HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Revealed preference theory, pioneered by economist Paul Anthony Samuelson in 1938, is a method of analyzing choices made by individuals, mostly used for comparing the influence of policies on
consumer behavior Consumer behaviour is the study of individuals, groups, or organisations and all activities associated with the purchase, use and disposal of goods and services. It encompasses how the consumer's emotions, attitudes, and preferences affe ...
. Revealed preference models assume that the
preferences In psychology, economics and philosophy, preference is a technical term usually used in relation to choosing between alternatives. For example, someone prefers A over B if they would rather choose A than B. Preferences are central to decision the ...
of consumers can be revealed by their purchasing habits. Revealed preference theory arose because existing theories of consumer
demand In economics, demand is the quantity of a goods, good that consumers are willing and able to purchase at various prices during a given time. In economics "demand" for a commodity is not the same thing as "desire" for it. It refers to both the desi ...
were based on a diminishing
marginal rate of substitution In economics, the marginal rate of substitution (MRS) is the rate at which a consumer can give up some amount of one good in exchange for another good while maintaining the same level of utility. At equilibrium consumption levels (assuming no ext ...
(MRS). This diminishing MRS relied on the assumption that consumers make consumption decisions to maximise their
utility In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings. * In a normative context, utility refers to a goal or objective that we wish ...
. While utility maximisation was not a controversial assumption, the underlying utility functions could not be measured with great certainty. Revealed preference theory was a means to reconcile demand theory by defining utility functions by observing behaviour. Therefore, revealed preference is a way to infer preferences between available choices. It contrasts with attempts to directly measure preferences or utility, for example through stated preferences.


Definition and theory

Let there be two bundles of goods, a and b, available in a budget set B. If it is observed that a is chosen over b, then a is considered (directly) ''revealed preferred'' to b.


Two-dimensional example

If the budget set B is defined for two goods; X, Y, and determined by prices p, q and income m, then let bundle a be (x_,y_) \in B and bundle b be (x_,y_) \in B . This situation would typically be represented arithmetically by the inequality pX + qY \leq m and graphically by a budget line in the positive real numbers. Assuming strongly
monotonic In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of ord ...
preferences, only bundles that are graphically located on the budget line, i.e. bundles where px_ + qy_ = m and px_ + qy_ = m are satisfied, need to be considered. If, in this situation, it is observed that (x_,y_) is chosen over (x_,y_), it is concluded that (x_,y_) is (directly) revealed preferred to (x_,y_), which can be summarized as the
binary relation In mathematics, a binary relation associates some elements of one Set (mathematics), set called the ''domain'' with some elements of another set called the ''codomain''. Precisely, a binary relation over sets X and Y is a set of ordered pairs ...
(x_,y_) \succeq (x_,y_) or equivalently as \mathbf \succeq \mathbf.


The Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (WARP)

The Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference (WARP) is one of the criteria which needs to be satisfied in order to make sure that the consumer is consistent with their preferences. If a bundle of goods a is chosen over another bundle b when both are affordable, then the consumer reveals that they prefer a over b. WARP says that when preferences remain the same, there are no circumstances ( budget set) where the consumer prefers b over a. By choosing a over b when both bundles are affordable, the consumer reveals that their preferences are such that they will never choose b over a when both are affordable, even as prices vary. Formally: : \left.\begin \mathbf,\mathbf \in B\\ \mathbf \in C(B, \succeq) \\ \mathbf \in B' \\ \mathbf \in C(B', \succeq) \end\right\} ~\Rightarrow~ \mathbf \notin B' where \mathbf and \mathbf are arbitrary bundles and C (B, \succeq) \subset B is the set of bundles chosen in budget set B, given preference relation \succeq. In other words, if a is chosen over b in budget set B where both a and b are feasible bundles, but b is chosen when the consumer faces some other budget set B', then a is not a feasible bundle in budget set B'.


Completeness: The Strong Axiom of Revealed Preferences (SARP)

The strong axiom of revealed preferences (SARP) is equivalent to WARP, except that the choices A and B are not allowed to be either directly or indirectly revealed preferable to each other at the same time. Here A is considered ''indirectly'' revealed preferred to B if C exists such that A is directly revealed preferred to C, and C is directly revealed preferred to B. In mathematical terminology, this says that transitivity is preserved. Transitivity is useful as it can reveal additional information by comparing two separate bundles from budget constraints. It is often desirable in economic models to prevent such "loops" from happening, for example in order to model choices with
utility function In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings. * In a Normative economics, normative context, utility refers to a goal or ob ...
s (which have real-valued outputs and are thus transitive). One way to do so is to impose completeness on the revealed preference relation with regards to the choices at large, i.e. without any price considerations or affordability constraints. This is useful because when evaluating as standalone options, it is ''directly'' obvious which is preferred or indifferent to which other. Using the weak axiom then prevents two choices from being preferred over each other at the same time; thus it would be impossible for "loops" to form. Another way to solve this is to impose SARP, which ensures transitivity. This is characterised by taking the
transitive closure In mathematics, the transitive closure of a homogeneous binary relation on a set (mathematics), set is the smallest Relation (mathematics), relation on that contains and is Transitive relation, transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be ...
of direct revealed preferences and require that it is antisymmetric, i.e. if A is revealed preferred to B (directly or indirectly), then B is not revealed preferred to A (directly or indirectly). These are two different approaches to solving the issue; completeness is concerned with the input (domain) of the choice functions; while the strong axiom imposes conditions on the output.


Generalised Axiom of Revealed Preference (GARP)

The Generalised axiom of revealed preference (GARP) is a generalisation of SARP. It is the final criteria required so that constancy may be satisfied to ensure consumers preferences do not change. This axiom accounts for conditions in which two or more consumption bundles satisfy equal levels of utility, given that the price level remains constant. It covers circumstances in which utility maximisation is achieved by more than one consumption bundle. A set of data satisfies GARP if x^i R x^j implies not x^jP^0x^i . This establishes that if consumption bundle x^i is revealed preferred to x^j , then the expenditure necessary to acquire bundle x^j given that prices remain constant, cannot be more than the expenditure necessary to acquire bundle x^i . To satisfy GARP, a dataset must also not establish a preference cycle. Therefore, when considering the bundles , the revealed preference bundle must be an acyclic order pair as such, If A\succeq B and B \succeq C , then B \nsucceq A and A \succeq C thus ruling out “preference cycles” while still holding transitivity. As GARP is closely related to SARP, it is very easy to demonstrate that each condition of SARP can imply GARP, however, GARP does not imply SARP. This is a result of the condition in which GARP is compatible with multivalued demand functions, whereas SARP is only compatible with single valued demand functions. As such, GARP permits for flat sections within indifference curves, as stated by Hal R Varian (1982).


Afriat's Theorem

Afriat's Theorem, introduced by economist Sydney Afriat in 1967, extends GARP by proving that a finite dataset of observed choices can be explained by a
utility function In economics, utility is a measure of a certain person's satisfaction from a certain state of the world. Over time, the term has been used with at least two meanings. * In a Normative economics, normative context, utility refers to a goal or ob ...
. Specifically, it states that a set of price vectors ''p''i and quantity vectors ''x''i (for ''i'' = 1, 2, ..., ''n'') satisfies GARP if and only if there exists a continuous, increasing, and concave utility function ''u(x)'' such that each ''x''i maximizes ''u(x)'' under the budget constraint ''p''i · ''x'' ≤ ''p''i · ''x''i. The theorem provides a practical test: if GARP holds, there exist utility levels ''u''i and positive weights ''λ''i satisfying the inequalities ''u''i - ''u''j ≤ ''λ''j (''p''j · (''x''i - ''x''j)) for all ''i'', ''j''. These ''Afriat inequalities'' allow construction of the utility function directly from the data, unlike earlier axioms like SARP, which only prove existence for infinite datasets. For instance, if two bundles both maximize utility at the same budget (as in the GARP figure), Afriat's Theorem ensures a utility function exists, even where SARP fails. This result is widely used in
econometrics Econometrics is an application of statistical methods to economic data in order to give empirical content to economic relationships. M. Hashem Pesaran (1987). "Econometrics", '' The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics'', v. 2, p. 8 p. 8 ...
to test rationality and build preferences from empirical data.


Applications

Revealed preference theory has been used in numerous applications, including college rankings in the U.S.


Criticism

Several economists criticised the theory of revealed preferences for different reasons. # Stanley Wong claimed that revealed preference theory was a failed research program. In 1938 Samuelson presented revealed preference theory as an alternative to utility theory, while in 1950, Samuelson took the demonstrated equivalence of the two theories as a vindication for his position, rather than as a refutation. # If there exist only an apple and an orange, and an orange is picked, then one can definitely say that an orange is revealed preferred to an apple. In the real world, when it is observed that a consumer purchased an orange, it is impossible to say what good or set of goods or behavioural options were discarded in preference of purchasing an orange. In this sense, preference is not revealed at all in the sense of ordinal utility. # The revealed preference theory assumes that the preference scale remains constant over time. Were this not the case all that can be stated is that an action, at a specific point of time, reveals part of a person's preference scale at that time. There is no warrant for assuming that it remains constant from one point of time to another. The "revealed preference" theorists assume constancy in addition to consistent behaviour ("rationality"). Consistency means that a person maintains a transitive order of rank on his preference scale (if A is preferred to B and B is preferred to C, then A is preferred to C). But the revealed preference procedure does not rest on this assumption so much as on an assumption of constancy—that an individual maintains the same value scale over time. While the former might be called irrational, there is certainly nothing irrational about someone's value scales changing through time. It is claimed that no valid theory can be built on a constancy assumption.Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics
article by Murray N. Rothbard, 2006. Citing Mises at Human Action.
# The inability to define or measure preferences independently of 'revealed-preferences' leads some authors to see the concept as a tautological fallacy. See, inter alia,
Amartya Sen Amartya Kumar Sen (; born 3 November 1933) is an Indian economist and philosopher. Sen has taught and worked in England and the United States since 1972. In 1998, Sen received the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences for his contributions ...
’s critiques in a series of articles: “Behaviour and the concept of preference” (Sen 1973), “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory” (Sen 1977), “Internal Consistency of Choice” (Sen 1993), “Maximization and the Act of Choice” (Sen 1997), and his book 'Rationality and Freedom' (Sen 2002).


See also

*
Choice modelling Choice modelling attempts to model the decision process of an individual or segment via revealed preferences or stated preferences made in a particular context or contexts. Typically, it attempts to use discrete choices (A over B; B over A, B & C) ...
* Conjoint analysis *
Contingent valuation Contingent valuation is a survey-based economic technique for the valuation of non- market resources, such as environmental preservation or the impact of externalities like pollution. While these resources do give people utility, certain aspec ...
or stated preference methods * Foot voting * Hedonic regression *
Induced demand In economics, induced demand – related to latent demand and generated demandSchneider, Benjamin (September 6, 2018"CityLab University: Induced Demand"'' CityLab'' – is the phenomenon whereby an increase in supply results in a decline ...
* Random utility model - an extension of revealed preference theory for agents whose choices are random.


Notes


References

* * Section 8.7


External links


Revealed Preference
review by Hal R. Varian, 2005, prepared for ''Samuelsonian Economics and the 21st Century''.
Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory
book by
Ariel Rubinstein Ariel Rubinstein (Hebrew: אריאל רובינשטיין; born April 13, 1951) is an Israeli economist who works in economic theory, game theory and bounded rationality. Biography Ariel Rubinstein is a professor of economics at the School of Ec ...
, 2005. {{DEFAULTSORT:Revealed Preference Consumer theory Evaluation methods Public policy research