
The axiom of countable choice or axiom of denumerable choice, denoted AC
ω, is an
axiom
An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
that states that every
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
collection of
non-empty sets must have a
choice function
Let ''X'' be a set of sets none of which are empty. Then a choice function (selector, selection) on ''X'' is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on ''X'' such that ''f'' is a mapping that assigns each element of ''X'' to one of its ele ...
. That is, given a
function with
domain (where
denotes the set of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s) such that
is a non-empty set for every
, there exists a function
with domain
such that
for every
.
Applications
AC
ω is particularly useful for the development of
mathematical analysis
Analysis is the branch of mathematics dealing with continuous functions, limit (mathematics), limits, and related theories, such as Derivative, differentiation, Integral, integration, measure (mathematics), measure, infinite sequences, series ( ...
, where many results depend on having a choice function for a countable collection of sets of
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s. For instance, in order to prove that every
accumulation point
In mathematics, a limit point, accumulation point, or cluster point of a Set (mathematics), set S in a topological space X is a point x that can be "approximated" by points of S in the sense that every neighbourhood (mathematics), neighbourhood of ...
of a set
is the
limit of some
sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
of elements of
, one needs (a weak form of) the axiom of countable choice. When formulated for accumulation points of arbitrary
metric space
In mathematics, a metric space is a Set (mathematics), set together with a notion of ''distance'' between its Element (mathematics), elements, usually called point (geometry), points. The distance is measured by a function (mathematics), functi ...
s, the statement becomes equivalent to AC
ω.
The ability to perform analysis using countable choice has led to the inclusion of AC
ω as an axiom in some forms of
constructive mathematics
In the philosophy of mathematics, constructivism asserts that it is necessary to find (or "construct") a specific example of a mathematical object in order to prove that an example exists. Contrastingly, in classical mathematics, one can prove th ...
, despite its assertion that a choice function exists without constructing it.
Example: infinite implies Dedekind-infinite
As an example of an application of AC
ω, here is a proof (from
ZF + AC
ω) that every infinite set is
Dedekind-infinite:
Let
be infinite. For each natural number
, let
be the set of all
-tuples of distinct elements of
. Since
is infinite, each
is non-empty. Application of AC
ω yields a sequence
where each
is an
-tuple. One can then concatenate these tuples into a single sequence
of elements of
, possibly with repeating elements. Suppressing repetitions produces a sequence
of distinct elements, where
This
exists, because when selecting
it is not possible for all elements of
to be among the
elements selected previously. So
contains a countable set. The function that maps each
to
(and leaves all other elements of
fixed) is a one-to-one map from
into
which is not onto, proving that
is Dedekind-infinite.
Relation to other axioms
Stronger and independent systems
The axiom of countable choice (AC
ω) is strictly weaker than the
axiom of dependent choice
In mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. T ...
(DC), which in turn is weaker than the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC). DC, and therefore also AC
ω, hold in the
Solovay model, constructed in 1970 by
Robert M. Solovay as a model of set theory without the full axiom of choice, in which all sets of real numbers are measurable.
Urysohn's lemma (UL) and the
Tietze extension theorem
In topology, the Tietze extension theorem (also known as the Tietze– Urysohn– Brouwer extension theorem or Urysohn-Brouwer lemma) states that any real-valued, continuous function on a closed subset of a normal topological space
In mathe ...
(TET) are independent of ZF+AC
ω: there exist models of ZF+AC
ω in which UL and TET are true, and models in which they are false. Both UL and TET are implied by DC.
Weaker systems
Paul Cohen
Paul Joseph Cohen (April 2, 1934 – March 23, 2007) was an American mathematician, best known for his proofs that the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice are independent from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, for which he was awarded a F ...
showed that AC
ω is not provable in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZF) without the axiom of choice. However, some countably infinite sets of non-empty sets can be proven to have a
choice function
Let ''X'' be a set of sets none of which are empty. Then a choice function (selector, selection) on ''X'' is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on ''X'' such that ''f'' is a mapping that assigns each element of ''X'' to one of its ele ...
in ZF without ''any'' form of the axiom of choice. For example,
has a choice function, where
is the set of
hereditarily finite set
In mathematics and set theory, hereditarily finite sets are defined as finite sets whose elements are all hereditarily finite sets. In other words, the set itself is finite, and all of its elements are finite sets, recursively all the way down to t ...
s, i.e. the first set in the
Von Neumann universe
In set theory and related branches of mathematics, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the class of hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ( ...
of non-finite rank. The choice function is (trivially) the least element in the well-ordering. Another example is the set of proper and bounded
open interval
In mathematics, a real interval is the set (mathematics), set of all real numbers lying between two fixed endpoints with no "gaps". Each endpoint is either a real number or positive or negative infinity, indicating the interval extends without ...
s of real numbers with rational endpoints.
ZF+AC
ω suffices to prove that the union of countably many countable sets is countable. These statements are not equivalent: ''
Cohen's First Model'' supplies an example where countable unions of countable sets are countable, but where AC
ω does not hold.
Equivalent forms
There are many equivalent forms to the axiom of countable choice, in the sense that any one of them can be proven in ZF assuming any other of them. They include the following:
*Every countable collection of non-empty sets has a choice function.
*Every infinite collection of non-empty sets has an infinite sub-collection with a choice function.
*Every
σ-compact space
In mathematics, a topological space is said to be ''σ''-compact if it is the union of countably many compact subspaces.
A space is said to be ''σ''-locally compact if it is both ''σ''-compact and (weakly) locally compact. That terminology ...
(the union of countably many
compact space
In mathematics, specifically general topology, compactness is a property that seeks to generalize the notion of a closed and bounded subset of Euclidean space. The idea is that a compact space has no "punctures" or "missing endpoints", i.e., i ...
s) is a
Lindelöf space
In mathematics, a Lindelöf space is a topological space in which every open cover has a countable subcover. The Lindelöf property is a weakening of the more commonly used notion of ''compactness'', which requires the existence of a ''finite'' sub ...
(every open cover has a countable subcover). A
metric space
In mathematics, a metric space is a Set (mathematics), set together with a notion of ''distance'' between its Element (mathematics), elements, usually called point (geometry), points. The distance is measured by a function (mathematics), functi ...
is σ-compact if and only if it is Lindelöf.
*Every
second-countable space (it has a countable base of open sets) is a
separable space
In mathematics, a topological space is called separable if it contains a countable, dense subset; that is, there exists a sequence ( x_n )_^ of elements of the space such that every nonempty open subset of the space contains at least one elemen ...
(it has a countable dense subset). A metric space is separable if and only if it is σ-compact.
*Every
sequentially continuous
In topology and related fields of mathematics, a sequential space is a topological space whose topology can be completely characterized by its convergent/divergent sequences. They can be thought of as spaces that satisfy a very weak axiom of count ...
real-valued function in a metric space is a
continuous function
In mathematics, a continuous function is a function such that a small variation of the argument induces a small variation of the value of the function. This implies there are no abrupt changes in value, known as '' discontinuities''. More preci ...
.
*Every
accumulation point
In mathematics, a limit point, accumulation point, or cluster point of a Set (mathematics), set S in a topological space X is a point x that can be "approximated" by points of S in the sense that every neighbourhood (mathematics), neighbourhood of ...
of a subset of a metric space is a
limit of a sequence of points from the subset.
*The
Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma MA
, a countable form of
Martin's axiom: in a
preorder
In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive relation, reflexive and Transitive relation, transitive. The name is meant to suggest that preorders are ''almost'' partial orders, ...
with the
countable chain condition, every countable family of dense subsets has a
filter intersecting all the subsets. (In this context, a set is called dense if every element of the preorder has a lower bound in the set.)
References
{{DEFAULTSORT:Axiom Of Countable Choice
Axiom of choice