HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
, a Kleisli category is a category naturally associated to any monad ''T''. It is equivalent to the category of free ''T''-algebras. The Kleisli category is one of two extremal solutions to the question ''Does every monad arise from an
adjunction In mathematics, the term ''adjoint'' applies in several situations. Several of these share a similar formalism: if ''A'' is adjoint to ''B'', then there is typically some formula of the type :(''Ax'', ''y'') = (''x'', ''By''). Specifically, adjoin ...
?'' The other extremal solution is the Eilenberg–Moore category. Kleisli categories are named for the mathematician Heinrich Kleisli.


Formal definition

Let ⟨''T'', ''η'', ''μ''⟩ be a monad over a category ''C''. The Kleisli category of ''C'' is the category ''C''''T'' whose objects and morphisms are given by :\begin\mathrm() &= \mathrm(), \\ \mathrm_(X,Y) &= \mathrm_(X,TY).\end That is, every morphism ''f: X → T Y'' in ''C'' (with codomain ''TY'') can also be regarded as a morphism in ''C''''T'' (but with codomain ''Y''). Composition of morphisms in ''C''''T'' is given by :g\circ_T f = \mu_Z \circ Tg \circ f : X \to T Y \to T^2 Z \to T Z where ''f: X → T Y'' and ''g: Y → T Z''. The identity morphism is given by the monad unit ''η'': :\mathrm_X = \eta_X. An alternative way of writing this, which clarifies the category in which each object lives, is used by Mac Lane. We use very slightly different notation for this presentation. Given the same monad and category C as above, we associate with each object X in C a new object X_T, and for each morphism f\colon X\to TY in C a morphism f^*\colon X_T\to Y_T. Together, these objects and morphisms form our category C_T, where we define :g^*\circ_T f^* = (\mu_Z \circ Tg \circ f)^*. Then the identity morphism in C_T is :\mathrm_ = (\eta_X)^*.


Extension operators and Kleisli triples

Composition of Kleisli arrows can be expressed succinctly by means of the ''extension operator'' (–)# : Hom(''X'', ''TY'') → Hom(''TX'', ''TY''). Given a monad ⟨''T'', ''η'', ''μ''⟩ over a category ''C'' and a morphism ''f'' : ''X'' → ''TY'' let :f^\sharp = \mu_Y\circ Tf. Composition in the Kleisli category ''C''''T'' can then be written :g\circ_T f = g^\sharp \circ f. The extension operator satisfies the identities: :\begin\eta_X^\sharp &= \mathrm_\\ f^\sharp\circ\eta_X &= f\\ (g^\sharp\circ f)^\sharp &= g^\sharp \circ f^\sharp\end where ''f'' : ''X'' → ''TY'' and ''g'' : ''Y'' → ''TZ''. It follows trivially from these properties that Kleisli composition is associative and that ''η''''X'' is the identity. In fact, to give a monad is to give a ''Kleisli triple'' ⟨''T'', ''η'', (–)#⟩, i.e. * A function T\colon \mathrm(C)\to \mathrm(C); * For each object A in C, a morphism \eta_A\colon A\to T(A); * For each morphism f\colon A\to T(B) in C, a morphism f^\sharp\colon T(A)\to T(B) such that the above three equations for extension operators are satisfied.


Kleisli adjunction

Kleisli categories were originally defined in order to show that every monad arises from an adjunction. That construction is as follows. Let ⟨''T'', ''η'', ''μ''⟩ be a monad over a category ''C'' and let ''C''''T'' be the associated Kleisli category. Using Mac Lane's notation mentioned in the “Formal definition” section above, define a functor ''F'': ''C'' → ''C''''T'' by :FX = X_T\; :F(f\colon X \to Y) = (\eta_Y \circ f)^* and a functor ''G'' : ''C''''T'' → ''C'' by :GY_T = TY\; :G(f^*\colon X_T \to Y_T) = \mu_Y \circ Tf\; One can show that ''F'' and ''G'' are indeed functors and that ''F'' is left adjoint to ''G''. The counit of the adjunction is given by :\varepsilon_ = (\mathrm_)^* : (TY)_T \to Y_T. Finally, one can show that ''T'' = ''GF'' and ''μ'' = ''GεF'' so that ⟨''T'', ''η'', ''μ''⟩ is the monad associated to the adjunction ⟨''F'', ''G'', ''η'', ''ε''⟩.


Showing that ''GF'' = ''T''

For any object ''X'' in category ''C'': : \begin (G \circ F)(X) &= G(F(X)) \\ &= G(X_T) \\ &= TX. \end For any f : X \to Y in category ''C'': : \begin (G \circ F)(f) &= G(F(f)) \\ &= G((\eta_Y \circ f)^*) \\ &= \mu_Y \circ T(\eta_Y \circ f) \\ &= \mu_Y \circ T\eta_Y \circ Tf \\ &= \text_ \circ Tf \\ &= Tf. \end Since (G \circ F)(X) = TX is true for any object ''X'' in ''C'' and (G \circ F)(f) = Tf is true for any morphism ''f'' in ''C'', then G \circ F = T.
Q.E.D. Q.E.D. or QED is an initialism of the Latin phrase , meaning "which was to be demonstrated". Literally it states "what was to be shown". Traditionally, the abbreviation is placed at the end of mathematical proofs and philosophical arguments in pri ...


References

* * *


External links

* {{Category theory Adjoint functors Categories in category theory