The many forms of IIA
In individual choice theory, IIA sometimes refers toVoting theory
In voting systems, independence from irrelevant alternatives is often interpreted as, if one candidate (''X'') would win an election, and if a new candidate (''Y'') were added to the ballot, then either ''X'' or ''Y'' would win the election.Local independence
A criterion weaker than IIA proposed by H. Peyton Young and A. Levenglick is called local independence from irrelevant alternatives (LIIA). LIIA requires that both of the following conditions always hold: *If the option that finished in last place is deleted from all the votes, then the order of finish of the remaining options must not change. (The winner must not change.) *If the winning option is deleted from all the votes, the order of finish of the remaining options must not change. (The option that finished in second place must become the winner.) An equivalent way to express LIIA is that if a subset of the options are in consecutive positions in the order of finish, then their relative order of finish must not change if all other options are deleted from the votes. For example, if all options except those in 3rd, 4th and 5th place are deleted, the option that finished 3rd must win, the 4th must finish second, and 5th must finish 3rd. Another equivalent way to express LIIA is that if two options are consecutive in the order of finish, the one that finished higher must win if all options except those two are deleted from the votes. LIIA is weaker than IIA because satisfaction of IIA implies satisfaction of LIIA, but not vice versa. Despite being a weaker criterion (i.e. easier to satisfy) than IIA, LIIA is satisfied by very few voting methods. These include Kemeny-Young and ranked pairs, but not Schulze. Just as with IIA, LIIA compliance for rating methods such asCriticism of IIA
IIA is largely incompatible with the majority criterion unless there are only two alternatives. Consider a scenario in which there are three candidates ''A'', ''B'', & ''C'', and the voters' preferences are as follows: :25% of the voters prefer ''A'' over ''B'', and ''B'' over ''C''. (''A''>''B''>''C'') :40% of the voters prefer ''B'' over ''C'', and ''C'' over ''A''. (''B''>''C''>''A'') :35% of the voters prefer ''C'' over ''A'', and ''A'' over ''B''. (''C''>''A''>''B'') (These are preferences, not votes, and thus are independent of the voting method.) 75% prefer ''C'' over ''A'', 65% prefer ''B'' over ''C'', and 60% prefer ''A'' over ''B''. The presence of this societal intransitivity is the voting paradox. Regardless of the voting method and the actual votes, there are only three cases to consider: *Case 1: ''A'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 75% who prefer ''C'' over ''A'' would elect ''C'' if ''B'' were not a candidate. *Case 2: ''B'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 60% who prefer ''A'' over ''B'' would elect ''A'' if ''C'' were not a candidate. *Case 3: ''C'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 65% who prefer ''B'' over ''C'' would elect ''B'' if ''A'' were not a candidate. To show failure, it is only assumed at least possible that enough voters in the majority might cast a minimally positive vote for their preferred candidate when there are only two candidates, rather than abstain. Most ranked ballot methods and Plurality voting satisfy the Majority Criterion, and therefore fail IIA automatically by the example above. Meanwhile, passage of IIA by Approval and Range voting requires in certain cases that voters in the majority are necessarily excluded from voting (they are assumed to necessarily abstain in a two candidate race, despite having a meaningful preference between the alternatives). So even if IIA is desirable, requiring its satisfaction seems to allow only voting methods that are undesirable in some other way, such as treating one of the voters as a dictator. Thus the goal must be to find which voting methods are best, rather than which are perfect. An argument can be made that IIA is itself undesirable. IIA assumes that when deciding whether ''A'' is likely to be better than ''B'', information about voters' preferences regarding ''C'' is irrelevant and should not make a difference. However, the heuristic that leads to majority rule when there are only two options is that the larger the number of people who think one option is better than the other, the greater the likelihood that it is better, all else being equal (see Condorcet's Jury Theorem). A majority is more likely than the opposing minority to be right about which of the two candidates is better, all else being equal, hence the use of majority rule. The same heuristic implies that the larger the majority, the more likely it is that they are right. It would seem to also imply that when there is more than one majority, larger majorities are more likely to be right than smaller majorities. Assuming this is so, the 75% who prefer ''C'' over ''A'' and the 65% who prefer ''B'' over ''C'' are more likely to be right than the 60% who prefer ''A'' over ''B'', and since it is not possible for all three majorities to be right, the smaller majority (who prefer ''A'' over ''B'') are more likely to be wrong, and less likely than their opposing minority to be right. Rather than being irrelevant to whether ''A'' is better than ''B'', the additional information about the voters' preferences regarding ''C'' provides a strong hint that this is a situation where all else is not equal.In social choice
From Kenneth Arrow, each "voter" ''i'' in the society has an ordering Ri that ranks the (conceivable) objects of social choice—''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' in simplest case—from high to low. An ''aggregation rule'' (''voting rule'') in turn maps each ''profile'' or tuple (R1, ...,Rn) of voter preferences (orderings) to a ''social ordering'' R that determines the social preference (ranking) of ''x'', ''y'', and ''z''. Arrow's IIA requires that whenever a pair of alternatives is ranked the same way in two preference profiles (over the same choice set), then the aggregation rule must order these alternatives identically across the two profiles. For example, suppose an aggregation rule ranks ''a'' above ''b'' at the profile given by *(''acbd'', ''dbac''), (i.e., the first individual prefers ''a'' first, ''c'' second, ''b'' third, ''d'' last; the second individual prefers ''d'' first, ..., and ''c'' last). Then, if it satisfies IIA, it must rank ''a'' above ''b'' at the following three profiles: *(''abcd'', ') *(''abcd'', ') *(''acdb'', '). The last two forms of profiles (placing the two at the top; and placing the two at the top and bottom) are especially useful in the proofs of theorems involving IIA. Arrow'sExamples
Borda count
In a Borda count election, 5 voters rank 5 alternatives 'A'', ''B'', ''C'', ''D'', ''E'' 3 voters rank ''B''>''C''>''D''>''E''">'A''>''B''>''C''>''D''>''E'' 1 voter ranks ''D''>''E''>''B''>''A''">'C''>''D''>''E''>''B''>''A'' 1 voter ranks ''C''>''D''>''B''>''A''">'E''>''C''>''D''>''B''>''A'' Borda count (''a''=0, ''b''=1): ''C''=13, ''A''=12, ''B''=11, ''D''=8, ''E''=6. ''C'' wins. Now, the voter who ranks ''D''>''E''>''B''>''A''">'C''>''D''>''E''>''B''>''A''instead ranks ''B''>''E''>''D''>''A''">'C''>''B''>''E''>''D''>''A'' and the voter who ranks ''C''>''D''>''B''>''A''">'E''>''C''>''D''>''B''>''A''instead ranks ''C''>''B''>''D''>''A''">'E''>''C''>''B''>''D''>''A'' They change their preferences only over the pairs 'B'', ''D'' 'B'', ''E''and 'D'', ''E'' The new Borda count: ''B''=14, ''C''=13, ''A''=12, ''E''=6, ''D''=5. ''B'' wins. The social choice has changed the ranking of 'B'', ''A''and 'B'', ''C'' The changes in the social choice ranking are dependent on irrelevant changes in the preference profile. In particular, ''B'' now wins instead of ''C'', even though no voter changed their preference over 'B'', ''C''=Borda count and strategic voting
= Consider an election in which there are three candidates, ''A'', ''B'', and ''C'', and only two voters. Each voter ranks the candidates in order of preference. The highest ranked candidate in a voter's preference is given 2 points, the second highest 1, and the lowest ranked 0; the overall ranking of a candidate is determined by the total score it gets; the highest ranked candidate wins. Considering two profiles: *In profiles 1 and 2, the first voter casts his votes in the order ''BAC'', so ''B'' receives 2 points, ''A'' receives 1, and ''C'' receives 0 from this voter. *In profile 1, the second voter votes ''ACB'', so ''A'' will win outright (the total scores: ''A'' 3, ''B'' 2, ''C'' 1). *In profile 2, the second voter votes ''ABC'', so ''A'' and ''B'' will tie (the total scores: ''A'' 3, ''B'' 3, ''C'' 0). Thus, if the second voter wishes ''A'' to be elected, he had better vote ''ACB'' regardless of his actual opinion of ''C'' and ''B''. This violates the idea of "independence from irrelevant alternatives" because the voter's comparative opinion of ''C'' and ''B'' affects whether ''A'' is elected or not. In both profiles, the rankings of ''A'' relative to ''B'' are the same for each voter, but the social rankings of ''A'' relative to ''B'' are different.Copeland
This example shows that Copeland's method violates IIA. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D with 6 voters with the following preferences: The results would be tabulated as follows: * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the column caption to the one in the row caption * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the row caption to the one in the column caption Result: A has two wins and one defeat, while no other candidate has more wins than defeats. Thus, A is elected Copeland winner.= Change of irrelevant preferences
= Now, assume all voters would raise D over B and C without changing the order of A and D. The preferences of the voters would now be: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: D wins against all three opponents. Thus, D is elected Copeland winner.= Conclusion
= The voters changed only their preference orders over B, C and D. As a result, the outcome order of D and A changed. A turned from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, Copeland's method fails the IIA criterion.Instant-runoff voting
In anKemeny–Young method
This example shows that the Kemeny–Young method violates the IIA criterion. Assume three candidates A, B and C with 7 voters and the following preferences: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: The ranking scores of all possible rankings are: Result: The ranking A > B > C has the highest ranking score. Thus, A wins ahead of B and C.= Change of irrelevant preferences
= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > C > A would change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: The ranking scores of all possible rankings are: Result: The ranking C > A > B has the highest ranking score. Thus, C wins ahead of A and B.= Conclusion
= The two voters changed only their preferences over B and C, but this resulted in a change of the order of A and C in the result, turning A from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Kemeny-Young method fails the IIA criterion.Minimax
This example shows that the Minimax method violates the IIA criterion. Assume four candidates A, B and C and 13 voters with the following preferences: Since all preferences are strict rankings (no equals are present), all three Minimax methods (winning votes, margins and pairwise opposite) elect the same winners. The results would be tabulated as follows: * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the column caption to the one in the row caption * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the row caption to the one in the column caption Result: A has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, A is elected Minimax winner.= Change of irrelevant preferences
= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > A > C change the preferences over the pair A and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: Now, B has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, B is elected Minimax winner.= Conclusion
= So, by changing the order of A and C in the preferences of some voters, the order of A and B in the result changed. B is turned from loser to winner without any change of the voters' preferences regarding B. Thus, the Minimax method fails the IIA criterion.Plurality voting system
In aRanked pairs
This example shows that the Ranked pairs method violates the IIA criterion. Assume three candidates A, B and C and 7 voters with the following preferences: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: A > B and B > C are locked in (and C > A cannot be locked in after that), so the full ranking is A > B > C. Thus, A is elected Ranked pairs winner.= Change of irrelevant preferences
= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > C > A change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: All three duels are locked in, so the full ranking is C > A > B. Thus, the Condorcet winner C is elected Ranked pairs winner.= Conclusion
= So, by changing their preferences over B and C, the two voters changed the order of A and C in the result, turning A from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Ranked pairs method fails the IIA criterion.Schulze method
This example shows that the Schulze method violates the IIA criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D and 12 voters with the following preferences: The pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified, e.g. the path D > A > B is stronger than the direct path D > B (which is nullified, since it is a tie). Result: The full ranking is C > D > A > B. Thus, C is elected Schulze winner and D is preferred over A.= Change of irrelevant preferences
= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences C > B > D > A change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: Hence, the pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified: Result: Now, the full ranking is A > B > C > D. Thus, A is elected Schulze winner and is preferred over D.= Conclusion
= So, by changing their preferences over B and C, the two voters changed the order of A and D in the result, turning A from loser to winner without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Schulze method fails the IIA criterion.Two-round system
A probable example of the two-round system failing this criterion was theCriticisms of the IIA assumption
IIA implies that adding another option or changing the characteristics of a third option does not affect the relative odds between the two options considered. This implication is not realistic for applications with similar options. Consider the Red Bus/Blue Bus example, due to Daniel McFadden. Commuter John Doe faces a decision between taking a car or a red bus. Suppose he chooses between these two options with equal probability on a given day (because of weather or whim). The odds ratio between car and red bus then equals 1:1. Now add a third alternative: blue bus. If Doe does not care about bus color, we would expect the probability of car to remain .5, while the probability of each of the two bus types would be 0.25. But IIA rules that out. It says that the new choice must not change the odds ratio of 1:1 between car and red bus. Since Doe's indifference to color requires the odds of red and blue bus to be equal, the new probabilities must be: car 0.33, red bus 0.33, blue bus 0.33. The overall probability of car travel has fallen from .5 to .33, which is absurd. The problem with the IIA axiom is that it takes no account of the fact that red bus and blue bus are perfect substitutes. The failure of this assumption has also been observed in practice, for example in the opinion polling for the 2019 European Elections held in the United Kingdom. In one survey, 21% of potential voters expressed support for the Labour Party under the scenario where there were three smaller Anti-Brexit parties to choose from, but under a scenario where two of those three parties did not stand candidates, the support for Labour dropped to 18%. This means at least 3% of potential voters stopped supporting their preferred party when a less preferred party dropped out.In econometrics
IIA is a direct consequence of the assumptions underlying the multinomial logit and the conditional logit models in econometrics. If these models are used in situations which in fact violate independence (such as multicandidate elections in which preferences exhibit cycling or situations mimicking the Red Bus/Blue Bus example given above) then these estimators become invalid. Many modeling advances have been motivated by a desire to alleviate the concerns raised by IIA. Generalized extreme value,Choice under uncertainty
In the expected utility theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern, four axioms together imply that individuals act in situations of risk as if they maximize the expected value of a utility function. One of the axioms is an independence axiom analogous to the IIA axiom: :If , then for any and , :: where ''p'' is a probability, ''pL''+(1-''p'')''N'' means a gamble with probability ''p'' of yielding ''L'' and probability (1-''p'') of yielding ''N'', and means that ''M'' is preferred over ''L''. This axiom says that if one outcome (or lottery ticket) ''L'' is considered to be not as good as another (''M''), then having a chance with probability ''p'' of receiving ''L'' rather than ''N'' is considered to be not as good as having a chance with probability ''p'' of receiving ''M'' rather than ''N''.In nature
Natural selection can favor animals' non-IIA-type choices, thought to be due to occasional availability of foodstuffs, according to a study published in January 2014.See also
* Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives * Luce's choice axiom * Sure-thing principle *Footnotes
References
* * * * * Discusses and deduces the not always recognized differences between various formulations of IIA.Further reading
* * {{voting systems Electoral system criteria Econometric modeling Social choice theory