HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
and
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, second-order logic is an extension of
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
, which itself is an extension of
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
. Second-order logic is in turn extended by
higher-order logic In mathematics and logic, a higher-order logic (abbreviated HOL) is a form of logic that is distinguished from first-order logic by additional quantifiers and, sometimes, stronger semantics. Higher-order logics with their standard semantics are m ...
and
type theory In mathematics and theoretical computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of ...
. First-order logic quantifies only variables that range over individuals (elements of the
domain of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse or universe of discourse (borrowing from the mathematical concept of ''universe'') is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. It is also ...
); second-order logic, in addition, quantifies over relations. For example, the second-order sentence \forall P\,\forall x (Px \lor \neg Px) says that for every
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
''P'', and every individual ''x'', either ''Px'' is true or not(''Px'') is true (this is the
law of excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle or the principle of excluded middle states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradiction and t ...
). Second-order logic also includes quantification over
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
s,
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-orie ...
s, and other variables (see section
below Below may refer to: *Earth *Ground (disambiguation) *Soil *Floor * Bottom (disambiguation) *Less than *Temperatures below freezing *Hell or underworld People with the surname * Ernst von Below (1863–1955), German World War I general * Fred Belo ...
). Both first-order and second-order logic use the idea of a
domain of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse or universe of discourse (borrowing from the mathematical concept of ''universe'') is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. It is also ...
(often called simply the "domain" or the "universe"). The domain is a set over which individual elements may be quantified.


Examples

First-order logic can quantify over individuals, but not over properties. That is, we can take an
atomic sentence In logic and analytic philosophy, an atomic sentence is a type of declarative sentence which is either true or false (may also be referred to as a proposition, statement or truthbearer) and which cannot be broken down into other simpler sentences. ...
like Cube(''b'') and obtain a quantified sentence by replacing the name with a variable and attaching a quantifier: \exists x\,\mathrm(x) However, we cannot do the same with the predicate. That is, the following expression: \exists\mathrm\,\mathrm(b) is not a sentence of first-order logic, but this is a legitimate sentence of second-order logic. Here, ''P'' is a
predicate variable In mathematical logic, a predicate variable is a predicate letter which functions as a "placeholder" for a relation (between terms), but which has not been specifically assigned any particular relation (or meaning). Common symbols for denoting pre ...
and is semantically a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
of individuals. As a result, second-order logic has greater expressive power than first-order logic. For example, there is no way in first-order logic to identify the set of all cubes and tetrahedrons. But the existence of this set can be asserted in second-order logic as: \exists\mathrm\,\forall x\,(\mathrmx\leftrightarrow(\mathrm(x)\vee\mathrm(x))). We can then assert properties of this set. For instance, the following says that the set of all cubes and tetrahedrons does not contain any dodecahedrons: \forall\mathrm\,(\forall x\,(\mathrmx\leftrightarrow(\mathrm(x)\vee\mathrm(x)))\rightarrow\lnot\exists x\,(\mathrmx\wedge\mathrm(x))). Second-order quantification is especially useful because it gives the ability to express
reachability In graph theory, reachability refers to the ability to get from one vertex to another within a graph. A vertex s can reach a vertex t (and t is reachable from s) if there exists a sequence of adjacent vertices (i.e. a walk) which starts with s a ...
properties. For example, if Parent(''x'', ''y'') denotes that ''x'' is a parent of ''y'', then first-order logic cannot express the property that ''x'' is an
ancestor An ancestor, also known as a forefather, fore-elder, or a forebear, is a parent or ( recursively) the parent of an antecedent (i.e., a grandparent, great-grandparent, great-great-grandparent and so forth). ''Ancestor'' is "any person from ...
of ''y''. In second-order logic we can express this by saying that every set of people containing ''y'' and closed under the Parent relation contains ''x'': \forall\mathrm\,((\mathrmy\wedge\forall a\,\forall b\,((\mathrmb\wedge\mathrm(a,b))\rightarrow\mathrma))\rightarrow\mathrmx). It is notable that while we have variables for predicates in second-order-logic, we don't have variables for properties of predicates. We cannot say, for example, that there is a property Shape(''P'') that is true for the predicates ''P'' Cube, Tet, and Dodec. This would require third-order logic.


Syntax and fragments

The syntax of second-order logic tells which expressions are well formed
formulas In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
. In addition to the syntax of first-order logic, second-order logic includes many new ''sorts'' (sometimes called ''types'') of variables. These are: * A sort of variables that range over sets of individuals. If ''S'' is a variable of this sort and ''t'' is a first-order term then the expression ''t'' ∈ ''S'' (also written ''S''(''t''), or ''St'' to save parentheses) is an
atomic formula In mathematical logic, an atomic formula (also known as an atom or a prime formula) is a formula with no deeper propositional structure, that is, a formula that contains no logical connectives or equivalently a formula that has no strict subformu ...
. Sets of individuals can also be viewed as
unary relation In mathematics, a finitary relation over a sequence of sets is a subset of the Cartesian product ; that is, it is a set of ''n''-tuples , each being a sequence of elements ''x'i'' in the corresponding ''X'i''. Typically, the relation descri ...
s on the domain. * For each natural number ''k'' there is a sort of variables that ranges over all ''k''-ary relations on the individuals. If ''R'' is such a ''k''-ary relation variable and ''t''1,...,''t''''k'' are first-order terms then the expression ''R''(''t''1,...,''t''''k'') is an atomic formula. * For each natural number ''k'' there is a sort of variables that ranges over all functions taking ''k'' elements of the domain and returning a single element of the domain. If ''f'' is such a ''k''-ary function variable and ''t''1,...,''t''''k'' are first-order terms then the expression ''f''(''t''1,...,''t''''k'') is a first-order term. Each of the variables just defined may be universally and/or existentially quantified over, to build up formulas. Thus there are many kinds of quantifiers, two for each sort of variables. A ''sentence'' in second-order logic, as in first-order logic, is a well-formed formula with no free variables (of any sort). It's possible to forgo the introduction of function variables in the definition given above (and some authors do this) because an ''n''-ary function variable can be represented by a relation variable of arity ''n''+1 and an appropriate formula for the uniqueness of the "result" in the ''n''+1 argument of the relation. (Shapiro 2000, p. 63)
Monadic second-order logic In mathematical logic, monadic second-order logic (MSO) is the fragment of second-order logic where the second-order quantification is limited to quantification over sets. It is particularly important in the logic of graphs, because of Courcelle's ...
(MSO) is a restriction of second-order logic in which only quantification over unary relations (i.e. sets) is allowed. Quantification over functions, owing to the equivalence to relations as described above, is thus also not allowed. The second-order logic without these restrictions is sometimes called ''full second-order logic'' to distinguish it from the monadic version. Monadic second-order logic is particularly used in the context of
Courcelle's theorem In the study of graph algorithms, Courcelle's theorem is the statement that every graph property definable in the monadic second-order logic of graphs can be decided in linear time on graphs of bounded treewidth. The result was first proved by B ...
, an algorithmic meta-theorem in
graph theory In mathematics and computer science, graph theory is the study of ''graph (discrete mathematics), graphs'', which are mathematical structures used to model pairwise relations between objects. A graph in this context is made up of ''Vertex (graph ...
. The MSO theory of the complete infinite binary tree ( S2S) is decidable. By contrast, full second order logic over any infinite set (or MSO logic over for example (\mathbb,+)) can interpret the true
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
. Just as in first-order logic, second-order logic may include
non-logical symbol In logic, the formal languages used to create expressions consist of symbols, which can be broadly divided into constants and variables. The constants of a language can further be divided into logical symbols and non-logical symbols (sometimes a ...
s in a particular second-order language. These are restricted, however, in that all terms that they form must be either first-order terms (which can be substituted for a first-order variable) or second-order terms (which can be substituted for a second-order variable of an appropriate sort). A formula in second-order logic is said to be of first-order (and sometimes denoted \Sigma^1_0 or \Pi^1_0) if its quantifiers (which may be universal or existential) range only over variables of first order, although it may have free variables of second order. A \Sigma^1_1 (existential second-order) formula is one additionally having some existential quantifiers over second order variables, i.e. \exists R_0\ldots\exists R_m \phi, where \phi is a first-order formula. The fragment of second-order logic consisting only of existential second-order formulas is called existential second-order logic and abbreviated as ESO, as \Sigma^1_1, or even as ∃SO. The fragment of \Pi^1_1 formulas is defined dually, it is called universal second-order logic. More expressive fragments are defined for any ''k'' > 0 by mutual recursion: \Sigma^1_ has the form \exists R_0\ldots\exists R_m \phi, where \phi is a \Pi^1_k formula, and similar, \Pi^1_ has the form \forall R_0\ldots\forall R_m \phi, where \phi is a \Sigma^1_k formula. (See
analytical hierarchy Analytic or analytical may refer to: Chemistry * Analytical chemistry, the analysis of material samples to learn their chemical composition and structure * Analytical technique, a method that is used to determine the concentration of a chemica ...
for the analogous construction of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
.)


Semantics

The semantics of second-order logic establish the meaning of each sentence. Unlike first-order logic, which has only one standard semantics, there are two different semantics that are commonly used for second-order logic: standard semantics and Henkin semantics. In each of these semantics, the interpretations of the first-order quantifiers and the logical connectives are the same as in first-order logic. Only the ranges of quantifiers over second-order variables differ in the two types of semantics. In standard semantics, also called full semantics, the quantifiers range over ''all'' sets or functions of the appropriate sort. A model with this condition is called a full model, and these are the same as models in which the range of the second-order quantifiers is the powerset of the model's first-order part. Thus once the domain of the first-order variables is established, the meaning of the remaining quantifiers is fixed. It is these semantics that give second-order logic its expressive power, and they will be assumed for the remainder of this article.
Leon Henkin Leon Albert Henkin (April 19, 1921, Brooklyn, New York – November 1, 2006, Oakland, California) was an American logician, whose works played a strong role in the development of logic, particularly in the Type theory, theory of types. He was an ...
(1950) defined an alternative kind of semantics for second-order and higher-order theories, in which the meaning of the higher-order domains is partly determined by an explicit axiomatisation, drawing on
type theory In mathematics and theoretical computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of ...
, of the properties of the sets or functions ranged over. Henkin semantics is a kind of many-sorted first-order semantics, where there are a class of models of the axioms, instead of the semantics being fixed to just the standard model as in the standard semantics. A model in Henkin semantics will provide a set of sets or set of functions as the interpretation of higher-order domains, which may be a proper subset of all sets or functions of that sort. For his axiomatisation, Henkin proved that
Gödel's completeness theorem Gödel's completeness theorem is a fundamental theorem in mathematical logic that establishes a correspondence between semantics, semantic truth and syntactic Provability logic, provability in first-order logic. The completeness theorem applies ...
and
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
, which hold for first-order logic, carry over to second-order logic with Henkin semantics. Since also the Skolem–Löwenheim theorems hold for Henkin semantics,
Lindström's theorem In mathematical logic, Lindström's theorem (named after Swedish logician Per Lindström, who published it in 1969) states that first-order logic is the '' strongest logic'' (satisfying certain conditions, e.g. closure under classical negation) ...
imports that Henkin models are just ''disguised first-order models''. For theories such as second-order arithmetic, the existence of non-standard interpretations of higher-order domains isn't just a deficiency of the particular axiomatisation derived from type theory that Henkin used, but a necessary consequence of Gödel's incompleteness theorem: Henkin's axioms can't be supplemented further to ensure the standard interpretation is the only possible model. Henkin semantics are commonly used in the study of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
.
Jouko Väänänen Jouko Antero Väänänen (born September 3, 1950 in Rovaniemi, Lapland) is a Finnish mathematical logician known for his contributions to set theory,J. VäänänenSecond order logic or set theory? Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 18(1), 91-121, 201 ...
argued that the distinction between Henkin semantics and full semantics for second-order logic is analogous to the distinction between provability in ZFC and truth in '' V'', in that the former obeys model-theoretic properties like the Lowenheim-Skolem theorem and compactness, and the latter has categoricity phenomena. For example, "we cannot meaningfully ask whether the V as defined in \mathrm is the real V . But if we reformalize \mathrm inside \mathrm, then we can note that the reformalized \mathrm ... has countable models and hence cannot be categorical."


Expressive power

Second-order logic is more expressive than first-order logic. For example, if the domain is the set of all
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s, one can assert in first-order logic the existence of an additive inverse of each real number by writing ∀''x'' ∃''y'' (''x'' + ''y'' = 0) but one needs second-order logic to assert the least-upper-bound property for sets of real numbers, which states that every bounded, nonempty set of real numbers has a
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
. If the domain is the set of all real numbers, the following second-order sentence (split over two lines) expresses the least upper bound property: : :: This formula is a direct formalization of "every , set A ." It can be shown that any
ordered field In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. Basic examples of ordered fields are the rational numbers and the real numbers, both with their standard ord ...
that satisfies this property is isomorphic to the real number field. On the other hand, the set of first-order sentences valid in the reals has arbitrarily large models due to the compactness theorem. Thus the least-upper-bound property cannot be expressed by any set of sentences in first-order logic. (In fact, every real-closed field satisfies the same first-order sentences in the signature \langle +,\cdot,\le\rangle as the real numbers.) In second-order logic, it is possible to write formal sentences that say "the domain is
finite Finite may refer to: * Finite set, a set whose cardinality (number of elements) is some natural number * Finite verb, a verb form that has a subject, usually being inflected or marked for person and/or tense or aspect * "Finite", a song by Sara Gr ...
" or "the domain is of
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
." To say that the domain is finite, use the sentence that says that every
surjective In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function ) is a function such that, for every element of the function's codomain, there exists one element in the function's domain such that . In other words, for a f ...
function from the domain to itself is
injective In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function ) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements of its codomain; that is, implies (equivalently by contraposition, impl ...
. To say that the domain has countable cardinality, use the sentence that says that there is a
bijection In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
between every two infinite subsets of the domain. It follows from the
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
and the upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem that it is not possible to characterize finiteness or countability, respectively, in first-order logic. Certain fragments of second-order logic like ESO are also more expressive than first-order logic even though they are strictly less expressive than the full second-order logic. ESO also enjoys translation equivalence with some extensions of first-order logic that allow non-linear ordering of quantifier dependencies, like first-order logic extended with Henkin quantifiers,
Hintikka Kaarlo Jaakko Juhani Hintikka (; ; 12 January 1929 – 12 August 2015) was a Finnish philosopher and logician. Hintikka is regarded as the founder of formal epistemic logic and of game semantics for logic. Life and career Hintikka was born in He ...
and Sandu's independence-friendly logic, and Väänänen's dependence logic.


Deductive systems

A
deductive system A formal system is an abstract structure and formalization of an axiomatic system used for deducing, using rules of inference, theorems from axioms. In 1921, David Hilbert proposed to use formal systems as the foundation of knowledge in math ...
for a logic is a set of
inference rules Rules of inference are ways of deriving conclusions from premises. They are integral parts of formal logic, serving as norms of the logical structure of valid arguments. If an argument with true premises follows a rule of inference then the c ...
and logical axioms that determine which sequences of formulas constitute valid proofs. Several deductive systems can be used for second-order logic, although none can be complete for the standard semantics (see below). Each of these systems is
sound In physics, sound is a vibration that propagates as an acoustic wave through a transmission medium such as a gas, liquid or solid. In human physiology and psychology, sound is the ''reception'' of such waves and their ''perception'' by the br ...
, which means any sentence they can be used to prove is logically valid in the appropriate semantics. The weakest deductive system that can be used consists of a standard deductive system for first-order logic (such as
natural deduction In logic and proof theory, natural deduction is a kind of proof calculus in which logical reasoning is expressed by inference rules closely related to the "natural" way of reasoning. This contrasts with Hilbert-style systems, which instead use ...
) augmented with substitution rules for second-order terms. This deductive system is commonly used in the study of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
. The deductive systems considered by and add to the augmented first-order deductive scheme both comprehension axioms and choice axioms. These axioms are sound for standard second-order semantics. They are sound for Henkin semantics restricted to Henkin models satisfying the comprehension and choice axioms.


Non-reducibility to first-order logic

One might attempt to reduce the second-order theory of the real numbers, with full second-order semantics, to the first-order theory in the following way. First expand the domain from the set of all real numbers to a two-sorted domain, with the second sort containing all ''sets of'' real numbers. Add a new binary predicate to the language: the membership relation. Then sentences that were second-order become first-order, with the formerly second-order quantifiers ranging over the second sort instead. This reduction can be attempted in a one-sorted theory by adding unary predicates that tell whether an element is a number or a set, and taking the domain to be the union of the set of real numbers and the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of the real numbers. But notice that the domain was asserted to include ''all'' sets of real numbers. That requirement cannot be reduced to a first-order sentence, as the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
shows. That theorem implies that there is some
countably infinite In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
subset of the real numbers, whose members we will call ''internal numbers'', and some countably infinite collection of sets of internal numbers, whose members we will call "internal sets", such that the domain consisting of internal numbers and internal sets satisfies exactly the same first-order sentences as are satisfied by the domain of real numbers and sets of real numbers. In particular, it satisfies a sort of least-upper-bound axiom that says, in effect: Countability of the set of all internal numbers (in conjunction with the fact that those form a densely ordered set) implies that that set does not satisfy the full least-upper-bound axiom. Countability of the set of all ''internal'' sets implies that it is not the set of ''all'' subsets of the set of all ''internal'' numbers (since
Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
implies that the set of all subsets of a countably infinite set is an uncountably infinite set). This construction is closely related to Skolem's paradox. Thus the first-order theory of real numbers and sets of real numbers has many models, some of which are countable. The second-order theory of the real numbers has only one model, however. This follows from the classical theorem that there is only one Archimedean
complete ordered field In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one-dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every real ...
, along with the fact that all the axioms of an Archimedean complete ordered field are expressible in second-order logic. This shows that the second-order theory of the real numbers cannot be reduced to a first-order theory, in the sense that the second-order theory of the real numbers has only one model but the corresponding first-order theory has many models. There are more extreme examples showing that second-order logic with standard semantics is more expressive than first-order logic. There is a finite second-order theory whose only model is the real numbers if the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
holds and that has no model if the continuum hypothesis does not hold. This theory consists of a finite theory characterizing the real numbers as a complete Archimedean ordered field plus an axiom saying that the domain is of the first uncountable cardinality. This example illustrates that the question of whether a sentence in second-order logic is consistent is extremely subtle. Additional limitations of second-order logic are described in the next section.


Metalogical results

It is a corollary of Gödel's incompleteness theorem that there is no deductive system (that is, no notion of ''provability'') for second-order formulas that simultaneously satisfies these three desired attributes: * (
Soundness In logic and deductive reasoning, an argument is sound if it is both Validity (logic), valid in form and has no false premises. Soundness has a related meaning in mathematical logic, wherein a Formal system, formal system of logic is sound if and o ...
) Every provable second-order sentence is universally valid, i.e., true in all domains under standard semantics. * ( Completeness) Every universally valid second-order formula, under standard semantics, is provable. * (
Effectiveness Effectiveness or effectivity is the capability of producing a desired result or the ability to produce desired output. When something is deemed effective, it means it has an intended or expected outcome, or produces a deep, vivid impression. Et ...
) There is a proof-checking algorithm that can correctly decide whether a given sequence of symbols is a proof or not. This corollary is sometimes expressed by saying that second-order logic does not admit a complete
proof theory Proof theory is a major branchAccording to , proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. consists of four corresponding parts, with part D being about "Proof The ...
. In this respect second-order logic with standard semantics differs from first-order logic;
Quine Quine may refer to: * Quine (computing), a program that produces its source code as output * Quine's paradox, in logic * Quine (surname), people with the surname ** Willard Van Orman Quine (1908–2000), American philosopher and logician See al ...
pointed to the lack of a complete proof system as a reason for thinking of second-order logic as not ''logic'', properly speaking. As mentioned above, Henkin proved that the standard deductive system for first-order logic is sound, complete, and effective for second-order logic with Henkin semantics, and the deductive system with comprehension and choice principles is sound, complete, and effective for Henkin semantics using only models that satisfy these principles. The
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
and the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
do not hold for full models of second-order logic. They do hold however for Henkin models. Manzano, M., ''Model Theory'', trans. Ruy J. G. B. de Queiroz (
Oxford Oxford () is a City status in the United Kingdom, cathedral city and non-metropolitan district in Oxfordshire, England, of which it is the county town. The city is home to the University of Oxford, the List of oldest universities in continuou ...
:
Clarendon Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the publishing house of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world. Its first book was printed in Oxford in 1478, with the Press officially granted the legal right to print books ...
, 1999)
p. xi


History and disputed value

Predicate logic was introduced to the mathematical community by C. S. Peirce, who coined the term ''second-order logic'' and whose notation is most similar to the modern form (Putnam 1982). However, today most students of logic are more familiar with the works of
Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
, who published his work several years prior to Peirce but whose works remained less known until
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
and
Alfred North Whitehead Alfred North Whitehead (15 February 1861 – 30 December 1947) was an English mathematician and philosopher. He created the philosophical school known as process philosophy, which has been applied in a wide variety of disciplines, inclu ...
made them famous. Frege used different variables to distinguish quantification over objects from quantification over properties and sets; but he did not see himself as doing two different kinds of logic. After the discovery of
Russell's paradox In mathematical logic, Russell's paradox (also known as Russell's antinomy) is a set-theoretic paradox published by the British philosopher and mathematician, Bertrand Russell, in 1901. Russell's paradox shows that every set theory that contains ...
it was realized that something was wrong with his system. Eventually logicians found that restricting Frege's logic in various ways—to what is now called
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
—eliminated this problem: sets and properties cannot be quantified over in first-order logic alone. The now-standard hierarchy of orders of logics dates from this time. It was found that
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
could be formulated as an axiomatized system within the apparatus of first-order logic (at the cost of several kinds of completeness, but nothing so bad as Russell's paradox), and this was done (see
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
), as sets are vital for
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
.
Arithmetic Arithmetic is an elementary branch of mathematics that deals with numerical operations like addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. In a wider sense, it also includes exponentiation, extraction of roots, and taking logarithms. ...
,
mereology Mereology (; from Greek μέρος 'part' (root: μερε-, ''mere-'') and the suffix ''-logy'', 'study, discussion, science') is the philosophical study of part-whole relationships, also called ''parthood relationships''. As a branch of metaphys ...
, and a variety of other powerful logical theories could be formulated axiomatically without appeal to any more logical apparatus than first-order quantification, and this, along with Gödel and Skolem's adherence to first-order logic, led to a general decline in work in second (or any higher) order logic. This rejection was actively advanced by some logicians, most notably
W. V. Quine Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth centur ...
. Quine advanced the view that in predicate-language sentences like ''Fx'' the "''x''" is to be thought of as a variable or name denoting an object and hence can be quantified over, as in "For all things, it is the case that . . ." but the "''F''" is to be thought of as an ''abbreviation'' for an incomplete sentence, not the name of an object (not even of an
abstract object In philosophy and the arts, a fundamental distinction exists between abstract and concrete entities. While there is no universally accepted definition, common examples illustrate the difference: numbers, sets, and ideas are typically classif ...
like a property). For example, it might mean " . . . is a dog." But it makes no sense to think we can quantify over something like this. (Such a position is quite consistent with Frege's own arguments on the concept-object distinction). So to use a predicate as a variable is to have it occupy the place of a name, which only individual variables should occupy. This reasoning has been rejected by George Boolos. In recent years second-order logic has made something of a recovery, buoyed by Boolos' interpretation of second-order quantification as
plural quantification In mathematics and mathematical logic, logic, plural quantification is the theory that an individual Variable (mathematics), variable x may take on ''plural'', as well as singular, values. As well as substituting individual objects such as Alice, ...
over the same domain of objects as first-order quantification (Boolos 1984). Boolos furthermore points to the claimed
nonfirstorderizability In formal logic, nonfirstorderizability is the inability of a natural-language statement to be adequately captured by a formula of first-order logic. Specifically, a statement is nonfirstorderizable if there is no formula of first-order logic whic ...
of sentences such as "Some critics admire only each other" and "Some of Fianchetto's men went into the warehouse unaccompanied by anyone else", which he argues can only be expressed by the full force of second-order quantification. However, generalized quantification and partially ordered (or branching) quantification may suffice to express a certain class of purportedly nonfirstorderizable sentences as well and these do not appeal to second-order quantification.


Relation to computational complexity

The expressive power of various forms of second-order logic on finite structures is intimately tied to
computational complexity theory In theoretical computer science and mathematics, computational complexity theory focuses on classifying computational problems according to their resource usage, and explores the relationships between these classifications. A computational problem ...
. The field of
descriptive complexity Descriptive complexity is a branch of computational complexity theory and of finite model theory that characterizes complexity classes by the type of logic needed to express the formal language, languages in them. For example, PH (complexity), PH, ...
studies which computational
complexity class In computational complexity theory, a complexity class is a set (mathematics), set of computational problems "of related resource-based computational complexity, complexity". The two most commonly analyzed resources are time complexity, time and s ...
es can be characterized by the power of the logic needed to express languages (sets of finite strings) in them. A string ''w'' = ''w''1···''wn'' in a finite alphabet ''A'' can be represented by a finite structure with domain ''D'' = , unary predicates ''Pa'' for each ''a'' ∈ ''A'', satisfied by those indices ''i'' such that ''wi'' = ''a'', and additional predicates that serve to uniquely identify which index is which (typically, one takes the graph of the successor function on ''D'' or the order relation <, possibly with other arithmetic predicates). Conversely, the
Cayley table Named after the 19th-century United Kingdom, British mathematician Arthur Cayley, a Cayley table describes the structure of a finite group by arranging all the possible products of all the group's elements in a square table reminiscent of an additi ...
s of any finite structure (over a finite
signature A signature (; from , "to sign") is a depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and intent. Signatures are often, but not always, Handwriting, handwritt ...
) can be encoded by a finite string. This identification leads to the following characterizations of variants of second-order logic over finite structures: * REG (the
regular language In theoretical computer science and formal language theory, a regular language (also called a rational language) is a formal language that can be defined by a regular expression, in the strict sense in theoretical computer science (as opposed to ...
s) is the set of languages definable by monadic, second-order formulas ( Büchi-Elgot-Trakhtenbrot theorem, 1960) * NP is the set of languages definable by existential, second-order formulas (
Fagin's theorem Fagin's theorem is the oldest result of descriptive complexity theory, a branch of computational complexity theory that characterizes complexity classes in terms of logic-based descriptions of their problems rather than by the behavior of algorith ...
, 1974). *
co-NP In computational complexity theory, co-NP is a complexity class. A decision problem X is a member of co-NP if and only if its complement is in the complexity class NP. The class can be defined as follows: a decision problem is in co-NP if and o ...
is the set of languages definable by universal, second-order formulas. * PH is the set of languages definable by second-order formulas. *
PSPACE In computational complexity theory, PSPACE is the set of all decision problems that can be solved by a Turing machine using a polynomial amount of space. Formal definition If we denote by SPACE(''f''(''n'')), the set of all problems that can ...
is the set of languages definable by second-order formulas with an added
transitive closure In mathematics, the transitive closure of a homogeneous binary relation on a set (mathematics), set is the smallest Relation (mathematics), relation on that contains and is Transitive relation, transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be ...
operator. *
EXPTIME In computational complexity theory, the complexity class EXPTIME (sometimes called EXP or DEXPTIME) is the set of all decision problems that are solvable by a deterministic Turing machine in exponential time, i.e., in O(2''p''(''n'')) time, w ...
is the set of languages definable by second-order formulas with an added
least fixed point In order theory, a branch of mathematics, the least fixed point (lfp or LFP, sometimes also smallest fixed point) of a function from a partially ordered set ("poset" for short) to itself is the fixed point which is less than each other fixed po ...
operator. Relationships among these classes directly impact the relative expressiveness of the logics over finite structures; for example, if PH = PSPACE, then adding a transitive closure operator to second-order logic would not make it any more expressive over finite structures.


See also

*
First-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
*
Higher-order logic In mathematics and logic, a higher-order logic (abbreviated HOL) is a form of logic that is distinguished from first-order logic by additional quantifiers and, sometimes, stronger semantics. Higher-order logics with their standard semantics are m ...
*
Löwenheim number In mathematical logic the Löwenheim number of an abstract logic is the smallest cardinal number for which a weak downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem holds. They are named after Leopold Löwenheim, who proved that these exist for a very broad c ...
*
Omega language In formal language theory within theoretical computer science, an infinite word is an infinite-length sequence (specifically, an ω-length sequence) of symbols, and an ω-language is a set of infinite words. Here, ω refers to the first infinite o ...
*
Second-order propositional logic A second-order propositional logic is a propositional logic extended with quantification over propositions. A special case are the logics that allow second-order Boolean propositions, where quantifiers may range either just over the Boolean truth ...
*
Monadic second-order logic In mathematical logic, monadic second-order logic (MSO) is the fragment of second-order logic where the second-order quantification is limited to quantification over sets. It is particularly important in the logic of graphs, because of Courcelle's ...


Notes


References


Works cited

* * * * *


Further reading

* *. Reprinted in Boolos, ''Logic, Logic and Logic'', 1998. * * . Reprinted in Putnam, Hilary (1990), ''Realism with a Human Face'',
Harvard University Press Harvard University Press (HUP) is an academic publishing house established on January 13, 1913, as a division of Harvard University. It is a member of the Association of University Presses. Its director since 2017 is George Andreou. The pres ...

pp. 252–260
* {{Mathematical logic Systems of formal logic Charles Sanders Peirce fr:Logique d'ordre supérieur#Logique du second ordre