
- The Stone–Čech compactification Theorem.
- Each of the following versions of the compactness theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
- If is a set of first-order sentences such that every finite subset of has a model, then has a model.
- If is a set of zero-order sentences such that every finite subset of has a model, then has a model.
- The completeness theorem: If is a set of zero-order sentences that is syntactically consistent, then it has a model (that is, it is semantically consistent).
Weaker statements
Any statement that can be deduced from the ultrafilter lemma (together with ZF) is said to be than the ultrafilter lemma.
A weaker statement is said to be if under ZF, it is not equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma.
Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma implies each of the following statements:
- The Axiom of Choice for Finite sets (ACF): Given and a family of non-empty sets, their product is not empty.
- A countable union of finite sets is a countable set.
* However, ZF with the ultrafilter lemma is too weak to prove that a countable union of sets is a countable set.
- The Hahn–Banach theorem.
* In ZF, the Hahn–Banach theorem is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
- The Banach–Tarski paradox.
* In fact, under ZF, the Banach–Tarski paradox can be deduced from the Hahn–Banach theorem, which is strictly weaker than the Ultrafilter Lemma.
- Every set can be linearly ordered.
- Every field has a unique algebraic closure.
- The
Alexander subbase theorem
In topology, a subbase (or subbasis, prebase, prebasis) for a topological space X with topology T is a subcollection B of T that generates T, in the sense that T is the smallest topology containing B. A slightly different definition is used by ...
.
- Non-trivial
ultraproducts
The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All factors ...
exist.
- The weak ultrafilter theorem: A free ultrafilter exists on
* Under ZF, the weak ultrafilter theorem does not imply the ultrafilter lemma; that is, it is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
- There exists a free ultrafilter on every infinite set;
* This statement is actually strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
* ZF alone does not even imply that there exists a non-principal ultrafilter on set.
Completeness
The completeness of an ultrafilter
on a powerset is the smallest
cardinal κ such that there are κ elements of
whose intersection is not in
The definition of an ultrafilter implies that the completeness of any powerset ultrafilter is at least
. An ultrafilter whose completeness is than
—that is, the intersection of any countable collection of elements of
is still in
—is called countably complete or σ-complete.
The completeness of a countably complete
nonprincipal ultrafilter on a powerset is always a
measurable cardinal.
The (named after Mary Ellen Rudin and Howard Jerome Keisler) is a preorder on the class of powerset ultrafilters defined as follows: if is an ultrafilter on and an ultrafilter on then if there exists a function such that
: if and only if
for every subset
Ultrafilters and are called , denoted , if there exist sets and and a bijection that satisfies the condition above. (If and have the same cardinality, the definition can be simplified by fixing )
It is known that ≡RK is the
kernel
Kernel may refer to:
Computing
* Kernel (operating system), the central component of most operating systems
* Kernel (image processing), a matrix used for image convolution
* Compute kernel, in GPGPU programming
* Kernel method, in machine lea ...
of ≤
RK, i.e., that if and only if
and
Ultrafilters on ℘(ω)
There are several special properties that an ultrafilter on
where
extends the natural numbers, may possess, which prove useful in various areas of set theory and topology.
* A non-principal ultrafilter
is called a P-point (or ) if for every
partition of
such that for all
there exists some
such that
is a finite set for each
* A non-principal ultrafilter
is called Ramsey (or selective) if for every partition
of
such that for all
there exists some
such that
is a
singleton set for each
It is a trivial observation that all Ramsey ultrafilters are P-points.
Walter Rudin proved that the
continuum hypothesis
In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that
or equivalently, that
In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent ...
implies the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters.
In fact, many hypotheses imply the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters, including
Martin's axiom.
Saharon Shelah later showed that it is consistent that there are no P-point ultrafilters.
Therefore, the existence of these types of ultrafilters is
independent
Independent or Independents may refer to:
Arts, entertainment, and media Artist groups
* Independents (artist group), a group of modernist painters based in the New Hope, Pennsylvania, area of the United States during the early 1930s
* Independe ...
of
ZFC.
P-points are called as such because they are topological
P-point
This is a glossary of some terms used in the branch of mathematics known as topology. Although there is no absolute distinction between different areas of topology, the focus here is on general topology. The following definitions are also funda ...
s in the usual topology of the space
of non-principal ultrafilters. The name Ramsey comes from
Ramsey's theorem. To see why, one can prove that an ultrafilter is Ramsey if and only if for every 2-coloring of
there exists an element of the ultrafilter that has a homogeneous color.
An ultrafilter on
is Ramsey if and only if it is
minimal in the Rudin–Keisler ordering of non-principal powerset ultrafilters.
See also
*
*
*
Notes
Proofs
References
Bibliography
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Further reading
*
*
*
{{Mathematical logic
Families of sets
Nonstandard analysis
Order theory