Transcendental Arguments
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

A transcendental argument is a kind of
deductive Deductive reasoning is the process of drawing valid inferences. An inference is valid if its conclusion follows logically from its premises, meaning that it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. For example, th ...
argument An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persu ...
that appeals to the necessary conditions that make
experience Experience refers to Consciousness, conscious events in general, more specifically to perceptions, or to the practical knowledge and familiarity that is produced by these processes. Understood as a conscious event in the widest sense, experience i ...
and
knowledge Knowledge is an Declarative knowledge, awareness of facts, a Knowledge by acquaintance, familiarity with individuals and situations, or a Procedural knowledge, practical skill. Knowledge of facts, also called propositional knowledge, is oft ...
possible.Transcendental-arguments and Scepticism; Answering the Question of Justification (Clarendon Press: Oxford, 2000), pp 3-6.Strawson, P., Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985) Premise-10. Transcendental arguments may have additional standards of justification which are more demanding than those of traditional deductive arguments. The philosopher
Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant (born Emanuel Kant; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German Philosophy, philosopher and one of the central Age of Enlightenment, Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works ...
gave transcendental arguments both their name and their notoriety.


The arguments

Typically, a transcendental argument starts from some
proposition A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
, and then makes the case that its truth or falsehood contradicts the necessary conditions for it to be possible to know, think or argue about it. So-called ''progressive'' transcendental arguments begin with an apparently indubitable and universally accepted statement about people's experiences of the world. They use this to make substantive knowledge-claims about the world, e.g., that it ''is'' causally and spatiotemporally related. They start with what is left at the ''end'' of the skeptic's process of doubting. Progressive transcendental arguments take the form of
modus ponens In propositional logic, (; MP), also known as (), implication elimination, or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. It can be summarized as "''P'' implies ''Q.'' ''P'' is true. Therefore, ''Q'' must ...
with modal operators: :If possibly ''P'', then necessarily ''Q''. :Actually ''P''. :Therefore, necessarily ''Q''. ''Regressive'' transcendental arguments, on the other hand, ''begin at the same point'' as the skeptic, e.g., the fact that we have experience of a causal and spatiotemporal world, and show that certain notions are implicit in our conceptions of such experience. Regressive transcendental arguments are more conservative in that they do not purport to make substantive ontological claims about the world. Regressive transcendental arguments take the form of
modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "mode that by denying denies") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens'' is a m ...
with modal operators: :If possibly ''P'', then necessarily ''Q''. :Actually not ''Q''. :Therefore, necessarily not ''P''. Transcendental arguments are often used to refute
skepticism Skepticism ( US) or scepticism ( UK) is a questioning attitude or doubt toward knowledge claims that are seen as mere belief or dogma. For example, if a person is skeptical about claims made by their government about an ongoing war then the p ...
. For example: # If we have knowledge, universal skepticism is false. # We have knowledge. (If we did not, we couldn't possibly argue that universal skepticism is true) # Universal skepticism is false. Kant uses an example in his refutation of
idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
. Idealists believe that objects have no existence independent of the mind. Briefly, Kant shows that: # since idealists acknowledge that we have an inner mental life, and # an inner life of self-awareness is bound up with the concepts of objects which are not inner, and which interact causally, # We must have legitimate experience of outer objects which interact causally. He has not established that outer objects exist, but only that the concept of them is legitimate, contrary to idealism. Robert Lockie makes a transcendental argument for libertarian free will: # If we want to know truth, we have free will. # We want to know the truth about free will. # We have free will. However, not all use of transcendental arguments is intended to counter skepticism. The Dutch philosopher Herman Dooyeweerd used transcendental critique to establish the conditions that make a theoretical (or scientific) attitude of thought (not just the process of thinking, as in Kant) possible. In particular, he showed that theoretical thought is not independent (or neutral) of pre-commitments and relationships but are rather grounded in commitments, attitudes, and presuppositions that are "religious" in nature.
C.S. Lewis CS, C-S, C.S., Cs, cs, or cs. may refer to: Job titles * Chief Secretary (Hong Kong) * Chief superintendent, a rank in the British and several other police forces * Company secretary, a senior position in a private sector company or public se ...
made transcendental arguments to prove the existence of God and refute naturalism.


Kant

It was Immanuel Kant who gave transcendental arguments their name and notoriety. It is open to controversy, though, whether his own transcendental arguments should be classified as progressive or regressive. In the ''
Critique of Pure Reason The ''Critique of Pure Reason'' (; 1781; second edition 1787) is a book by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant, in which the author seeks to determine the limits and scope of metaphysics. Also referred to as Kant's "First Critique", it was foll ...
'' (1781) Kant developed one of philosophy's most famous transcendental arguments in 'The Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding'. In the 'Transcendental Aesthetic', Kant used transcendental arguments to show that sensory experiences would not be possible if we did not impose their spatial and temporal forms on them, making space and time "conditions of the possibility of experience".


Criticisms of transcendental arguments

One of the main uses of transcendental arguments is to appeal to something that cannot be consistently denied to counter skeptics' arguments that we cannot ''know'' something about the nature of the world. One need not be a skeptic about those matters, however, to find transcendental arguments unpersuasive. There are a number of ways that one might deny that a given transcendental argument gives us knowledge of the world. The following responses may suit some versions and not others. *First, critics respond by claiming that the arguer cannot be sure that he or she is having particular experiences. That a person cannot be sure about the nature of his or her own experiences may initially seem bizarre. However, it may be claimed that the very act of thinking about or, even more, describing our experiences in words, involves interpreting them in ways that go beyond so-called 'pure' experience. Baggini, Julian and Peter S. Fosl. 2003. '2.10 Transcendental arguments'. In ''The Philosopher's Toolkit: A compendium of philosophical concepts and methods''. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing *Second, skeptics object to the use of transcendental arguments to draw conclusions about the nature of the world by claiming that even if a person ''does'' know the nature of his or her experiences, that person cannot know that the reasoning from these experiences to conclusions about the world is accurate. *Lastly, critics have debated whether showing that we must think of the world in a certain way, given certain features of experience, is tantamount to showing that the world answers to that conception. Perhaps transcendental arguments show only the necessities of our cognitive apparatus rather than the realities of the world apart from us. This objection may amount to throwing doubt on whether transcendental arguments are ever more than merely "regressive". A. C. Grayling, "Transcendental Arguments" in ''The Blackwell Companion to Epistemology'', Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa, eds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992) .


See also

*
Transcendental idealism Transcendental idealism is a philosophical system founded by German philosopher Immanuel Kant in the 18th century. Kant's epistemological program is found throughout his '' Critique of Pure Reason'' (1781). By ''transcendental'' (a term that des ...
*
Ludwig Wittgenstein Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein ( ; ; 26 April 1889 – 29 April 1951) was an Austrian philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language. From 1929 to 1947, Witt ...
* Transcendental argument for the existence of God


References


Bibliography

*Brueckner, Anthony. " Transcendental Arguments I". ''Nous'' 17 (4): 551-575. and "Transcendental Arguments II". ''Nous'' 18 (2): 197-225. * Stapleford, Scott Kant's Transcendental Arguments: Disciplining Pure Reason - Continuum Publishing 2008 ( - hb) * Stern, Robert, ed.''Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Prospect''. Oxford: Clarendon. * Stroud, Barry. "Transcendental Arguments". ''Journal of Philosophy'' 65 (1968) 241-56. * Taylor, Charles. "The Validity of Transcendental Arguments". Reprinted in ''Philosophical Arguments''. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1955.


External links

* * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Transcendental Arguments Philosophical arguments Deductive reasoning Philosophical methodology German idealism