Hausdorff Maximality Principle
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the Hausdorff maximal principle is an alternate and earlier formulation of
Zorn's lemma Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain (that is, every totally ordered subset) necessarily contains at least on ...
proved by
Felix Hausdorff Felix Hausdorff ( , ; November 8, 1868 – January 26, 1942) was a German mathematician, pseudonym Paul Mongré (''à mogré' (Fr.) = "according to my taste"), who is considered to be one of the founders of modern topology and who contributed sig ...
in 1914 (Moore 1982:168). It states that in any
partially ordered set In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
, every
totally ordered In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( r ...
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
is contained in a maximal totally ordered subset, where "maximal" is with respect to set inclusion. In a partially ordered set, a totally ordered subset is also called a chain. Thus, the maximal principle says every chain in the set extends to a maximal chain. The Hausdorff maximal principle is one of many statements equivalent to the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
over ZF (
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
without the axiom of choice). The principle is also called the Hausdorff maximality theorem or the Kuratowski lemma (Kelley 1955:33).


Statement

The Hausdorff maximal principle states that, in any
partially ordered set In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
P, every chain C_0 (i.e., a
totally ordered In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( r ...
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
) is contained in a maximal chain C (i.e., a chain that is not contained in a strictly larger chain in P). In general, there may be several maximal chains containing a given chain. An equivalent form of the Hausdorff maximal principle is that in every partially ordered set, there exists a maximal chain. (Note if the set is empty, the empty subset is a maximal chain.) This form follows from the original form since the empty set is a chain. Conversely, to deduce the original form from this form, consider the set P' of all chains in P containing a given chain C_0 in P. Then P' is partially ordered by set inclusion. Thus, by the maximal principle in the above form, P' contains a maximal chain C'. Let C be the union of C', which is a chain in P since a union of a totally ordered set of chains is a chain. Since C contains C_0, it is an element of P'. Also, since any chain containing C is contained in C as C is a union, C is in fact a maximal element of P'; i.e., a maximal chain in P. The proof that the Hausdorff maximal principle is equivalent to Zorn's lemma is somehow similar to this proof. Indeed, first assume Zorn's lemma. Since a union of a totally ordered set of chains is a chain, the hypothesis of Zorn's lemma (every chain has an upper bound) is satisfied for P' and thus P' contains a maximal element or a maximal chain in P. Conversely, if the maximal principle holds, then P contains a maximal chain C. By the hypothesis of Zorn's lemma, C has an upper bound x in P. If y \ge x, then \widetilde = C \cup \ is a chain containing C and so by maximality, \widetilde = C; i.e., y \in C and so y = x. \square


Examples

If ''A'' is any collection of sets, the relation "is a proper subset of" is a
strict partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements needs to be comparable; ...
on ''A''. Suppose that ''A'' is the collection of all circular regions (interiors of circles) in the plane. One maximal totally ordered sub-collection of ''A'' consists of all circular regions with centers at the origin. Another maximal totally ordered sub-collection consists of all circular regions bounded by circles tangent from the right to the y-axis at the origin. If (x0, y0) and (x1, y1) are two points of the plane \mathbb^, define (x0, y0) < (x1, y1) if y0 = y1 and x0 < x1. This is a partial ordering of \mathbb^ under which two points are comparable only if they lie on the same horizontal line. The maximal totally ordered sets are horizontal lines in \mathbb^.


Application

By the Hausdorff maximal principle, we can show every
Hilbert space In mathematics, a Hilbert space is a real number, real or complex number, complex inner product space that is also a complete metric space with respect to the metric induced by the inner product. It generalizes the notion of Euclidean space. The ...
H contains a maximal orthonormal subset A as follows. (This fact can be stated as saying that H \simeq \ell^2(A) as Hilbert spaces.) Let P be the set of all orthonormal subsets of the given Hilbert space H, which is partially ordered by set inclusion. It is nonempty as it contains the empty set and thus by the maximal principle, it contains a maximal chain Q. Let A be the union of Q. We shall show it is a maximal orthonormal subset. First, if S, T are in Q, then either S \subset T or T \subset S. That is, any given two distinct elements in A are contained in some S in Q and so they are orthogonal to each other (and of course, A is a subset of the unit sphere in H). Second, if B \supsetneq A for some B in P, then B cannot be in Q and so Q \cup \ is a chain strictly larger than Q, a contradiction. \square For the purpose of comparison, here is a proof of the same fact by Zorn's lemma. As above, let P be the set of all orthonormal subsets of H. If Q is a chain in P, then the union of Q is also orthonormal by the same argument as above and so is an upper bound of Q. Thus, by Zorn's lemma, P contains a maximal element A. (So, the difference is that the maximal principle gives a maximal chain while Zorn's lemma gives a maximal element directly.)


Proof 1

The idea of the proof is essentially due to Zermelo and is to prove the following weak form of
Zorn's lemma Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain (that is, every totally ordered subset) necessarily contains at least on ...
, from the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
. :Let F be a nonempty set of subsets of some fixed set, ordered by set inclusion, such that (1) the union of each totally ordered subset of F is in F and (2) each subset of a set in F is in F. Then F has a maximal element. (Zorn's lemma itself also follows from this weak form.) The maximal principle follows from the above since the set of all chains in P satisfies the above conditions. By the axiom of choice, we have a function f : \mathfrak(P) - \ \to P such that f(S) \in S for the power set \mathfrak(P) of P. For each C \in F, let C^* be the set of all x \in P - C such that C \cup \ is in F. If C^* = \emptyset, then let \widetilde = C. Otherwise, let :\widetilde = C \cup \. Note C is a maximal element if and only if \widetilde = C. Thus, we are done if we can find a C such that \widetilde = C. Fix a C_0 in F. We call a subset T \subset F a ''tower (over C_0)'' if # C_0 is in T. # The union of each totally ordered subset T' \subset T is in T, where "totally ordered" is with respect to set inclusion. # For each C in T, \widetilde is in T. There exists at least one tower; indeed, the set of all sets in F containing C_0 is a tower. Let T_0 be the intersection of all towers, which is again a tower. Now, we shall show T_0 is totally ordered. We say a set C is ''comparable in T_0'' if for each A in T_0, either A \subset C or C \subset A. Let \Gamma be the set of all sets in T_0 that are comparable in T_0. We claim \Gamma is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are straightforward to check. For 3., let C in \Gamma be given and then let U be the set of all A in T_0 such that either A \subset C or \widetilde \subset A. We claim U is a tower. The conditions 1. and 2. are again straightforward to check. For 3., let A be in U. If A \subset C, then since C is comparable in T_0, either \widetilde \subset C or C \subset \widetilde . In the first case, \widetilde is in U. In the second case, we have A \subset C \subset \widetilde, which implies either A = C or C = \widetilde. (This is the moment we needed to collapse a set to an element by the axiom of choice to define \widetilde.) Either way, we have \widetilde is in U. Similarly, if C \subset A, we see \widetilde is in U. Hence, U is a tower. Now, since U \subset T_0 and T_0 is the intersection of all towers, U = T_0, which implies \widetilde is comparable in T_0; i.e., is in \Gamma. This completes the proof of the claim that \Gamma is a tower. Finally, since \Gamma is a tower contained in T_0, we have T_0 = \Gamma, which means T_0 is totally ordered. Let C be the union of T_0. By 2., C is in T_0 and then by 3., \widetilde C is in T_0. Since C is the union of T_0, \widetilde C \subset C and thus \widetilde C = C. \square


Proof 2

The
Bourbaki–Witt theorem In mathematics, the Bourbaki–Witt theorem in order theory, named after Nicolas Bourbaki and Ernst Witt, is a basic fixed-point theorem for partially ordered sets. It states that if ''X'' is a non-empty chain complete poset, and f : X \to X such ...
, together with the
Axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
, can be used to prove the Hausdorff maximal principle. Indeed, let P be a nonempty poset and X\mathrel=\ be the set of all totally ordered subsets of P. Notice that X\neq \emptyset, since P\neq \emptyset and \\in X, for any x\in P. Also, equipped with the inclusion \subseteq, X is a poset. We claim that every chain \mathcal\subseteq X has a
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
. In order to check this out, let S be the union \bigcup_C. Clearly, C\subseteq S, for all C\in \mathcal. Also, if U is any upper bound of \mathcal, then S\subseteq U, since by definition C\subseteq U for all C\in \mathcal. Now, consider the map f\colon X\to X given by f(C)\mathrel=\beginC, &\text\ C\ \text\\ C\cup \, &\text\ C\ \text\end where g is a
choice function Let ''X'' be a set of sets none of which are empty. Then a choice function (selector, selection) on ''X'' is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on ''X'' such that ''f'' is a mapping that assigns each element of ''X'' to one of its ele ...
on \ whose existence is ensured by the Axiom of choice, and the fact that P\setminus C\neq \emptyset is an immediate consequence of the non-maximality of C. Thus, C\subseteq f(C), for each C\in X. In view of the Bourbaki-Witt theorem, there exists an element C_0\in \mathcal such that f(C_0)=C_0, and therefore C_0 is a maximal chain of P. In the case P=\emptyset, the empty set is trivially a maximal chain of P, as already mentioned above. \square


Notes


References

* . Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. (Springer-Verlag edition). * John Kelley (1955), ''General topology'', Von Nostrand. * Gregory Moore (1982), ''Zermelo's axiom of choice'', Springer. *
James Munkres James Raymond Munkres (born ) is a Professor Emeritus of mathematics at MIT and the author of several texts in the area of topology, including ''Topology'' (an undergraduate-level text), ''Analysis on Manifolds'', ''Elements of Algebraic Topology' ...
(2000), ''Topology'', Pearson. * Appendix of {{Order theory Axiom of choice Mathematical principles Order theory