Asymmetry (population Ethics)
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The Asymmetry, also known as the Procreation Asymmetry, is the idea in
population ethics Population ethics is the philosophical study of the ethical problems arising when our actions affect ''who'' is born and ''how many'' people are born in the future. An important area within population ethics is population axiology, which is "the s ...
that there is a
moral A moral (from Latin ''morālis'') is a message that is conveyed or a lesson to be learned from a story or event. The moral may be left to the hearer, reader, or viewer to determine for themselves, or may be explicitly encapsulated in a maxim. ...
or evaluative asymmetry between bringing into existence individuals with good or bad lives. It was first discussed by Jan Narveson in 1967, and Jeff McMahan coined the term 'the Asymmetry' in 1981. McMahan formulates the Asymmetry as follows: "while the fact that a person's life would be worse than no life at all ... constitutes a strong moral reason for not bringing him into existence, the fact that a person's life would be worth living provides no (or only a relatively weak) moral reason for bringing him into existence." Professor Nils Holtug formulates the Asymmetry evaluatively in terms of the value of outcomes instead of in terms of moral reasons. Holtug's formulation says that "while it detracts from the value of an outcome to add individuals whose lives are of overall negative value, it does not increase the value of an outcome to add individuals whose lives are of overall positive value." Much of the literature on the ethics of procreation deals with the Asymmetry. A number of authors have defended the Asymmetry, and a number of authors have argued against it. Many who defend the asymmetry appeal to its intuitiveness. However, more elaborated defences of the asymmetry have been yielded. For instance, Jan Narveson argues that:
If we cause a miserable child to come into existence, there will exist a child who will have a justified complaint, while if we refrain from causing a happy child to come into existence, this child will not exist and so can have no complaint.
Against Narverson's argument, Timothy Sprigge has claimed that if we give a miserable child a genuine reason to complain by bringing her into existence we also give a happy child a genuine reason to be grateful. Professor Sprigge's argument highlights that Narveson's claim does not explain why the future of the miserable child is special but the future of the happy child is not special in the same way. Parfit solves this issue by holding these views:
(1) appeal to the Person-affecting Restriction, (2) claim that causing someone to exist can be either good or bad for him, and (3) appeal to the Narrow Principle. According to the Narrow Principle, it is wrong, if other things are equal, to do what would be either bad for, or worse for, the people who ever live. It is therefore wrong to have the Wretched Child, since this would be bad for him. But it is in no way wrong to fail to have the Happy Child.
The Narrow principle justifies Narveson's defence of the asymmetry. However, this has been contested. For instance, Nils Holtug holds that the asymmetry is incompatible with a person-affecting solution to the
nonidentity problem The nonidentity problem (also called the paradox of future individuals) is a problem in population ethics concerning actions that affect the existence, identity, or well-being of future people. It arises from the observation that even small chang ...
and, in addition, it is counterintuitive in another case. Suppose that in the future the last inhabitants of the earth can populate the world again or refrain from procreating and thus bring an end to the human race. Whatever they do, these already existing individuals will be equally happy. Even if they could bring billions of happy individuals into existence, there would surely be a few of them whose existence would be miserable and, hence, given the asymmetry they should bring about the end of the human race since the happiness of those possible billions of individuals counts for nothing compared to the suffering of those who would have miserable lives. To avoid this radical separation between happiness and suffering, Holtug appeals instead to the Weak Asymmetry:
Everything else being equal, it is better to avoid that a person comes into existence and has a life worth not living (at level –n), than to ensure that a person comes into existence and has a life worth living (at level n).
This allows to give extra weight to the badness of bringing miserable lives into existence but also allows to outweight small quantities by much larger ones when comparing suffering and happiness.


Additional perspectives

The asymmetry in population ethics is further supported by views emphasizing the moral urgency of suffering over happiness. Christoph Fehige's antifrustrationist view argues that preventing frustrated preferences is more morally significant than creating satisfied ones, aligning with the idea that suffering has a greater moral claim. Similarly, Michael St. Jules suggests that pleasure only matters if it affects someone experiencing it, highlighting the asymmetry between the moral imperatives of alleviating suffering and promoting happiness. These perspectives underscore the ethical priority of avoiding harm and misery, reinforcing the core principles of the asymmetry in population ethics.


World destruction objection

A key challenge to the Asymmetry is the argument that preventing even minor suffering could justify extreme actions, such as destroying a paradise of blissful individuals. However, this scenario introduces concerns beyond the core asymmetry debate, such as world destruction. A refined perspective considers a case where no sentient beings yet exist. If we could create a paradise by imposing suffering on one being, refusing to do so does not seem morally wrong. This highlights a core intuition behind the Asymmetry: suffering cannot be justified by the creation of happiness, reinforcing the idea that bad outcomes outweigh good ones.


See also

* Antifrustrationism *
Antinatalism Antinatalism or anti-natalism is the philosophical value judgment that procreation is unethical or unjustifiable. Antinatalists thus argue that humans should abstain from making children. Some antinatalists consider coming into existence to alw ...
*
Benatar's asymmetry argument Benatar's asymmetry argument for antinatalism Antinatalism or anti-natalism is the philosophical value judgment that procreation is unethical or unjustifiable. Antinatalists thus argue that humans should abstain from making children. Some antin ...
*
Natalism Natalism (also called pronatalism or the pro-birth position) is a policy paradigm or personal value that promotes the reproduction of human life as an important objective of humanity and therefore advocates a high birthrate. Cf.: According to t ...
* Negative Consequentialism *
Negative Utilitarianism Negative utilitarianism is a form of negative consequentialism that can be described as the view that people should minimize the total amount of aggregate suffering, or that they should minimize suffering and then, secondarily, maximize the tot ...
*
Person-affecting view A person-affecting or person-based view (also called person-affecting restriction) in population ethics captures the intuition that an act can only be bad if it is bad ''for'' someone. Similarly something can be good only if it is good ''for'' some ...
*
Suffering-focused ethics Suffering-focused ethics are those views in ethics according to which reducing suffering is either a key priority or our only aim. Those suffering-focused ethics according to which the reduction of suffering is a key priority are pluralistic views ...


Citations


References

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *


Further reading

*


External links

* {{DEFAULTSORT:Asymmetry Population ethics Asymmetry