:''In
mathematical physics
Mathematical physics refers to the development of mathematics, mathematical methods for application to problems in physics. The ''Journal of Mathematical Physics'' defines the field as "the application of mathematics to problems in physics and t ...
, ''Hilbert system'' is an infrequently used term for a physical system described by a
C*-algebra.''
In
logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premis ...
, especially
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal ...
, a Hilbert system, sometimes called Hilbert calculus, Hilbert-style deductive system or Hilbert–Ackermann system, is a type of system of
formal deduction attributed to
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic ph ...
[Máté & Ruzsa 1997:129] and
David Hilbert. These
deductive systems are most often studied for
first-order logic
First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quanti ...
, but are of interest for other logics as well.
Most variants of Hilbert systems take a characteristic tack in the way they balance a
trade-off between
logical axioms and
rules of inference.
Hilbert systems can be characterised by the choice of a large number of
schemes of logical axioms and a small set of
rules of inference. Systems of
natural deduction take the opposite tack, including many deduction rules but very few or no axiom schemes. The most commonly studied Hilbert systems have either just one rule of inference
modus ponens, for
propositional logics or two with
generalisation
A generalization is a form of abstraction whereby common properties of specific instances are formulated as general concepts or claims. Generalizations posit the existence of a domain or set theory, set of elements, as well as one or more commo ...
, to handle
predicate logic
First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quanti ...
s, as well and several infinite axiom schemes. Hilbert systems for propositional
modal logics, sometimes called
Hilbert-Lewis systems, are generally axiomatised with two additional rules, the
necessitation rule and the
uniform substitution
A uniform is a variety of clothing worn by members of an organization while participating in that organization's activity. Modern uniforms are most often worn by armed forces and paramilitary organizations such as police, emergency services, ...
rule.
A characteristic feature of the many variants of Hilbert systems is that the ''context'' is not changed in any of their rules of inference, while both
natural deduction and
sequent calculus contain some context-changing rules. Thus, if one is interested only in the derivability of
tautologies, no hypothetical judgments, then one can formalize the Hilbert system in such a way that its rules of inference contain only
judgments of a rather simple form. The same cannot be done with the other two deductions systems: as context is changed in some of their rules of inferences, they cannot be formalized so that hypothetical judgments could be avoided not even if we want to use them just for proving derivability of tautologies.
Formal deductions

In a Hilbert-style deduction system, a formal deduction is a finite sequence of formulas in which each formula is either an axiom or is obtained from previous formulas by a rule of inference. These formal deductions are meant to mirror natural-language proofs, although they are far more detailed.
Suppose
is a set of formulas, considered as hypotheses. For example,
could be a set of axioms for
group theory
In abstract algebra, group theory studies the algebraic structures known as group (mathematics), groups.
The concept of a group is central to abstract algebra: other well-known algebraic structures, such as ring (mathematics), rings, field ...
or
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concer ...
. The notation
means that there is a deduction that ends with
using as axioms only logical axioms and elements of
. Thus, informally,
means that
is provable assuming all the formulas in
.
Hilbert-style deduction systems are characterized by the use of numerous schemes of logical axioms. An
axiom scheme is an infinite set of axioms obtained by substituting all formulas of some form into a specific pattern. The set of logical axioms includes not only those axioms generated from this pattern, but also any generalization of one of those axioms. A generalization of a formula is obtained by prefixing zero or more universal quantifiers on the formula; for example
is a generalization of
.
Logical axioms
There are several variant axiomatisations of predicate logic, since for any logic there is freedom in choosing axioms and rules that characterise that logic. We describe here a Hilbert system with nine axioms and just the rule modus ponens, which we call the one-rule axiomatisation and which describes classical equational logic. We deal with a minimal language for this logic, where formulas use only the connectives
and
and only the quantifier
. Later we show how the system can be extended to include additional logical connectives, such as
and
, without enlarging the class of deducible formulas.
The first four logical axiom schemes allow (together with modus ponens) for the manipulation of logical connectives.
:P1.
:P2.
:P3.
:P4.
The axiom P1 is redundant, as it follows from P3, P2 and modus ponens (see
proof
Proof most often refers to:
* Proof (truth), argument or sufficient evidence for the truth of a proposition
* Alcohol proof, a measure of an alcoholic drink's strength
Proof may also refer to:
Mathematics and formal logic
* Formal proof, a con ...
). These axioms describe
classical propositional logic; without axiom P4 we get
positive implicational logic.
Minimal logic is achieved either by adding instead the axiom P4m, or by defining
as
.
:P4m.
Intuitionistic logic is achieved by adding axioms P4i and P5i to positive implicational logic, or by adding axiom P5i to minimal logic. Both P4i and P5i are theorems of classical propositional logic.
:P4i.
:P5i.
Note that these are axiom schemes, which represent infinitely many specific instances of axioms. For example, P1 might represent the particular axiom instance
, or it might represent
: the
is a place where any formula can be placed. A variable such as this that ranges over formulae is called a 'schematic variable'.
With a second rule of
uniform substitution
A uniform is a variety of clothing worn by members of an organization while participating in that organization's activity. Modern uniforms are most often worn by armed forces and paramilitary organizations such as police, emergency services, ...
(US), we can change each of these axiom schemes into a single axiom, replacing each schematic variable by some propositional variable that isn't mentioned in any axiom to get what we call the substitutional axiomatisation. Both formalisations have variables, but where the one-rule axiomatisation has schematic variables that are outside the logic's language, the substitutional axiomatisation uses propositional variables that do the same work by expressing the idea of a variable ranging over formulae with a rule that uses substitution.
:US. Let
be a formula with one or more instances of the propositional variable
, and let
be another formula. Then from
, infer
.
The next three logical axiom schemes provide ways to add, manipulate, and remove universal quantifiers.
:Q5.