Single-peaked Preferences
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Single-peaked preferences are a class of preference relations. A group has single-peaked preferences over a set of outcomes if the outcomes can be ordered along a line such that: # Each agent has a "best outcome" in the set, and # For each agent, outcomes that are further from his or her best outcome are preferred less. Single-peaked preferences are typical of one-dimensional domains. A typical example is when several consumers have to decide on the amount of
public good In economics, a public good (also referred to as a social good or collective good)Oakland, W. H. (1987). Theory of public goods. In Handbook of public economics (Vol. 2, pp. 485–535). Elsevier. is a commodity, product or service that is bo ...
to purchase. The amount is a one-dimensional variable. Usually, each consumer decides on a certain quantity which is best for him or her, and if the actual quantity is more/less than that ideal quantity, the agent is then less satisfied. With single-peaked preferences, there is a simple
truthful mechanism In mechanism design, a strategyproof (SP) mechanism is a game form in which each player has a weakly- dominant strategy, so that no player can gain by "spying" over the other players to know what they are going to play. When the players have privat ...
for selecting an outcome, which is to select the median quantity; this results in the
median voter theorem In political science and social choice theory, social choice, Black's median voter theorem says that if voters and candidates are distributed along a political spectrum, any voting method Condorcet criterion, compatible with majority-rule will elec ...
. It is truthful because the median function satisfies the strong monotonicity property. The notion was first presented by
Duncan Black Duncan Black, FBA (23 May 1908 – 14 January 1991) was a Scottish economist who laid the foundations of social choice theory. In particular he was responsible for unearthing the work of many early political scientists, including Charles Lut ...
and later by
Kenneth Arrow Kenneth Joseph Arrow (August 23, 1921 – February 21, 2017) was an American economist, mathematician and political theorist. He received the John Bates Clark Medal in 1957, and the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences in 1972, along with ...
.


Definitions

Let X = \ be the set of possible outcomes. Let N = \ be the set of agents. The preference-relation of agent ''i'' is denoted by \succ_i. The maximum element of \succ_i in ''X'' is denoted by x^*_i.


Definition using a common order

The group ''N'' is said to have single-peaked preferences over ''X'', if there exists an ordering > of the outcomes such that, for every agent ''i'' in ''N'':
x_k
x_k>x_j \geq x^*_i \Rightarrow x_j \succ_i x_k
In words, x^*_i is the ideal point for agent ''i''. When the agent compares between two outcomes that are both to the right or to the left of his ideal point, he strictly prefers whichever option is closest to x^*_i. Note that the preference-relations \succ_i are different, but the ordering > of the outcomes must be the same for all agents.


Necessary and sufficient condition

Ballester and Haeringer proved the following two conditions are necessary and sufficient for a profile of preferences to be single-peaked preferences. * Worst-restricted: For every triplet of outcomes in ''X'', there exists an outcome that is not ranked last by any agent in ''N''. * \alpha-restricted: There does not exist four outcomes in ''X'', say, a, b, c, and d, and two agents i and j such that a\succ_i c\succ_i\succ_i d, b\succ_i c, and d\succ_j c\succ_j a, b\succ_j c. It was already known since Inada that Worst-restricted was necessary but not sufficient for a profile to be single-peaked.


Some examples


Single-peaked preferences

The following graph shows a set of three preferences that are single-peaked over outcomes . On the vertical axis, the number represents the preference ranking of the outcome, with 1 being most preferred. Two outcomes that are equally preferred have the same ranking. The ordering over the outcomes is A < B < C < D < E. The ideal outcome for the green agent is A, for the red it is B, for the blue it is C. For each agent, when we move away from his ideal outcome, the ranking decreases. It can also be verified that, for each triplet of outcomes, one of them is never ranked last - the one in the middle. E.g., in , B is never ranked last; in , D is never ranked last; etc.


Non single-peaked preferences

If each of the two preferences represented by the following two graphs is added to the three preferences above, then the resulting group of four preferences is not single-peaked: For the blue preferences, it can be seen that the preference ranking spikes down for "D" and then spikes up for "E". This proves that the blue preferences are not single-peaked with respect to the ordering A

Interpretations

Single-peaked preferences have a number of interpretations for different applications. A simple application of ideological preferences is to think of the outcome space \ as locations on a street and each x_i as the address of an individual. Suppose a single bus stop has to be located on the street and every individual wishes to walk as little as possible to the stop. Individuals then have single-peaked preferences: individual i's ideal point is x_i and she dislikes other locations the farther they are to the west or the farther they are to the east. The outcome space can also be thought as different policies in an ideological spectrum: policies from the Left vs policies from the Right; policies that are more liberal vs policies that are more conservative; policies that are pro free markets vs policies that are pro state intervention. Voters have single-peaked preferences if they have an ideal balance between the two directions of the ideological spectrum and if they dislike policies the farther away they are from their ideal point.


Related preference domains

A group of agents is said to have single-dipped preferences over a set of possible outcomes if the outcomes can be ordered along a line such that: # Each agent has a "worst outcome" in the set, and - # For each agent, outcomes that are further from his worst outcome are preferred more. Lackner and Peters study a class of preferences that are single-peaked on a circle.


Recognition

The single-peaked recognition problem is the following
decision problem In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a decision problem is a computational problem that can be posed as a yes–no question on a set of input values. An example of a decision problem is deciding whether a given natura ...
: given a set of preferences on a set of outcomes, decide if there is a common order of the outcomes for which the preferences are single-peaked. Usually, it is required to also find this common order, if it exists. Trick presents a polynomial-time algorithm for recognizing preferences that are single-peaked on a tree. Escoffier, Spanjaard and Tydrichova study the problem of recognizing preferences that are single-peaked on a general graph.


See also

* Single-parameter mechanism *
Star-shaped preferences In social choice theory, star-shaped preferences are a class of preferences over points in a Euclidean space. An agent with star-shaped preferences has a unique ideal point (optimum), where he is maximally satisfied. Moreover, he becomes less and le ...
- an extension of single-peaked preferences to multi-dimensional domains.


References

* * * {{Refend Elections Utility function types