Closure Algebra
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
abstract algebra In mathematics, more specifically algebra, abstract algebra or modern algebra is the study of algebraic structures, which are set (mathematics), sets with specific operation (mathematics), operations acting on their elements. Algebraic structur ...
, an interior algebra is a certain type of
algebraic structure In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
that encodes the idea of the topological interior of a set. Interior algebras are to
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
and the
modal logic Modal logic is a kind of logic used to represent statements about Modality (natural language), necessity and possibility. In philosophy and related fields it is used as a tool for understanding concepts such as knowledge, obligation, and causality ...
S4 what
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
s are to
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
and ordinary
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
. Interior algebras form a variety of modal algebras.


Definition

An interior algebra is an
algebraic structure In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
with the
signature A signature (; from , "to sign") is a depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and intent. Signatures are often, but not always, Handwriting, handwritt ...
:⟨''S'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1, I⟩ where :⟨''S'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1⟩ is a
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
and postfix I designates a unary operator, the interior operator, satisfying the identities: # ''x''I ≤ ''x'' # ''x''II = ''x''I # (''xy'')I = ''x''I''y''I # 1I = 1 ''x''I is called the interior of ''x''. The dual of the interior operator is the closure operator C defined by ''x''C = ((''x''′)I)′. ''x''C is called the closure of ''x''. By the principle of duality, the closure operator satisfies the identities: # ''x''C ≥ ''x'' # ''x''CC = ''x''C # (''x'' + ''y'')C = ''x''C + ''y''C # 0C = 0 If the closure operator is taken as primitive, the interior operator can be defined as ''x''I = ((''x''′)C)′. Thus the theory of interior algebras may be formulated using the closure operator instead of the interior operator, in which case one considers closure algebras of the form ⟨''S'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1, C⟩, where ⟨''S'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1⟩ is again a Boolean algebra and C satisfies the above identities for the closure operator. Closure and interior algebras form dual pairs, and are paradigmatic instances of "Boolean algebras with operators." The early literature on this subject (mainly Polish topology) invoked closure operators, but the interior operator formulation eventually became the norm following the work of Wim Blok.


Open and closed elements

Elements of an interior algebra satisfying the condition ''x''I = ''x'' are called
open Open or OPEN may refer to: Music * Open (band), Australian pop/rock band * The Open (band), English indie rock band * ''Open'' (Blues Image album), 1969 * ''Open'' (Gerd Dudek, Buschi Niebergall, and Edward Vesala album), 1979 * ''Open'' (Go ...
. The complements of open elements are called closed and are characterized by the condition ''x''C = ''x''. An interior of an element is always open and the closure of an element is always closed. Interiors of closed elements are called regular open and closures of open elements are called regular closed. Elements that are both open and closed are called clopen. 0 and 1 are clopen. An interior algebra is called Boolean if all its elements are open (and hence clopen). Boolean interior algebras can be identified with ordinary Boolean algebras as their interior and closure operators provide no meaningful additional structure. A special case is the class of trivial interior algebras, which are the single element interior algebras characterized by the identity 0 = 1.


Morphisms of interior algebras


Homomorphisms

Interior algebras, by virtue of being
algebraic structure In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
s, have
homomorphism In algebra, a homomorphism is a morphism, structure-preserving map (mathematics), map between two algebraic structures of the same type (such as two group (mathematics), groups, two ring (mathematics), rings, or two vector spaces). The word ''homo ...
s. Given two interior algebras ''A'' and ''B'', a map ''f'' : ''A'' → ''B'' is an interior algebra homomorphism
if and only if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
''f'' is a homomorphism between the underlying Boolean algebras of ''A'' and ''B'', that also preserves interiors and closures. Hence: *''f''(''x''I) = ''f''(''x'')I; *''f''(''x''C) = ''f''(''x'')C.


Topomorphisms

Topomorphisms are another important, and more general, class of
morphism In mathematics, a morphism is a concept of category theory that generalizes structure-preserving maps such as homomorphism between algebraic structures, functions from a set to another set, and continuous functions between topological spaces. Al ...
s between interior algebras. A map ''f'' : ''A'' → ''B'' is a topomorphism if and only if ''f'' is a homomorphism between the Boolean algebras underlying ''A'' and ''B'', that also preserves the open and closed elements of ''A''. Hence: * If ''x'' is open in ''A'', then ''f''(''x'') is open in ''B''; * If ''x'' is closed in ''A'', then ''f''(''x'') is closed in ''B''. (Such morphisms have also been called ''stable homomorphisms'' and ''closure algebra semi-homomorphisms''.) Every interior algebra homomorphism is a topomorphism, but not every topomorphism is an interior algebra homomorphism.


Boolean homomorphisms

Early research often considered mappings between interior algebras that were homomorphisms of the underlying Boolean algebras but that did not necessarily preserve the interior or closure operator. Such mappings were called Boolean homomorphisms. (The terms ''closure homomorphism'' or ''topological homomorphism'' were used in the case where these were preserved, but this terminology is now redundant as the standard definition of a homomorphism in
universal algebra Universal algebra (sometimes called general algebra) is the field of mathematics that studies algebraic structures in general, not specific types of algebraic structures. For instance, rather than considering groups or rings as the object of stud ...
requires that it preserves all operations.) Applications involving countably complete interior algebras (in which countable meets and joins always exist, also called ''σ-complete'') typically made use of countably complete Boolean homomorphisms also called Boolean ''σ''-homomorphisms—these preserve countable meets and joins.


Continuous morphisms

The earliest generalization of continuity to interior algebras was Sikorski's, based on the
inverse image In mathematics, for a function f: X \to Y, the image of an input value x is the single output value produced by f when passed x. The preimage of an output value y is the set of input values that produce y. More generally, evaluating f at each ...
map of a continuous map. This is a Boolean homomorphism, preserves unions of sequences and includes the closure of an inverse image in the inverse image of the closure. Sikorski thus defined a ''continuous homomorphism'' as a Boolean ''σ''-homomorphism ''f'' between two ''σ''-complete interior algebras such that ''f''(''x'')C ≤ ''f''(''x''C). This definition had several difficulties: The construction acts contravariantly producing a dual of a continuous map rather than a generalization. On the one hand ''σ''-completeness is too weak to characterize inverse image maps (completeness is required), on the other hand it is too restrictive for a generalization. (Sikorski remarked on using non-''σ''-complete homomorphisms but included ''σ''-completeness in his axioms for ''closure algebras''.) Later J. Schmid defined a continuous homomorphism or continuous morphism for interior algebras as a Boolean homomorphism ''f'' between two interior algebras satisfying ''f''(''x''C) ≤ ''f''(''x'')C. This generalizes the forward image map of a continuous map—the image of a closure is contained in the closure of the image. This construction is covariant but not suitable for category theoretic applications as it only allows construction of continuous morphisms from continuous maps in the case of bijections. (C. Naturman returned to Sikorski's approach while dropping ''σ''-completeness to produce topomorphisms as defined above. In this terminology, Sikorski's original "continuous homomorphisms" are ''σ''-complete topomorphisms between ''σ''-complete interior algebras.)


Relationships to other areas of mathematics


Topology

Given a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
''X'' = ⟨''X'', ''T''⟩ one can form the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
Boolean algebra of ''X'': : and extend it to an interior algebra :, where I is the usual topological interior operator. For all ''S'' ⊆ ''X'' it is defined by : For all ''S'' ⊆ ''X'' the corresponding closure operator is given by : ''S''I is the largest open subset of ''S'' and ''S''C is the smallest closed superset of ''S'' in ''X''. The open, closed, regular open, regular closed and clopen elements of the interior algebra ''A''(''X'') are just the open, closed, regular open, regular closed and clopen subsets of ''X'' respectively in the usual topological sense. Every complete atomic interior algebra is
isomorphic In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping or morphism between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between the ...
to an interior algebra of the form ''A''(''X'') for some
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
''X''. Moreover, every interior algebra can be embedded in such an interior algebra giving a representation of an interior algebra as a topological field of sets. The properties of the structure ''A''(''X'') are the very motivation for the definition of interior algebras. Because of this intimate connection with topology, interior algebras have also been called topo-Boolean algebras or topological Boolean algebras. Given a continuous map between two topological spaces : we can define a complete topomorphism : by :''A''(''f'')(''S'') = ''f''−1 'S'' for all subsets ''S'' of ''Y''. Every complete topomorphism between two complete atomic interior algebras can be derived in this way. If Top is the
category of topological spaces In mathematics, the category of topological spaces, often denoted Top, is the category whose objects are topological spaces and whose morphisms are continuous maps. This is a category because the composition of two continuous maps is again con ...
and continuous maps and Cit is the
category Category, plural categories, may refer to: General uses *Classification, the general act of allocating things to classes/categories Philosophy * Category of being * ''Categories'' (Aristotle) * Category (Kant) * Categories (Peirce) * Category ( ...
of complete atomic interior algebras and complete topomorphisms then Top and Cit are dually isomorphic and is a
contravariant functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a mapping between categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) are associated to topological spaces, and ...
that is a dual isomorphism of categories. ''A''(''f'') is a homomorphism if and only if ''f'' is a continuous
open map In mathematics, more specifically in topology, an open map is a function between two topological spaces that maps open sets to open sets. That is, a function f : X \to Y is open if for any open set U in X, the image f(U) is open in Y. Likewise, ...
. Under this dual isomorphism of categories many natural topological properties correspond to algebraic properties, in particular connectedness properties correspond to irreducibility properties: *''X'' is empty if and only if ''A''(''X'') is trivial *''X'' is indiscrete if and only if ''A''(''X'') is
simple Simple or SIMPLE may refer to: *Simplicity, the state or quality of being simple Arts and entertainment * ''Simple'' (album), by Andy Yorke, 2008, and its title track * "Simple" (Florida Georgia Line song), 2018 * "Simple", a song by John ...
*''X'' is
discrete Discrete may refer to: *Discrete particle or quantum in physics, for example in quantum theory * Discrete device, an electronic component with just one circuit element, either passive or active, other than an integrated circuit * Discrete group, ...
if and only if ''A''(''X'') is Boolean *''X'' is almost discrete if and only if ''A''(''X'') is semisimple *''X'' is finitely generated (Alexandrov) if and only if ''A''(''X'') is operator complete i.e. its interior and closure operators distribute over arbitrary meets and joins respectively *''X'' is connected if and only if ''A''(''X'') is directly indecomposable *''X'' is ultraconnected if and only if ''A''(''X'') is finitely subdirectly irreducible *''X'' is
compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact, a type of agreement used by U.S. states * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a t ...
ultra-connected if and only if ''A''(''X'') is subdirectly irreducible


Generalized topology

The modern formulation of topological spaces in terms of topologies of open subsets, motivates an alternative formulation of interior algebras: A generalized topological space is an
algebraic structure In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
of the form :⟨''B'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1, ''T''⟩ where ⟨''B'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1⟩ is a Boolean algebra as usual, and ''T'' is a unary relation on ''B'' (subset of ''B'') such that: # #''T'' is closed under arbitrary joins (i.e. if a join of an arbitrary subset of ''T'' exists then it will be in ''T'') #''T'' is closed under finite meets #For every element ''b'' of ''B'', the join exists ''T'' is said to be a generalized topology in the Boolean algebra. Given an interior algebra its open elements form a generalized topology. Conversely given a generalized topological space :⟨''B'', ·, +, ′, 0, 1, ''T''⟩ we can define an interior operator on ''B'' by thereby producing an interior algebra whose open elements are precisely ''T''. Thus generalized topological spaces are equivalent to interior algebras. Considering interior algebras to be generalized topological spaces, topomorphisms are then the standard homomorphisms of Boolean algebras with added relations, so that standard results from
universal algebra Universal algebra (sometimes called general algebra) is the field of mathematics that studies algebraic structures in general, not specific types of algebraic structures. For instance, rather than considering groups or rings as the object of stud ...
apply.


Neighbourhood functions and neighbourhood lattices

The topological concept of
neighbourhood A neighbourhood (Commonwealth English) or neighborhood (American English) is a geographically localized community within a larger town, city, suburb or rural area, sometimes consisting of a single street and the buildings lining it. Neighbourh ...
s can be generalized to interior algebras: An element ''y'' of an interior algebra is said to be a neighbourhood of an element ''x'' if . The set of neighbourhoods of ''x'' is denoted by ''N''(''x'') and forms a filter. This leads to another formulation of interior algebras: A neighbourhood function on a Boolean algebra is a mapping ''N'' from its underlying set ''B'' to its set of filters, such that: #For all exists #For all if and only if there is a such that and . The mapping ''N'' of elements of an interior algebra to their filters of neighbourhoods is a neighbourhood function on the underlying Boolean algebra of the interior algebra. Moreover, given a neighbourhood function ''N'' on a Boolean algebra with underlying set ''B'', we can define an interior operator by thereby obtaining an interior algebra. will then be precisely the filter of neighbourhoods of ''x'' in this interior algebra. Thus interior algebras are equivalent to Boolean algebras with specified neighbourhood functions. In terms of neighbourhood functions, the open elements are precisely those elements ''x'' such that . In terms of open elements if and only if there is an open element ''z'' such that . Neighbourhood functions may be defined more generally on (meet)-semilattices producing the structures known as neighbourhood (semi)lattices. Interior algebras may thus be viewed as precisely the Boolean neighbourhood lattices i.e. those neighbourhood lattices whose underlying semilattice forms a Boolean algebra.


Modal logic

Given a
theory A theory is a systematic and rational form of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the conclusions derived from such thinking. It involves contemplative and logical reasoning, often supported by processes such as observation, experimentation, ...
(set of formal sentences) ''M'' in the modal logic S4, we can form its Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra: :''L''(''M'') = ⟨''M'' / ~, ∧, ∨, ¬, ''F'', ''T'', □⟩ where ~ is the equivalence relation on sentences in ''M'' given by ''p'' ~ ''q'' if and only if ''p'' and ''q'' are logically equivalent in ''M'', and ''M'' / ~ is the set of equivalence classes under this relation. Then ''L''(''M'') is an interior algebra. The interior operator in this case corresponds to the modal operator □ (necessarily), while the closure operator corresponds to ◊ (possibly). This construction is a special case of a more general result for modal algebras and modal logic. The open elements of ''L''(''M'') correspond to sentences that are only true if they are necessarily true, while the closed elements correspond to those that are only false if they are necessarily false. Because of their relation to S4, interior algebras are sometimes called S4 algebras or Lewis algebras, after the logician C. I. Lewis, who first proposed the modal logics S4 and S5.


Preorders

Since interior algebras are (normal)
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
s with operators, they can be represented by fields of sets on appropriate relational structures. In particular, since they are modal algebras, they can be represented as fields of sets on a set with a single
binary relation In mathematics, a binary relation associates some elements of one Set (mathematics), set called the ''domain'' with some elements of another set called the ''codomain''. Precisely, a binary relation over sets X and Y is a set of ordered pairs ...
, called a Kripke frame. The Kripke frames corresponding to interior algebras are precisely the preordered sets. Preordered sets (also called ''S4-frames'') provide the Kripke semantics of the modal logic S4, and the connection between interior algebras and preorders is deeply related to their connection with modal logic. Given a preordered set ''X'' = ⟨''X'', «⟩ we can construct an interior algebra : from the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
of ''X'' where the interior operator I is given by : for all ''S'' ⊆ ''X''. The corresponding closure operator is given by : for all ''S'' ⊆ ''X''. ''S''I is the set of all ''worlds'' inaccessible from ''worlds'' outside ''S'', and ''S''C is the set of all ''worlds'' accessible from some ''world'' in ''S''. Every interior algebra can be embedded in an interior algebra of the form ''B''(''X'') for some preordered set ''X'' giving the above-mentioned representation as a field of sets (a preorder field). This construction and representation theorem is a special case of the more general result for modal algebras and Kripke frames. In this regard, interior algebras are particularly interesting because of their connection to
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
. The construction provides the preordered set ''X'' with a
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
, the
Alexandrov topology In general topology, an Alexandrov topology is a topology in which the intersection of an ''arbitrary'' family of open sets is open (while the definition of a topology only requires this for a ''finite'' family). Equivalently, an Alexandrov top ...
, producing a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a Geometry, geometrical space in which Closeness (mathematics), closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric Distance (mathematics), distance. More specifically, a to ...
''T''(''X'') whose open sets are: :. The corresponding closed sets are: :. In other words, the open sets are the ones whose ''worlds'' are inaccessible from outside (the up-sets), and the closed sets are the ones for which every outside ''world'' is inaccessible from inside (the down-sets). Moreover, ''B''(''X'') = ''A''(''T''(''X'')).


Monadic Boolean algebras

Any monadic Boolean algebra can be considered to be an interior algebra where the interior operator is the universal quantifier and the closure operator is the existential quantifier. The monadic Boolean algebras are then precisely the variety of interior algebras satisfying the identity ''x''IC = ''x''I. In other words, they are precisely the interior algebras in which every open element is closed or equivalently, in which every closed element is open. Moreover, such interior algebras are precisely the semisimple interior algebras. They are also the interior algebras corresponding to the modal logic S5, and so have also been called S5 algebras. In the relationship between preordered sets and interior algebras they correspond to the case where the preorder is an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
, reflecting the fact that such preordered sets provide the Kripke semantics for S5. This also reflects the relationship between the monadic logic of quantification (for which monadic Boolean algebras provide an algebraic description) and S5 where the modal operators □ (necessarily) and ◊ (possibly) can be interpreted in the Kripke semantics using monadic universal and existential quantification, respectively, without reference to an accessibility relation.


Heyting algebras

The open elements of an interior algebra form a Heyting algebra and the closed elements form a dual Heyting algebra. The regular open elements and regular closed elements correspond to the pseudo-complemented elements and dual pseudo-complemented elements of these algebras respectively and thus form Boolean algebras. The clopen elements correspond to the complemented elements and form a common subalgebra of these Boolean algebras as well as of the interior algebra itself. Every Heyting algebra can be represented as the open elements of an interior algebra and the latter may be chosen to be an interior algebra generated by its open elements—such interior algebras correspond one-to-one with Heyting algebras (up to isomorphism) being the free Boolean extensions of the latter. Heyting algebras play the same role for
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
that interior algebras play for the modal logic S4 and
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
s play for
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
. The relation between Heyting algebras and interior algebras reflects the relationship between intuitionistic logic and S4, in which one can interpret theories of intuitionistic logic as S4 theories closed under necessity. The one-to-one correspondence between Heyting algebras and interior algebras generated by their open elements reflects the correspondence between extensions of intuitionistic logic and normal extensions of the modal logic S4.Grz.


Derivative algebras

Given an interior algebra ''A'', the closure operator obeys the axioms of the derivative operator, D. Hence we can form a derivative algebra ''D''(''A'') with the same underlying Boolean algebra as ''A'' by using the closure operator as a derivative operator. Thus interior algebras are derivative algebras. From this perspective, they are precisely the variety of derivative algebras satisfying the identity ''x''D ≥ ''x''. Derivative algebras provide the appropriate algebraic semantics for the modal logic wK4. Hence derivative algebras stand to topological derived sets and wK4 as interior/closure algebras stand to topological interiors/closures and S4. Given a derivative algebra ''V'' with derivative operator D, we can form an interior algebra with the same underlying Boolean algebra as ''V'', with interior and closure operators defined by and , respectively. Thus every derivative algebra can be regarded as an interior algebra. Moreover, given an interior algebra ''A'', we have . However, {{math, 1=''D''(''I''(''V'')) = ''V'' does ''not'' necessarily hold for every derivative algebra ''V''.


Stone duality and representation for interior algebras

Stone duality provides a category theoretic duality between Boolean algebras and a class of topological spaces known as Boolean spaces. Building on nascent ideas of relational semantics (later formalized by Kripke) and a result of R. S. Pierce, Jónsson, Tarski and G. Hansoul extended Stone duality to Boolean algebras with operators by equipping Boolean spaces with relations that correspond to the operators via a power set construction. In the case of interior algebras the interior (or closure) operator corresponds to a pre-order on the Boolean space. Homomorphisms between interior algebras correspond to a class of continuous maps between the Boolean spaces known as pseudo-epimorphisms or p-morphisms for short. This generalization of Stone duality to interior algebras based on the Jónsson–Tarski representation was investigated by Leo Esakia and is also known as the ''Esakia duality for S4-algebras (interior algebras)'' and is closely related to the Esakia duality for Heyting algebras. Whereas the Jónsson–Tarski generalization of Stone duality applies to Boolean algebras with operators in general, the connection between interior algebras and topology allows for another method of generalizing Stone duality that is unique to interior algebras. An intermediate step in the development of Stone duality is
Stone's representation theorem In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first ha ...
, which represents a Boolean algebra as a field of sets. The Stone topology of the corresponding Boolean space is then generated using the field of sets as a topological basis. Building on the topological semantics introduced by Tang Tsao-Chen for Lewis's modal logic, McKinsey and Tarski showed that by generating a topology equivalent to using only the complexes that correspond to open elements as a basis, a representation of an interior algebra is obtained as a topological field of sets—a field of sets on a topological space that is closed with respect to taking interiors or closures. By equipping topological fields of sets with appropriate morphisms known as field maps, C. Naturman showed that this approach can be formalized as a category theoretic Stone duality in which the usual Stone duality for Boolean algebras corresponds to the case of interior algebras having redundant interior operator (Boolean interior algebras). The pre-order obtained in the Jónsson–Tarski approach corresponds to the accessibility relation in the Kripke semantics for an S4 theory, while the intermediate field of sets corresponds to a representation of the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra for the theory using the sets of possible worlds in the Kripke semantics in which sentences of the theory hold. Moving from the field of sets to a Boolean space somewhat obfuscates this connection. By treating fields of sets on pre-orders as a category in its own right this deep connection can be formulated as a category theoretic duality that generalizes Stone representation without topology. R. Goldblatt had shown that with restrictions to appropriate homomorphisms such a duality can be formulated for arbitrary modal algebras and Kripke frames. Naturman showed that in the case of interior algebras this duality applies to more general topomorphisms and can be factored via a category theoretic functor through the duality with topological fields of sets. The latter represent the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra using sets of points satisfying sentences of the S4 theory in the topological semantics. The pre-order can be obtained as the specialization pre-order of the McKinsey–Tarski topology. The Esakia duality can be recovered via a functor that replaces the field of sets with the Boolean space it generates. Via a functor that instead replaces the pre-order with its corresponding Alexandrov topology, an alternative representation of the interior algebra as a field of sets is obtained where the topology is the Alexandrov bico-reflection of the McKinsey–Tarski topology. The approach of formulating a topological duality for interior algebras using both the Stone topology of the Jónsson–Tarski approach and the Alexandrov topology of the pre-order to form a bi-topological space has been investigated by G. Bezhanishvili, R.Mines, and P.J. Morandi. The McKinsey–Tarski topology of an interior algebra is the intersection of the former two topologies.


Metamathematics

Grzegorczyk proved the first-order theory of closure algebras undecidable.According to footnote 19 in McKinsey and Tarski, 1944, the result had been proved earlier by Stanisław Jaśkowski in 1939, but remained unpublished and not accessible ''in view of the present t the timewar conditions''. Naturman demonstrated that the theory is hereditarily undecidable (all its subtheories are undecidable) and demonstrated an infinite chain of elementary classes of interior algebras with hereditarily undecidable theories.


Notes


References

* Blok, W.A., 1976, ''Varieties of interior algebras,'' Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam. * Esakia, L., 2004,
Intuitionistic logic and modality via topology
" '' Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 127'': 155–70. * McKinsey, J.C.C. and
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
, 1944, "The Algebra of Topology," ''
Annals of Mathematics The ''Annals of Mathematics'' is a mathematical journal published every two months by Princeton University and the Institute for Advanced Study. History The journal was established as ''The Analyst'' in 1874 and with Joel E. Hendricks as t ...
45'': 141–91. * Naturman, C.A., 1991, ''Interior Algebras and Topology'', Ph.D. thesis, University of Cape Town Department of Mathematics. * Bezhanishvili, G., Mines, R. and Morandi, P.J., 2008, ''Topo-canonical completions of closure algebras and Heyting algebras'', '' Algebra Universalis 58'': 1–34. * Schmid, J., 1973, ''On the compactification of closure algebras'', ''
Fundamenta Mathematicae ''Fundamenta Mathematicae'' is a peer-reviewed scientific journal of mathematics with a special focus on the foundations of mathematics, concentrating on set theory, mathematical logic, topology and its interactions with algebra, and dynamical sys ...
79'': 33–48 * Sikorski R., 1955, ''Closure homomorphisms and interior mappings'', ''Fundamenta Mathematicae 41'': 12–20 Algebraic structures Mathematical logic Boolean algebra Closure operators Modal logic