Aronszajn Trees
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, an Aronszajn tree is a
tree In botany, a tree is a perennial plant with an elongated stem, or trunk, usually supporting branches and leaves. In some usages, the definition of a tree may be narrower, e.g., including only woody plants with secondary growth, only ...
of uncountable height with no uncountable branches and no uncountable levels. For example, every Suslin tree is an Aronszajn tree. More generally, for a
cardinal Cardinal or The Cardinal most commonly refers to * Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds **''Cardinalis'', genus of three species in the family Cardinalidae ***Northern cardinal, ''Cardinalis cardinalis'', the common cardinal of ...
''κ'', a ''κ''-Aronszajn tree is a tree of height ''κ'' in which all levels have size less than ''κ'' and all branches have height less than ''κ'' (so Aronszajn trees are the same as \aleph_1-Aronszajn trees). They are named for
Nachman Aronszajn Nachman Aronszajn (26 July 1907 – 5 February 1980) was a Polish American mathematician. Aronszajn's main field of study was mathematical analysis, where he systematically developed the concept of reproducing kernel Hilbert space. He also contrib ...
, who constructed an Aronszajn tree in 1934; his construction was described by . A cardinal ''κ'' for which no ''κ''-Aronszajn trees exist is said to have the tree property (sometimes the condition that ''κ'' is regular and uncountable is included).


Existence of κ-Aronszajn trees

Kőnig's lemma states that \aleph_0-Aronszajn trees do not exist. The existence of Aronszajn trees (=\aleph_1-Aronszajn trees) was proven by
Nachman Aronszajn Nachman Aronszajn (26 July 1907 – 5 February 1980) was a Polish American mathematician. Aronszajn's main field of study was mathematical analysis, where he systematically developed the concept of reproducing kernel Hilbert space. He also contrib ...
, and implies that the analogue of Kőnig's lemma does not hold for uncountable trees. The existence of \aleph_2-Aronszajn trees is undecidable in ZFC: more precisely, the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
implies the existence of an \aleph_2-Aronszajn tree, and Mitchell and Silver showed that it is
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
(relative to the existence of a
weakly compact cardinal In mathematics, a weakly compact cardinal is a certain kind of cardinal number introduced by ; weakly compact cardinals are large cardinals, meaning that their existence cannot be proven from the standard axioms of set theory. (Tarski originally ...
) that no \aleph_2-Aronszajn trees exist. Jensen proved that V = L implies that there is a ''κ''-Aronszajn tree (in fact a ''κ''- Suslin tree) for every infinite successor cardinal ''κ''. showed (using a large cardinal axiom) that it is consistent that no \aleph_n-Aronszajn trees exist for any finite ''n'' other than 1. If ''κ'' is weakly compact then no ''κ''-Aronszajn trees exist. Conversely, if ''κ'' is inaccessible and no ''κ''-Aronszajn trees exist, then ''κ'' is weakly compact.


Special Aronszajn trees

An Aronszajn tree is called special if there is a function ''f'' from the tree to the rationals so that ''f''(''x'') < ''f''(''y'') whenever ''x'' < ''y''. Martin's axiom MA(\aleph_1) implies that all Aronszajn trees are special, a proposition sometimes abbreviated by EATS. The stronger proper forcing axiom implies the stronger statement that for any two Aronszajn trees there is a club set of levels such that the restrictions of the trees to this set of levels are isomorphic, which says that in some sense any two Aronszajn trees are essentially isomorphic . On the other hand, it is consistent that non-special Aronszajn trees exist, and this is also consistent with the generalized continuum hypothesis plus Suslin's hypothesis .


Construction of a special Aronszajn tree

A special Aronszajn tree can be constructed as follows. The elements of the tree are certain well-ordered sets of rational numbers with supremum that is rational or −∞. If ''x'' and ''y'' are two of these sets then we define ''x'' ≤ ''y'' (in the tree order) to mean that ''x'' is an initial segment of the ordered set ''y''. For each countable ordinal α we write ''U''''α'' for the elements of the tree of level α, so that the elements of ''U''''α'' are certain sets of rationals with order type α. The special Aronszajn tree ''T'' is the union of the sets ''U''''α'' for all countable α. We construct the countable levels ''U''''α'' by transfinite induction on α as follows starting with the empty set as ''U''''0'': *If ''α'' + 1 is a successor then ''U''''α''+1 consists of all extensions of a sequence ''x'' in ''U''''α'' by a rational greater than sup ''x''. ''U''''α'' + 1 is countable as it consists of countably many extensions of each of the countably many elements in ''U''''α''. *If ''α'' is a limit then let ''T''''α'' be the tree of all points of level less than ''α''. For each ''x'' in ''T''''α'' and for each rational number ''q'' greater than sup ''x'', choose a level ''α'' branch of ''T''''α'' containing ''x'' with supremum ''q''. Then ''U''''α'' consists of these branches. ''U''''α'' is countable as it consists of countably many branches for each of the countably many elements in ''T''''α''. The function ''f''(''x'') = sup ''x'' is rational or −∞, and has the property that if ''x'' < ''y'' then ''f''(''x'') < ''f''(''y''). Any branch in ''T'' is countable as ''f'' maps branches injectively to −∞ and the rationals. ''T'' is uncountable as it has a non-empty level ''U''''α'' for each countable ordinal ''α'' which make up the first uncountable ordinal. This proves that ''T'' is a special Aronszajn tree. This construction can be used to construct ''κ''-Aronszajn trees whenever ''κ'' is a successor of a regular cardinal and the generalized continuum hypothesis holds, by replacing the rational numbers by a more general ''η'' set.


See also

*
Kurepa tree In set theory, a Kurepa tree is a tree (''T'', <) of height ω1, each of whose levels is
...
* Aronszajn line


References

* * * * * * * *{{citation, mr=0776625 , last=Todorčević, first= S. , chapter=Trees and linearly ordered sets, title= Handbook of set-theoretic topology, pages= 235–293, publisher= North-Holland, place= Amsterdam , year=1984


External links


PlanetMath
Trees (set theory) Independence results