HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
, the double negation of a statement states that "it is not the case that the statement is not true". In
classical logic Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy. Characteristics Each logical system in this c ...
, every statement is logically equivalent to its double negation, but this is not true in
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
; this can be expressed by the formula A ≡ ~(~A) where the sign ≡ expresses logical equivalence and the sign expresses
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
. Like the law of the excluded middle, this principle is considered to be a law of thought in classical logic, but it is disallowed by
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
. The principle was stated as a theorem of
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
by Russell and Whitehead in ''
Principia Mathematica The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by the mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1 ...
'' as: :: \mathbf. \ \ \vdash.\ p \ \equiv \ \thicksim(\thicksim p)PM 1952 reprint of 2nd edition 1927 pp. 101–02, 117. ::"This is the principle of double negation, ''i.e.'' a proposition is equivalent of the falsehood of its negation."


Elimination and introduction

Double negation elimination and double negation introduction are two valid rules of replacement. They are the
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
s that, if ''not not-A'' is true, then ''A'' is true, and its converse, that, if ''A'' is true, then ''not not-A'' is true, respectively. The rule allows one to introduce or eliminate a
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
from a
formal proof In logic and mathematics, a formal proof or derivation is a finite sequence of sentences (known as well-formed formulas when relating to formal language), each of which is an axiom, an assumption, or follows from the preceding sentences in the s ...
. The rule is based on the equivalence of, for example, ''It is false that it is not raining.'' and ''It is raining.'' The ''double negation introduction'' rule is: :''P \Rightarrow P'' and the ''double negation elimination'' rule is: :''P \Rightarrow P'' Where "\Rightarrow" is a metalogical
symbol A symbol is a mark, Sign (semiotics), sign, or word that indicates, signifies, or is understood as representing an idea, physical object, object, or wikt:relationship, relationship. Symbols allow people to go beyond what is known or seen by cr ...
representing "can be replaced in a proof with." In logics that have both rules, negation is an involution.


Formal notation

The ''double negation introduction'' rule may be written in sequent notation: :P \vdash \neg \neg P The ''double negation elimination'' rule may be written as: :\neg \neg P \vdash P In rule form: :\frac and :\frac or as a tautology (plain propositional calculus sentence): :P \to \neg \neg P and :\neg \neg P \to P These can be combined into a single biconditional formula: : \neg \neg P \leftrightarrow P . Since biconditionality is an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
, any instance of ¬¬''A'' in a
well-formed formula In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language. The abbreviation wf ...
can be replaced by ''A'', leaving unchanged the
truth-value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in c ...
of the well-formed formula. Double negative elimination is a theorem of
classical logic Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy. Characteristics Each logical system in this c ...
, but not of weaker logics such as
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
and minimal logic. Double negation introduction is a theorem of both intuitionistic logic and minimal logic, as is \neg \neg \neg A \vdash \neg A . Because of their constructive character, a statement such as ''It's not the case that it's not raining'' is weaker than ''It's raining.'' The latter requires a proof of rain, whereas the former merely requires a proof that rain would not be contradictory. This distinction also arises in natural language in the form of
litotes In rhetoric, litotes (, ), also known classically as antenantiosis or moderatour, is a figures of speech, figure of speech and form of irony in which understatement is used to emphasize a point by stating a negative to further affirm a positive, o ...
.


Proofs


In classical propositional calculus system

In Hilbert-style deductive systems for propositional logic, double negation is not always taken as an axiom (see list of Hilbert systems), and is rather a theorem. We describe a proof of this theorem in the system of three axioms proposed by
Jan Łukasiewicz Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic. His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logi ...
: :A1. \phi \to \left( \psi \to \phi \right) :A2. \left( \phi \to \left( \psi \rightarrow \xi \right) \right) \to \left( \left( \phi \to \psi \right) \to \left( \phi \to \xi \right) \right) :A3. \left ( \lnot \phi \to \lnot \psi \right) \to \left( \psi \to \phi \right) We use the lemma p \to p proved here, which we refer to as (L1), and use the following additional lemma, proved here: :(L2) p \to ((p \to q) \to q) We first prove \neg \neg p \to p. For shortness, we denote q \to ( r \to q ) by φ0. We also use repeatedly the method of the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem as a shorthand for several proof steps. :(1) \varphi_0       (instance of (A1)) :(2) (\neg \neg \varphi_0 \to \neg \neg p ) \to (\neg p \to \neg \varphi_0)       (instance of (A3)) :(3) (\neg p \to \neg \varphi_0) \to (\varphi_0 \to p )       (instance of (A3)) :(4) (\neg \neg \varphi_0 \to \neg \neg p ) \to (\varphi_0 \to p )       (from (2) and (3) by the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem) :(5) \neg \neg p \to ( \neg \neg \varphi_0 \to \neg \neg p )       (instance of (A1)) :(6) \neg \neg p \to (\varphi_0 \to p )       (from (4) and (5) by the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem) :(7) \varphi_0 \to ((\varphi_0 \to p) \to p)       (instance of (L2)) :(8) (\varphi_0 \to p) \to p       (from (1) and (7) by modus ponens) :(9) \neg \neg p \to p       (from (6) and (8) by the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem) We now prove p \to \neg \neg p . :(1) \neg\neg\neg p \to \neg p       (instance of the first part of the theorem we have just proven) :(2) (\neg\neg\neg p \to \neg p) \to (p \to \neg\neg p)       (instance of (A3)) :(3) p \to \neg \neg p       (from (1) and (2) by modus ponens) And the proof is complete.


See also

* Gödel–Gentzen negative translation


References


Bibliography

* William Hamilton, 1860, ''Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic, Vol. II. Logic; Edited by Henry Mansel and John Veitch'', Boston, Gould and Lincoln. * Christoph Sigwart, 1895, ''Logic: The Judgment, Concept, and Inference; Second Edition, Translated by Helen Dendy'', Macmillan & Co. New York. * Stephen C. Kleene, 1952, ''Introduction to Metamathematics'', 6th reprinting with corrections 1971, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam NY, . * Stephen C. Kleene, 1967, ''Mathematical Logic'', Dover edition 2002, Dover Publications, Inc, Mineola N.Y. {{ISBN, 0-486-42533-9 *
Alfred North Whitehead Alfred North Whitehead (15 February 1861 – 30 December 1947) was an English mathematician and philosopher. He created the philosophical school known as process philosophy, which has been applied in a wide variety of disciplines, inclu ...
and
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
, ''Principia Mathematica to *56'', 2nd edition 1927, reprint 1962, Cambridge at the University Press. Theorems in propositional logic Classical logic Rules of inference