In
mathematics
Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, particularly
set theory, a finite set is a
set that has a
finite number of
elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example,
:
is a finite set with five elements. The number of elements of a finite set is a
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country").
Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
(possibly zero) and is called the ''
cardinality (or the
cardinal number
In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. T ...
)'' of the set. A set that is not a finite set is called an ''
infinite set''. For example, the set of all positive integers is infinite:
:
Finite sets are particularly important in
combinatorics
Combinatorics is an area of mathematics primarily concerned with counting, both as a means and an end in obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. It is closely related to many other areas of mathematics and has many a ...
, the mathematical study of
counting. Many arguments involving finite sets rely on the
pigeonhole principle, which states that there cannot exist an
injective
In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements; that is, implies . (Equivalently, implies in the equivalent contrapositiv ...
function from a larger finite set to a smaller finite set.
Definition and terminology
Formally, a set is called finite if there exists a
bijection
:
for some natural number . The number is the set's cardinality, denoted as . The
empty set or ∅ is considered finite, with cardinality zero.
If a set is finite, its elements may be written — in many ways — in a
sequence:
:
In
combinatorics
Combinatorics is an area of mathematics primarily concerned with counting, both as a means and an end in obtaining results, and certain properties of finite structures. It is closely related to many other areas of mathematics and has many a ...
, a finite set with elements is sometimes called an ''-set'' and a
subset
In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
with elements is called a ''-subset''. For example, the set is a 3-set – a finite set with three elements – and is a 2-subset of it.
(Those familiar with the definition of the natural numbers themselves as conventional in
set theory, the so-called
von Neumann construction, may prefer to use the existence of the bijection
, which is equivalent.)
Basic properties
Any
proper subset of a finite set ''S'' is finite and has fewer elements than ''S'' itself. As a consequence, there cannot exist a
bijection between a finite set ''S'' and a proper subset of ''S''. Any set with this property is called
Dedekind-finite. Using the standard
ZFC axioms for
set theory, every Dedekind-finite set is also finite, but this implication cannot be
proved in ZF (Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms without the
axiom of choice) alone.
The
axiom of countable choice, a weak version of the axiom of choice, is sufficient to prove this equivalence.
Any injective function between two finite sets of the same cardinality is also a
surjective function (a surjection). Similarly, any surjection between two finite sets of the same cardinality is also an injection.
The
union of two finite sets is finite, with
:
In fact, by the
inclusion–exclusion principle:
:
More generally, the union of any finite number of finite sets is finite. The
Cartesian product of finite sets is also finite, with:
:
Similarly, the Cartesian product of finitely many finite sets is finite. A finite set with ''n'' elements has 2 distinct subsets. That is, the
power set ''P''(''S'') of a finite set ''S'' is finite, with cardinality 2.
Any subset of a finite set is finite. The set of values of a function when applied to elements of a finite set is finite.
All finite sets are
countable, but not all countable sets are finite. (Some authors, however, use "countable" to mean "countably infinite", so do not consider finite sets to be countable.)
The
free semilattice over a finite set is the set of its non-empty subsets, with the
join operation being given by set union.
Necessary and sufficient conditions for finiteness
In
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice (ZF), the following conditions are all equivalent:
# ''S'' is a finite set. That is, ''S'' can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of those natural numbers less than some specific natural number.
# (
Kazimierz Kuratowski) ''S'' has all properties which can be proved by mathematical induction beginning with the empty set and adding one new element at a time. (See
below for the set-theoretical formulation of Kuratowski finiteness.)
# (
Paul Stäckel
Paul Gustav Samuel Stäckel (20 August 1862, Berlin – 12 December 1919, Heidelberg) was a German mathematician, active in the areas of differential geometry, number theory, and non-Euclidean geometry. In the area of prime number theory, he ...
) ''S'' can be given a
total ordering which is
well-ordered both forwards and backwards. That is, every non-empty subset of ''S'' has both a least and a greatest element in the subset.
# Every one-to-one function from ''P''(''P''(''S'')) into itself is
onto. That is, the
powerset
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is postu ...
of the powerset of ''S'' is Dedekind-finite (see below).
# Every surjective function from ''P''(''P''(''S'')) onto itself is one-to-one.
# (
Alfred Tarski) Every non-empty family of subsets of ''S'' has a
minimal element with respect to inclusion. (Equivalently, every non-empty family of subsets of ''S'' has a
maximal element
In mathematics, especially in order theory, a maximal element of a subset ''S'' of some preordered set is an element of ''S'' that is not smaller than any other element in ''S''. A minimal element of a subset ''S'' of some preordered set is defin ...
with respect to inclusion.)
# ''S'' can be well-ordered and any two well-orderings on it are
order isomorphic
In the mathematical field of order theory, an order isomorphism is a special kind of monotone function that constitutes a suitable notion of isomorphism for partially ordered sets (posets). Whenever two posets are order isomorphic, they can be cons ...
. In other words, the well-orderings on ''S'' have exactly one
order type.
If the
axiom of choice is also assumed (the
axiom of countable choice is sufficient), then the following conditions are all equivalent:
# ''S'' is a finite set.
# (
Richard Dedekind
Julius Wilhelm Richard Dedekind (6 October 1831 – 12 February 1916) was a German mathematician who made important contributions to number theory, abstract algebra (particularly ring theory), and
the axiomatic foundations of arithmetic. His ...
) Every one-to-one function from ''S'' into itself is onto.
# Every surjective function from ''S'' onto itself is one-to-one.
# ''S'' is empty or every
partial ordering of ''S'' contains a
maximal element
In mathematics, especially in order theory, a maximal element of a subset ''S'' of some preordered set is an element of ''S'' that is not smaller than any other element in ''S''. A minimal element of a subset ''S'' of some preordered set is defin ...
.
Foundational issues
Georg Cantor initiated his theory of sets in order to provide a mathematical treatment of infinite sets. Thus the distinction between the finite and the infinite lies at the core of set theory. Certain foundationalists, the
strict finitists, reject the existence of infinite sets and thus recommend a mathematics based solely on finite sets. Mainstream mathematicians consider strict finitism too confining, but acknowledge its relative consistency: the universe of
hereditarily finite sets constitutes a model of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the
axiom of infinity replaced by its
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P or \overline. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when P is false, and false ...
.
Even for the majority of mathematicians that embrace infinite sets, in certain important contexts, the formal distinction between the finite and the infinite can remain a delicate matter. The difficulty stems from
Gödel's incompleteness theorems. One can interpret the theory of hereditarily finite sets within
Peano arithmetic
In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
(and certainly also vice versa), so the incompleteness of the theory of Peano arithmetic implies that of the theory of hereditarily finite sets. In particular, there exists a plethora of so-called
non-standard models of both theories. A seeming paradox is that there are non-standard models of the theory of hereditarily finite sets which contain infinite sets, but these infinite sets look finite from within the model. (This can happen when the model lacks the sets or functions necessary to witness the infinitude of these sets.) On account of the incompleteness theorems, no
first-order predicate, nor even any recursive scheme of first-order predicates, can characterize the standard part of all such models. So, at least from the point of view of first-order logic, one can only hope to describe finiteness approximately.
More generally, informal notions like set, and particularly finite set, may receive interpretations across a range of
formal systems varying in their axiomatics and logical apparatus. The best known axiomatic set theories include Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF), Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice (ZFC),
Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG),
Non-well-founded set theory,
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, philosopher, logician, and public intellectual. He had a considerable influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, linguistics, ar ...
's
Type theory and all the theories of their various models. One may also choose among classical first-order logic, various
higher-order logics and
intuitionistic logic.
A
formalist might see the meaning of ''set'' varying from system to system. Some kinds of
Platonists might view particular formal systems as approximating an underlying reality.
Set-theoretic definitions of finiteness
In contexts where the notion of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country").
Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
sits logically prior to any notion of set, one can define a set ''S'' as finite if ''S'' admits a
bijection to some set of natural numbers of the form
. Mathematicians more typically choose to ground notions of number in
set theory, for example they might model natural numbers by the order types of finite
well-ordered sets. Such an approach requires a structural definition of finiteness that does not depend on natural numbers.
Various properties that single out the finite sets among all sets in the theory ZFC turn out logically inequivalent in weaker systems such as ZF or intuitionistic set theories. Two definitions feature prominently in the literature, one due to
Richard Dedekind
Julius Wilhelm Richard Dedekind (6 October 1831 – 12 February 1916) was a German mathematician who made important contributions to number theory, abstract algebra (particularly ring theory), and
the axiomatic foundations of arithmetic. His ...
, the other to
Kazimierz Kuratowski. (Kuratowski's is the definition used above.)
A set ''S'' is called
Dedekind infinite if there exists an injective, non-surjective function
. Such a function exhibits a bijection between ''S'' and a proper subset of ''S'', namely the image of ''f''. Given a Dedekind infinite set ''S'', a function ''f'', and an element ''x'' that is not in the image of ''f'', we can form an infinite sequence of distinct elements of ''S'', namely
. Conversely, given a sequence in ''S'' consisting of distinct elements
, we can define a function ''f'' such that on elements in the sequence
and ''f'' behaves like the identity function otherwise. Thus Dedekind infinite sets contain subsets that correspond bijectively with the natural numbers. Dedekind finite naturally means that every injective self-map is also surjective.
Kuratowski finiteness is defined as follows. Given any set ''S'', the binary operation of union endows the
powerset
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is postu ...
''P''(''S'') with the structure of a
semilattice. Writing ''K''(''S'') for the sub-semilattice generated by the empty set and the
singletons, call set ''S'' Kuratowski finite if ''S'' itself belongs to ''K''(''S''). Intuitively, ''K''(''S'') consists of the finite subsets of ''S''. Crucially, one does not need induction, recursion or a definition of natural numbers to define ''generated by'' since one may obtain ''K''(''S'') simply by taking the intersection of all sub-semilattices containing the empty set and the singletons.
Readers unfamiliar with semilattices and other notions of abstract algebra may prefer an entirely elementary formulation. Kuratowski finite means ''S'' lies in the set ''K''(''S''), constructed as follows. Write ''M'' for the set of all subsets ''X'' of ''P''(''S'') such that:
* ''X'' contains the empty set;
* For every set ''T'' in ''P''(''S''), if ''X'' contains ''T'' then ''X'' also contains the union of ''T'' with any singleton.
Then ''K''(''S'') may be defined as the intersection of ''M''.
In ZF, Kuratowski finite implies Dedekind finite, but not vice versa. In the parlance of a popular pedagogical formulation, when the axiom of choice fails badly, one may have an infinite family of socks with no way to choose one sock from more than finitely many of the pairs. That would make the set of such socks Dedekind finite: there can be no infinite sequence of socks, because such a sequence would allow a choice of one sock for infinitely many pairs by choosing the first sock in the sequence. However, Kuratowski finiteness would fail for the same set of socks.
Other concepts of finiteness
In ZF set theory without the
axiom of choice, the following concepts of finiteness for a set ''S'' are distinct. They are arranged in strictly decreasing order of strength, i.e. if a set ''S'' meets a criterion in the list then it meets all of the following criteria. In the absence of the axiom of choice the reverse implications are all unprovable, but if the axiom of choice is assumed then all of these concepts are equivalent. (Note that none of these definitions need the set of finite
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the lea ...
s to be defined first; they are all pure "set-theoretic" definitions in terms of the equality and membership relations, not involving ω.)
* I-finite. Every non-empty set of subsets of ''S'' has a ⊆-maximal element. (This is equivalent to requiring the existence of a ⊆-minimal element. It is also equivalent to the standard numerical concept of finiteness.)
* Ia-finite. For every partition of ''S'' into two sets, at least one of the two sets is I-finite. (A set with this property which is not I-finite is called an
amorphous set
In set theory, an amorphous set is an infinite set which is not the disjoint union of two infinite subsets..
Existence
Amorphous sets cannot exist if the axiom of choice is assumed. Fraenkel constructed a permutation model of Zermelo–Fraenke ...
.)
* II-finite. Every non-empty ⊆-monotone set of subsets of ''S'' has a ⊆-maximal element.
* III-finite. The power set ''P''(''S'') is Dedekind finite.
* IV-finite. ''S'' is Dedekind finite.
* V-finite. ∣''S''∣ = 0 or 2 ⋅ ∣''S''∣ > ∣''S'', .
* VI-finite. ∣''S''∣ = 0 or ∣''S''∣ = 1 or ∣''S''∣
2 > ∣''S''∣.
* VII-finite. ''S'' is I-finite or not well-orderable.
The forward implications (from strong to weak) are theorems within ZF. Counter-examples to the reverse implications (from weak to strong) in ZF with
urelements are found using
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the s ...
.
[ found counter-examples to each of the reverse implications in Mostowski models. Lévy attributes most of the results to earlier papers by Mostowski and Lindenbaum.]
Most of these finiteness definitions and their names are attributed to by . However, definitions I, II, III, IV and V were presented in , together with proofs (or references to proofs) for the forward implications. At that time, model theory was not sufficiently advanced to find the counter-examples.
Each of the properties I-finite thru IV-finite is a notion of smallness in the sense that any subset of a set with such a property will also have the property. This is not true for V-finite thru VII-finite because they may have countably infinite subsets.
See also
*
FinSet
*
Ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the lea ...
*
Peano arithmetic
In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
Notes
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
External links
*
{{Set theory
Basic concepts in set theory
Cardinal numbers