
In mathematics, Pappus's hexagon theorem (attributed to
Pappus of Alexandria) states that
*given one set of
collinear
In geometry, collinearity of a set of points is the property of their lying on a single line. A set of points with this property is said to be collinear (sometimes spelled as colinear). In greater generality, the term has been used for aligned o ...
points
and another set of collinear points
then the intersection points
of
line pairs
and
and
and
are
collinear
In geometry, collinearity of a set of points is the property of their lying on a single line. A set of points with this property is said to be collinear (sometimes spelled as colinear). In greater generality, the term has been used for aligned o ...
, lying on the ''Pappus line''. These three points are the points of intersection of the "opposite" sides of the hexagon
.
It holds in a
projective plane over any field, but fails for projective planes over any noncommutative
division ring. Projective planes in which the "theorem" is valid are called pappian planes.
If one restricts the projective plane such that the Pappus line
is the line at infinity, one gets the ''affine version'' of Pappus's theorem shown in the second diagram.
If the Pappus line
and the lines
have a point in common, one gets the so-called little version of Pappus's theorem.
The
dual
Dual or Duals may refer to:
Paired/two things
* Dual (mathematics), a notion of paired concepts that mirror one another
** Dual (category theory), a formalization of mathematical duality
*** see more cases in :Duality theories
* Dual (grammatical ...
of this
incidence theorem
In projective geometry, an intersection theorem or incidence theorem is a statement concerning an incidence structure – consisting of points, lines, and possibly higher-dimensional objects and their incidences – together with a pair of objects ...
states that given one set of
concurrent lines , and another set of concurrent lines
, then the lines
defined by pairs of points resulting from pairs of intersections
and
and
and
are concurrent. (''Concurrent'' means that the lines pass through one point.)
Pappus's theorem is a
special case of
Pascal's theorem for a conic—the
limiting case when the conic
degenerates into 2 straight lines. Pascal's theorem is in turn a special case of the
Cayley–Bacharach theorem.
The
Pappus configuration is the
configuration of 9 lines and 9 points that occurs in Pappus's theorem, with each line meeting 3 of the points and each point meeting 3 lines. In general, the Pappus line does not pass through the point of intersection of
and
. This configuration is
self dual. Since, in particular, the lines
have the properties of the lines
of the dual theorem, and collinearity of
is equivalent to concurrence of
, the dual theorem is therefore just the same as the theorem itself. The
Levi graph of the Pappus configuration is the
Pappus graph, a
bipartite
Bipartite may refer to:
* 2 (number)
* Bipartite (theology), a philosophical term describing the human duality of body and soul
* Bipartite graph, in mathematics, a graph in which the vertices are partitioned into two sets and every edge has an en ...
distance-regular graph with 18 vertices and 27 edges.
Proof: affine form

If the affine form of the statement can be proven, then the projective form of Pappus's theorem is proven, as the extension of a pappian plane to a projective plane is unique.
Because of the parallelity in an affine plane one has to distinct two cases:
and
. The key for a simple proof is the possibility for introducing a "suitable" coordinate system:
Case 1: The lines
intersect at point
.
In this case coordinates are introduced, such that
(see diagram).
have the coordinates
.
From the parallelity of the lines
one gets
and the parallelity of the lines
yields
. Hence line
has slope
and is parallel line
.
Case 2:
(little theorem).
In this case the coordinates are chosen such that
. From the parallelity of
and
one gets
and
, respectively, and at least the parallelity
.
Proof with homogeneous coordinates
Choose homogeneous coordinates with
:
.
On the lines
, given by
, take the points
to be
:
for some
. The three lines
are
, so they pass through the same point
if and only if
. The condition for the three lines
and
with equations
to pass through the same point
is
. So this last set of three lines is concurrent if all the other eight sets are because multiplication is commutative, so
. Equivalently,
are collinear.
The proof above also shows that for Pappus's theorem to hold for a projective space over a division ring it is both sufficient and necessary that the division ring is a (commutative) field. German mathematician
Gerhard Hessenberg proved that Pappus's theorem implies
Desargues's theorem.
In general, Pappus's theorem holds for some projective plane if and only if it is a projective plane over a commutative field. The projective planes in which Pappus's theorem does not hold are
Desarguesian projective planes over noncommutative division rings, and
non-Desarguesian planes.
The proof is invalid if
happen to be collinear. In that case an alternative proof can be provided, for example, using a different projective reference.
Dual theorem
Because of the
principle of duality for projective planes the dual theorem of Pappus is true:
If 6 lines
are chosen alternately from two
pencils with centers
, the lines
:
:
:
are concurrent, that means: they have a point
in common.
The left diagram shows the projective version, the right one an affine version, where the points
are points at infinity. If point
is on the line
than one gets the "dual little theorem" of Pappus' theorem.
Pappus-dual-proj-ev.svg, dual theorem: projective form
Pappus-dual-aff-ev.svg, dual theorem: affine form
If in the affine version of the dual "little theorem" point
is a point at infinity too, one gets
Thomsen's theorem, a statement on 6 points on the sides of a triangle (see diagram). The Thomsen figure plays an essential role coordinatising an axiomatic defined projective plane. The proof of the closure of Thomsen's figure is covered by the proof for the "little theorem", given above. But there exists a simple direct proof, too:
Because the statement of Thomsen's theorem (the closure of the figure) uses only the terms ''connect, intersect'' and ''parallel'', the statement is
affinely invariant, and one can introduce coordinates such that
(see right diagram). The starting point of the sequence of chords is
One easily verifies the coordinates of the points given in the diagram, which shows: the last point coincides with the first point.
Thomsen-kl-d-pap-ev.svg, ''Thomsen figure'' (points of the triangle ) as dual theorem of the little theorem of Pappus ( is at infinity, too !).
Thomsen-beweis.svg, Thomsen figure: proof
Other statements of the theorem
In addition to the above characterizations of Pappus's theorem and its dual, the following are equivalent statements:
* If the six vertices of a hexagon lie alternately on two lines, then the three points of intersection of pairs of opposite sides are collinear.
* Arranged in a matrix of nine points (as in the figure and description above) and thought of as evaluating a
permanent, if the first two rows and the six "diagonal" triads are collinear, then the third row is collinear.
::
:That is, if
are lines, then Pappus's theorem states that
must be a line. Also, note that the same matrix formulation applies to the dual form of the theorem when
''etc.'' are triples of concurrent lines.
[Coxeter, p. 233]
* Given three distinct points on each of two distinct lines, pair each point on one of the lines with one from the other line, then the joins of points not paired will meet in (opposite) pairs at points along a line.
* If two triangles are
perspective in at least two different ways, then they are perspective in three ways.
* If
and
are concurrent and
and
are concurrent, then
and
are concurrent.
Origins
In its earliest known form, Pappus's Theorem is Propositions 138, 139, 141, and 143 of Book VII of
Pappus's ''Collection''. These are Lemmas XII, XIII, XV, and XVII in the part of Book VII consisting of lemmas to the first of the three books of
Euclid's ''Porisms.''
The lemmas are proved in terms of what today is known as the cross ratio of four collinear points. Three earlier lemmas are used. The first of these, Lemma III, has the diagram below (which uses Pappus's lettering, with G for Γ, D for Δ, J for Θ, and L for Λ).
:

Here three concurrent straight lines, AB, AG, and AD, are crossed by two lines, JB and JE, which concur at J.
Also KL is drawn parallel to AZ.
Then
:KJ : JL :: (KJ : AG & AG : JL) :: (JD : GD & BG : JB).
These proportions might be written today as equations:
[A reason for using the notation above is that, for the ancient Greeks, a ratio is not a number or a geometrical object. We may think of ratio today as an equivalence class of pairs of geometrical objects. Also, equality for the Greeks is what we might today call congruence. In particular, distinct line segments may be equal. Ratios are not ''equal'' in this sense; but they may be the ''same.'']
:KJ/JL = (KJ/AG)(AG/JL) = (JD/GD)(BG/JB).
The last compound ratio (namely JD : GD & BG : JB) is what is known today as the
cross ratio of the collinear points J, G, D, and B in that order; it is denoted today by (J, G; D, B). So we have shown that this is independent of the choice of the particular straight line JD that crosses the three straight lines that concur at A. In particular
:(J, G; D, B) = (J, Z; H, E).
It does not matter on which side of A the straight line JE falls. In particular, the situation may be as in the next diagram, which is the diagram for Lemma X.
:

Just as before, we have (J, G; D, B) = (J, Z; H, E). Pappus does not explicitly prove this; but Lemma X is a converse, namely that if these two cross ratios are the same, and the straight lines BE and DH cross at A, then the points G, A, and Z must be collinear.
What we showed originally can be written as (J, ∞; K, L) = (J, G; D, B), with ∞ taking the place of the (nonexistent) intersection of JK and AG. Pappus shows this, in effect, in Lemma XI, whose diagram, however, has different lettering:
:

What Pappus shows is DE.ZH : EZ.HD :: GB : BE, which we may write as
:(D, Z; E, H) = (∞, B; E, G).
The diagram for Lemma XII is:
:

The diagram for Lemma XIII is the same, but BA and DG, extended, meet at N. In any case, considering straight lines through G as cut by the three straight lines through A, (and accepting that equations of cross ratios remain valid after permutation of the entries,) we have by Lemma III or XI
:(G, J; E, H) = (G, D; ∞ Z).
Considering straight lines through D as cut by the three straight lines through B, we have
:(L, D; E, K) = (G, D; ∞ Z).
Thus (E, H; J, G) = (E, K; D, L), so by Lemma X, the points H, M, and K are collinear. That is, the points of intersection of the pairs of opposite sides of the hexagon ADEGBZ are collinear.
Lemmas XV and XVII are that, if the point M is determined as the intersection of HK and BG, then the points A, M, and D are collinear. That is, the points of intersection of the pairs of opposite sides of the hexagon BEKHZG are collinear.
Notes
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*{{Citation , last1=Whicher , first1=Olive , title=Projective Geometry , publisher=Rudolph Steiner Press , year=1971 , isbn=0-85440-245-4
External links
Pappus's hexagon theoremat
cut-the-knot
Dual to Pappus's hexagon theoremat
cut-the-knot
Pappus’s Theorem: Nine proofs and three variations Theorems in projective geometry
Euclidean plane geometry
Articles containing proofs