
In
logic, (
Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (
Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical arguments'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absurdity or contradiction.
This argument form traces back to
Ancient Greek philosophy
Ancient Greek philosophy arose in the 6th century BC, marking the end of the Greek Dark Ages. Greek philosophy continued throughout the Hellenistic period and the period in which Greece and most Greek-inhabited lands were part of the Roman Empire ...
and has been used throughout history in both formal mathematical and philosophical reasoning, as well as in debate.
Examples
The "absurd" conclusion of a ''reductio ad absurdum'' argument can take a range of forms, as these examples show:
* The Earth cannot be flat; otherwise, since Earth assumed to be finite in extent, we would find people falling off the edge.
* There is no smallest positive
rational number because, if there were, then it could be divided by two to get a smaller one.
The first example argues that denial of the premise would result in a ridiculous conclusion, against the evidence of our senses. The second example is a mathematical
proof by contradiction (also known as an indirect proof
), which argues that the denial of the premise would result in a
logical contradiction (there is a "smallest" number and yet there is a number smaller than it).
Greek philosophy
''Reductio ad absurdum'' was used throughout
Greek philosophy. The earliest example of a argument can be found in a satirical poem attributed to
Xenophanes of Colophon (c. 570 – c. 475 BCE).
Criticizing
Homer's attribution of human faults to the gods, Xenophanes states that humans also believe that the gods' bodies have human form. But if horses and oxen could draw, they would draw the gods with horse and ox bodies. The gods cannot have both forms, so this is a contradiction. Therefore, the attribution of other human characteristics to the gods, such as human faults, is also false.
Greek mathematicians proved fundamental propositions using ''reductio ad absurdum''.
Euclid of Alexandria (mid-4th – mid-3rd centuries BCE) and
Archimedes of Syracuse (c. 287 – c. 212 BCE) are two very early examples.
The earlier dialogues of
Plato (424–348 BCE), relating the discourses of
Socrates, raised the use of arguments to a formal dialectical method (), also called the
Socratic method.
Typically, Socrates' opponent would make what would seem to be an innocuous assertion. In response, Socrates, via a step-by-step train of reasoning, bringing in other background assumptions, would make the person admit that the assertion resulted in an absurd or contradictory conclusion, forcing him to abandon his assertion and adopt a position of
aporia.
The technique was also a focus of the work of
Aristotle (384–322 BCE), particularly in his ''
Prior Analytics
The ''Prior Analytics'' ( grc-gre, Ἀναλυτικὰ Πρότερα; la, Analytica Priora) is a work by Aristotle on reasoning, known as his syllogistic, composed around 350 BCE. Being one of the six extant Aristotelian writings on logic ...
'' where he referred to it as ( grc-gre, ἡ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον ἀπόδειξις, , demonstration to the impossible, 62b).
The
Pyrrhonists
Pyrrho of Elis (; grc, Πύρρων ὁ Ἠλεῖος, Pyrrhо̄n ho Ēleios; ), born in Elis, Greece, was a Greek philosopher of Classical antiquity, credited as being the first Greek Philosophical skepticism, skeptic philosopher and found ...
and the
Academic Skeptics
An academy (Attic Greek: Ἀκαδήμεια; Koine Greek Ἀκαδημία) is an institution of secondary or tertiary higher learning (and generally also research or honorary membership). The name traces back to Plato's school of philosophy, ...
extensively used ''reductio ad absurdum'' arguments to refute the
dogmas of the other schools of
Hellenistic philosophy
Hellenistic philosophy is a time-frame for Western philosophy and Ancient Greek philosophy corresponding to the Hellenistic period. It is purely external and encompasses disparate intellectual content. There is no single philosophical school or cu ...
.
Buddhist philosophy
Much of
Madhyamaka Buddhist philosophy centers on showing how various
essentialist ideas have absurd conclusions through ''reductio ad absurdum'' arguments (known as ''prasaṅga'' - "consequence" - in Sanskrit). In the
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā,
Nāgārjuna's ''reductio ad absurdum'' arguments are used to show that any theory of substance or essence was unsustainable and therefore, phenomena (''dharmas'') such as change, causality, and sense perception were empty (''sunya'') of any essential existence. Nāgārjuna's main goal is often seen by scholars as refuting the essentialism of certain Buddhist
Abhidharma schools (mainly
''Vaibhasika'') which posited theories of ''
svabhava'' (essential nature) and also the Hindu
Nyāya
(Sanskrit: न्याय, ''nyā-yá''), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment",[Vaiśeṣika
Vaisheshika or Vaiśeṣika ( sa, वैशेषिक) is one of the six schools of Indian philosophy (Vedic systems) from ancient India. In its early stages, the Vaiśeṣika was an independent philosophy with its own metaphysics, epistemolog ...]
schools which posited a theory of ontological substances (''dravyatas'').
[Wasler, Joseph. ''Nagarjuna in Context.'' New York: Columibia University Press. 2005, pgs. 225-263.]
Principle of non-contradiction
Aristotle clarified the connection between contradiction and falsity in his
principle of non-contradiction, which states that a proposition cannot be both true and false.
That is, a proposition
and its negation
(not-''Q'') cannot both be true. Therefore, if a proposition and its negation can both be derived logically from a premise, it can be concluded that the premise is false. This technique, known as indirect proof or
proof by contradiction,
has formed the basis of arguments in formal fields such as
logic and mathematics.
See also
*
Appeal to ridicule
*
Argument from fallacy
Argument from fallacy is the formal fallacy of analyzing an argument and inferring that, since it contains a fallacy, its ''conclusion'' must be false. It is also called argument to logic (''argumentum ad logicam''), the fallacy fallacy, the falla ...
*
Contraposition
In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as proof by contraposition. The contrapositive of a statemen ...
*
List of Latin phrases
__NOTOC__
This is a list of Wikipedia articles of Latin phrases and their translation into English.
''To view all phrases on a single, lengthy document, see: List of Latin phrases (full)''
The list also is divided alphabetically into twenty page ...
*
Mathematical proof
A mathematical proof is an Inference, inferential Argument-deduction-proof distinctions, argument for a Proposition, mathematical statement, showing that the stated assumptions logically guarantee the conclusion. The argument may use other previo ...
*
Prasangika
*
Slippery slope
A slippery slope argument (SSA), in logic, critical thinking, political rhetoric, and caselaw, is an argument in which a party asserts that a relatively small first step leads to a chain of related events culminating in some significant (usuall ...
*
Strawman
A straw man (sometimes written as strawman) is a form of argument and an informal fallacy of having the impression of refuting an argument, whereas the real subject of the argument was not addressed or refuted, but instead replaced with a false ...
Sources
* Pasti, Mary. Reductio Ad Absurdum: An Exercise in the Study of Population Change. United States, Cornell University, Jan., 1977.
* Daigle, Robert W.. The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument Prior to Aristotle. N.p., San Jose State University, 1991.
References
External links
*
*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Reductio Ad Absurdum
Latin logical phrases
Latin philosophical phrases
Theorems in propositional logic
Madhyamaka
Arguments
Pyrrhonism