Lindley's paradox is a
counterintuitive
A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true or apparently true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictor ...
situation in
statistics
Statistics (from German language, German: ', "description of a State (polity), state, a country") is the discipline that concerns the collection, organization, analysis, interpretation, and presentation of data. In applying statistics to a s ...
in which the
Bayesian
Thomas Bayes ( ; c. 1701 – 1761) was an English statistician, philosopher, and Presbyterian minister.
Bayesian ( or ) may be either any of a range of concepts and approaches that relate to statistical methods based on Bayes' theorem
Bayes ...
and
frequentist
Frequentist inference is a type of statistical inference based in frequentist probability, which treats “probability” in equivalent terms to “frequency” and draws conclusions from sample-data by means of emphasizing the frequency or pro ...
approaches to a
hypothesis testing
A statistical hypothesis test is a method of statistical inference used to decide whether the data provide sufficient evidence to reject a particular hypothesis. A statistical hypothesis test typically involves a calculation of a test statistic. T ...
problem give different results for certain choices of the
prior distribution
A prior probability distribution of an uncertain quantity, simply called the prior, is its assumed probability distribution before some evidence is taken into account. For example, the prior could be the probability distribution representing the ...
. The problem of the disagreement between the two approaches was discussed in
Harold Jeffreys
Sir Harold Jeffreys, FRS (22 April 1891 – 18 March 1989) was a British geophysicist who made significant contributions to mathematics and statistics. His book, ''Theory of Probability'', which was first published in 1939, played an importan ...
' 1939 textbook; it became known as Lindley's paradox after
Dennis Lindley
Dennis Victor Lindley (25 July 1923 – 14 December 2013) was an English statistician, decision theorist and leading advocate of Bayesian statistics.
Biography
Lindley grew up in the south-west London suburb of Surbiton. He was an only child a ...
called the disagreement a
paradox
A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true or apparently true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictor ...
in a 1957 paper.
Although referred to as a ''paradox'', the differing results from the Bayesian and frequentist approaches can be explained as using them to answer fundamentally different questions, rather than actual disagreement between the two methods.
Nevertheless, for a large class of priors the differences between the frequentist and Bayesian approach are caused by keeping the significance level fixed: as even Lindley recognized, "the theory does not justify the practice of keeping the significance level fixed" and even "some computations by Prof. Pearson in the discussion to that paper emphasized how the significance level would have to change with the sample size, if the losses and prior probabilities were kept fixed".
In fact, if the critical value increases with the sample size suitably fast, then the disagreement between the frequentist and Bayesian approaches becomes negligible as the sample size increases.
The paradox continues to be a source of active discussion.
Description of the paradox
The result
of some experiment has two possible explanations hypotheses
and
and some prior distribution
representing uncertainty as to which hypothesis is more accurate before taking into account
.
Lindley's paradox occurs when
# The result
is "significant" by a frequentist test of
indicating sufficient evidence to reject
say, at the 5% level, and
# The
posterior probability
The posterior probability is a type of conditional probability that results from updating the prior probability with information summarized by the likelihood via an application of Bayes' rule. From an epistemological perspective, the posteri ...
of
given
is high, indicating strong evidence that
is in better agreement with
than
These results can occur at the same time when
is very specific,
more diffuse, and the prior distribution does not strongly favor one or the other, as seen below.
Numerical example
The following numerical example illustrates Lindley's paradox. In a certain city 49,581 boys and 48,870 girls have been born over a certain time period. The observed proportion
of male births is thus / ≈ 0.5036. We assume the fraction of male births is a
binomial variable with parameter
We are interested in testing whether
is 0.5 or some other value. That is, our null hypothesis is
and the alternative is
Frequentist approach
The frequentist approach to testing
is to compute a
p-value
In null-hypothesis significance testing, the ''p''-value is the probability of obtaining test results at least as extreme as the result actually observed, under the assumption that the null hypothesis is correct. A very small ''p''-value means ...
, the probability of observing a fraction of boys at least as large as
assuming
is true. Because the number of births is very large, we can use a
normal approximation for the fraction of male births
with
and
to compute
:
We would have been equally surprised if we had seen female births, i.e.
so a frequentist would usually perform a
two-sided test, for which the p-value would be
In both cases, the p-value is lower than the significance level α = 5%, so the frequentist approach rejects
as it disagrees with the observed data.
Bayesian approach
Assuming no reason to favor one hypothesis over the other, the Bayesian approach would be to assign prior probabilities
and a uniform distribution to
under
and then to compute the posterior probability of
using
Bayes' theorem
Bayes' theorem (alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule, after Thomas Bayes) gives a mathematical rule for inverting Conditional probability, conditional probabilities, allowing one to find the probability of a cause given its effect. For exampl ...
:
:
After observing
boys out of
births, we can compute the posterior probability of each hypothesis using the
probability mass function
In probability and statistics, a probability mass function (sometimes called ''probability function'' or ''frequency function'') is a function that gives the probability that a discrete random variable is exactly equal to some value. Sometimes i ...
for a binomial variable:
:
where
is the
Beta function
In mathematics, the beta function, also called the Euler integral of the first kind, is a special function that is closely related to the gamma function and to binomial coefficients. It is defined by the integral
: \Beta(z_1,z_2) = \int_0^1 t^ ...
.
From these values, we find the posterior probability of
which strongly favors
over
.
The two approaches—the Bayesian and the frequentist—appear to be in conflict, and this is the "paradox".
Reconciling the Bayesian and frequentist approaches
Almost sure hypothesis testing
Naaman
proposed an adaption of the significance level to the sample size in order to control false positives: , such that with .
At least in the numerical example, taking , results in a significance level of 0.00318, so the frequentist would not reject the null hypothesis, which is in agreement with the Bayesian approach.
Uninformative priors
If we use an
uninformative prior
A prior probability distribution of an uncertain quantity, simply called the prior, is its assumed probability distribution before some evidence is taken into account. For example, the prior could be the probability distribution representing the ...
and test a hypothesis more similar to that in the frequentist approach, the paradox disappears.
For example, if we calculate the posterior distribution
, using a uniform prior distribution on
(i.e.
), we find
:
If we use this to check the probability that a newborn is more likely to be a boy than a girl, i.e.
we find
:
In other words, it is very likely that the proportion of male births is above 0.5.
Neither analysis gives an estimate of the
effect size
In statistics, an effect size is a value measuring the strength of the relationship between two variables in a population, or a sample-based estimate of that quantity. It can refer to the value of a statistic calculated from a sample of data, the ...
, directly, but both could be used to determine, for instance, if the fraction of boy births is likely to be above some particular threshold.
The lack of an actual paradox
The apparent disagreement between the two approaches is caused by a combination of factors. First, the frequentist approach above tests
without reference to
. The Bayesian approach evaluates
as an alternative to
and finds the first to be in better agreement with the observations. This is because the latter hypothesis is much more diffuse, as
can be anywhere in