In
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of for ...
, a
theory
A theory is a rational type of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the results of such thinking. The process of contemplative and rational thinking is often associated with such processes as observational study or research. Theories may be s ...
is categorical if it has exactly one
model (
up to isomorphism Two mathematical objects ''a'' and ''b'' are called equal up to an equivalence relation ''R''
* if ''a'' and ''b'' are related by ''R'', that is,
* if ''aRb'' holds, that is,
* if the equivalence classes of ''a'' and ''b'' with respect to ''R'' a ...
). Such a theory can be viewed as ''defining'' its model, uniquely characterizing the model's structure.
In
first-order logic, only theories with a
finite model can be categorical.
Higher-order logic contains categorical theories with an
infinite model. For example, the second-order
Peano axioms are categorical, having a unique model whose domain is the
set
Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to:
Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics
*Set (mathematics), a collection of elements
*Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively
Electro ...
of natural numbers
In
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the s ...
, the notion of a categorical theory is refined with respect to
cardinality
In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
. A theory is -categorical (or categorical in ) if it has exactly one model of cardinality up to isomorphism. Morley's categoricity theorem is a theorem of stating that if a
first-order theory
First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantif ...
in a
countable language is categorical in some
uncountable cardinality
In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
, then it is categorical in all uncountable cardinalities.
extended Morley's theorem to uncountable languages: if the language has cardinality and a theory is categorical in some uncountable cardinal greater than or equal to then it is categorical in all cardinalities greater than .
History and motivation
Oswald Veblen
Oswald Veblen (June 24, 1880 – August 10, 1960) was an American mathematician, geometer and topologist, whose work found application in atomic physics and the theory of relativity
The theory of relativity usually encompasses two interrelat ...
in 1904 defined a theory to be categorical if all of its models are isomorphic. It follows from the definition above and the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem
In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem.
The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order t ...
that any
first-order theory
First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantif ...
with a model of infinite
cardinality
In mathematics, the cardinality of a set is a measure of the number of elements of the set. For example, the set A = \ contains 3 elements, and therefore A has a cardinality of 3. Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept was generalized ...
cannot be categorical. One is then immediately led to the more subtle notion of -categoricity, which asks: for which cardinals is there exactly one model of cardinality of the given theory ''T'' up to isomorphism? This is a deep question and significant progress was only made in 1954 when
Jerzy Łoś
Jerzy Łoś (born 22 March 1920 in Lwów, Poland (now Lviv, Ukraine) – 1 June 1998 in Warsaw) () was a Polish mathematician, logician, economist, and philosopher. He is especially known for his work in model theory, in particular for "Łoś's the ...
noticed that, at least for
complete theories ''T'' over countable
languages
Language is a structured system of communication. The structure of a language is its grammar and the free components are its vocabulary. Languages are the primary means by which humans communicate, and may be conveyed through a variety of met ...
with at least one infinite model, he could only find three ways for ''T'' to be -categorical at some :
*''T'' is totally categorical, ''i.e.'' ''T'' is -categorical for all infinite
cardinal
Cardinal or The Cardinal may refer to:
Animals
* Cardinal (bird) or Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds
**''Cardinalis'', genus of cardinal in the family Cardinalidae
**''Cardinalis cardinalis'', or northern cardinal, the ...
s .
*''T'' is uncountably categorical, ''i.e.'' ''T'' is -categorical if and only if is an
uncountable cardinal.
*''T'' is
countably categorical, ''i.e.'' ''T'' is -categorical if and only if is a countable cardinal.
In other words, he observed that, in all the cases he could think of, -categoricity at any one uncountable cardinal implied -categoricity at all other uncountable cardinals. This observation spurred a great amount of research into the 1960s, eventually culminating in
Michael Morley's famous result that these are in fact the only possibilities. The theory was subsequently extended and refined by
Saharon Shelah
Saharon Shelah ( he, שהרן שלח; born July 3, 1945) is an Israeli mathematician. He is a professor of mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University in New Jersey.
Biography
Shelah was born in Jerusalem on July 3, ...
in the 1970s and beyond, leading to
stability theory
In mathematics, stability theory addresses the stability of solutions of differential equations and of trajectories of dynamical systems under small perturbations of initial conditions. The heat equation, for example, is a stable partial diffe ...
and Shelah's more general programme of
classification theory.
Examples
There are not many natural examples of theories that are categorical in some uncountable cardinal. The known examples include:
* Pure identity theory (with no functions, constants, predicates other than "=", or axioms).
* The classic example is the theory of
algebraically closed fields
Fields may refer to:
Music
*Fields (band), an indie rock band formed in 2006
*Fields (progressive rock band), a progressive rock band formed in 1971
* ''Fields'' (album), an LP by Swedish-based indie rock band Junip (2010)
* "Fields", a song by ...
of a given
characteristic. Categoricity does ''not'' say that all algebraically closed fields of characteristic 0 as large as the
complex numbers C are the same as C; it only asserts that they are isomorphic ''as fields'' to C. It follows that although the completed
''p''-adic closures C
''p'' are all isomorphic as fields to C, they may (and in fact do) have completely different
topological and analytic properties. The theory of algebraically closed fields of given characteristic is not categorical in (the countable infinite cardinal); there are models of
transcendence degree 0, 1, 2, ..., .
*
Vector space
In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set whose elements, often called ''vectors'', may be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called '' scalars''. Scalars are often real numbers, but can ...
s over a given countable field. This includes
abelian group
In mathematics, an abelian group, also called a commutative group, is a group in which the result of applying the group operation to two group elements does not depend on the order in which they are written. That is, the group operation is commut ...
s of given
prime
A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime because the only ways ...
exponent
Exponentiation is a mathematical operation, written as , involving two numbers, the '' base'' and the ''exponent'' or ''power'' , and pronounced as " (raised) to the (power of) ". When is a positive integer, exponentiation corresponds to re ...
(essentially the same as vector spaces over a finite field) and
divisible torsion-free abelian group
In mathematics, specifically in abstract algebra, a torsion-free abelian group is an abelian group which has no non-trivial torsion elements; that is, a group in which the group operation is commutative and the identity element is the only elemen ...
s (essentially the same as vector spaces over the
rationals).
* The theory of the set of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country").
Numbers used for counting are called ''Cardinal n ...
s with a successor function.
There are also examples of theories that are categorical in but not categorical in uncountable cardinals.
The simplest example is the theory of an
equivalence relation
In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation.
Each equivalence relation ...
with exactly two
equivalence class
In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
es, both of which are infinite. Another example is the theory of
dense
Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the substance's mass per unit of volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' can also be used. Mathematically ...
linear orders with no endpoints;
Cantor proved that any such countable linear order is isomorphic to the rational numbers: see
Cantor's isomorphism theorem.
Properties
Every categorical theory is
complete
Complete may refer to:
Logic
* Completeness (logic)
* Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable
Mathematics
* The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
. However, the converse does not hold.
Any theory ''T'' categorical in some infinite cardinal is very close to being complete. More precisely, the
Łoś–Vaught test In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, the Łoś–Vaught test is a criterion for a theory to be complete, unable to be augmented without becoming inconsistent. For theories in classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic or Frege-R ...
states that if a satisfiable theory has no finite models and is categorical in some infinite cardinal at least equal to the cardinality of its language, then the theory is complete. The reason is that all infinite models are first-order equivalent to some model of cardinal by the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem
In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem.
The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order t ...
, and so are all equivalent as the theory is categorical in . Therefore, the theory is complete as all models are equivalent. The assumption that the theory have no finite models is necessary.
[Marker (2002) p. 42]
See also
*
Spectrum of a theory
In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, the spectrum of a theory
is given by the number of isomorphism classes of models in various cardinalities. More precisely,
for any complete theory ''T'' in a language we write ''I''(''T'', ''κ'') ...
Notes
References
*
*
Hodges, Wilfrid, "First-order Model Theory", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).*
*
*
*
*
* (IX, 1.19, pg.49)
*
{{Mathematical logic
Mathematical logic
Model theory
Theorems in the foundations of mathematics