HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, particularly in
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, the aleph numbers are a
sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
of numbers used to represent the
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
(or size) of
infinite set In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
s. They were introduced by the mathematician
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter
aleph Aleph (or alef or alif, transliterated ʾ) is the first Letter (alphabet), letter of the Semitic abjads, including Phoenician alphabet, Phoenician ''ʾālep'' 𐤀, Hebrew alphabet, Hebrew ''ʾālef'' , Aramaic alphabet, Aramaic ''ʾālap'' � ...
(ℵ). The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, denoted by \aleph_0 (read ''aleph-nought'', ''aleph-zero'', or ''aleph-null''); the next larger cardinality of a
well-ordered In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then called a ...
set is \aleph_1, then \aleph_2, then \aleph_3, and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define an infinite
cardinal number In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
\aleph_ for every
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
\alpha, as described below. The concept and notation are due to
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
, who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities. The aleph numbers differ from the
infinity Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is denoted by \infty, called the infinity symbol. From the time of the Ancient Greek mathematics, ancient Greeks, the Infinity (philosophy), philosophic ...
(\infty) commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the
real number line A number line is a graphical representation of a straight line that serves as spatial representation of numbers, usually graduated like a ruler with a particular origin point representing the number zero and evenly spaced marks in either direc ...
(applied to a
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-orie ...
or
sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
that " diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the
extended real number line In mathematics, the extended real number system is obtained from the real number system \R by adding two elements denoted +\infty and -\infty that are respectively greater and lower than every real number. This allows for treating the potential ...
.


Aleph-zero

\aleph_0 (aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an infinite cardinal. The set of all finite ordinals, called \omega or \omega_0 (where \omega is the lowercase Greek letter
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
), also has cardinality \aleph_0. A set has cardinality \aleph_0 if and only if it is
countably infinite In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
, that is, there is a
bijection In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
(one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are * the set of
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
, irrespective of including or excluding zero, * the set of all
integer An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s, * any infinite subset of the integers, such as the set of all
square numbers In mathematics, a square number or perfect square is an integer that is the square of an integer; in other words, it is the product of some integer with itself. For example, 9 is a square number, since it equals and can be written as . The us ...
or the set of all
prime numbers A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime because the only ways ...
, * the set of all
rational number In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example, The set of all ...
s, * the set of all constructible numbers (in the geometric sense), * the set of all
algebraic number In mathematics, an algebraic number is a number that is a root of a function, root of a non-zero polynomial in one variable with integer (or, equivalently, Rational number, rational) coefficients. For example, the golden ratio (1 + \sqrt)/2 is ...
s, * the set of all
computable number In mathematics, computable numbers are the real numbers that can be computed to within any desired precision by a finite, terminating algorithm. They are also known as the recursive numbers, effective numbers, computable reals, or recursive reals ...
s, * the set of all
computable function Computable functions are the basic objects of study in computability theory. Informally, a function is ''computable'' if there is an algorithm that computes the value of the function for every value of its argument. Because of the lack of a precis ...
s, * the set of all binary
string String or strings may refer to: *String (structure), a long flexible structure made from threads twisted together, which is used to tie, bind, or hang other objects Arts, entertainment, and media Films * ''Strings'' (1991 film), a Canadian anim ...
s of finite length, and * the set of all finite
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
s of any given countably infinite set. Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals, including for example \omega, \omega+1, \omega \cdot 2, \omega^2, \omega^\omega, and \varepsilon_0. For example, the sequence (with
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
\omega \cdot 2) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers \ is an ordering of the set (with cardinality \aleph_0) of positive integers. If the
axiom of countable choice The axiom of countable choice or axiom of denumerable choice, denoted ACω, is an axiom of set theory that states that every countable collection of non-empty sets must have a choice function. That is, given a function A with domain \mathbb ( ...
(a weaker version of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
) holds, then \aleph_0 is smaller than any other infinite cardinal, and is therefore the (unique) least infinite ordinal.


Aleph-one

\aleph_1 is the cardinality of the set of all countable
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s. This set is denoted by \omega_1 (or sometimes Ω). The set \omega_1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an
uncountable set In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger t ...
. Therefore, \aleph_1 is the smallest cardinality that is larger than \aleph_0, the smallest infinite cardinality. The definition of \aleph_1 implies (in ZF,
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
''without'' the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between \aleph_0 and \aleph_1. If the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is
totally ordered In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( r ...
, and thus \aleph_1 is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. One can show one of the most useful properties of the set : Any countable subset of \omega_1 has an upper bound in \omega_1 (this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable). This fact is analogous to the situation in \aleph_0: Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and finite unions of finite sets are finite. An example application of the ordinal \omega_1 is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the
σ-algebra In mathematical analysis and in probability theory, a σ-algebra ("sigma algebra") is part of the formalism for defining sets that can be measured. In calculus and analysis, for example, σ-algebras are used to define the concept of sets with a ...
generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g.
Borel hierarchy In mathematical logic, the Borel hierarchy is a stratification of the Borel algebra generated by the open subsets of a Polish space; elements of this algebra are called Borel sets. Each Borel set is assigned a unique countable ordinal number call ...
). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (
vector space In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set (mathematics), set whose elements, often called vector (mathematics and physics), ''vectors'', can be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called sc ...
s,
group A group is a number of persons or things that are located, gathered, or classed together. Groups of people * Cultural group, a group whose members share the same cultural identity * Ethnic group, a group whose members share the same ethnic iden ...
s, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, etc. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
, a set by "throwing in" all possible ''countable'' unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of \omega_1.


Continuum hypothesis

The
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
of the set of
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s (
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
) is 2\aleph_0. It cannot be determined from ZFC (
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
augmented with the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis (CH) is equivalent to the identity :2\aleph_0 = \aleph_1. The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the natural numbers and the real numbers. CH is independent of ZFC: It can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that ZFC is
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
). That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
in 1940, when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC. That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by
Paul Cohen Paul Joseph Cohen (April 2, 1934 – March 23, 2007) was an American mathematician, best known for his proofs that the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice are independent from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, for which he was awarded a F ...
in 1963, when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC – by the (then-novel) method of forcing.


Aleph-omega

Aleph-omega is \aleph_\omega = \sup\ = \sup\ where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted as \omega. That is, the cardinal number \aleph_\omega is the
least upper bound In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
of \sup\. Notably, \aleph_\omega is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ''not'' to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s 2^: For any natural number n \ge 1 , we can consistently assume that 2^ = \aleph_n, and moreover it is possible to assume that 2^ is as least as large as any cardinal number we like. The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of 2^ is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with
cofinality In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf(''A'') of a partially ordered set ''A'' is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of ''A''. Formally, :\operatorname(A) = \inf \ This definition of cofinality relies o ...
\aleph_0. An uncountably infinite cardinal \kappa having cofinality \aleph_0 means that there is a (countable-length) sequence \kappa_0 \le \kappa_1 \le \kappa_2 \le \cdots of cardinals \kappa_i < \kappa whose limit (i.e. its least upper bound) is \kappa (see
Easton's theorem In set theory, Easton's theorem is a result on the possible cardinal numbers of powersets. (extending a result of Robert M. Solovay) showed via forcing that the only constraints on permissible values for 2''κ'' when ''κ'' is a regular cardin ...
). As per the definition above, \aleph_\omega is the limit of a countable-length sequence of smaller cardinals.


Aleph-''α'' for general ''α''

To define \aleph_\alpha for arbitrary ordinal number \alpha, we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number \rho the next larger
well-order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then calle ...
ed cardinal \rho^ (if the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
holds, this is the (unique) next larger cardinal). We can then define the aleph numbers as follows: :\aleph_0 = \omega :\aleph_ = (\aleph_)^ :\aleph_ = \bigcup\ for \lambda an infinite
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
, The \alpha-th infinite
initial ordinal The von Neumann cardinal assignment is a cardinal assignment that uses ordinal numbers. For a well-orderable set ''U'', we define its cardinal number to be the smallest ordinal number equinumerous to ''U'', using the von Neumann definition of an ...
is written \omega_\alpha. Its cardinality is written \aleph_\alpha. Informally, the aleph function \aleph : \text \rightarrow \text is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals. Formally, in ZFC, \aleph is ''not a function'', but a function-like class, as it is not a set (due to the Burali-Forti paradox).


Fixed points of omega

For any ordinal \alpha we have \alpha \le \omega_\alpha. In many cases \omega_\alpha is strictly greater than ''α''. For example, it is true for any successor ordinal: \alpha + 1 \le \omega_ holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence : \omega, \omega_, \omega_, \cdots which is sometimes denoted \omega_. Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function. This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose \kappa = \aleph_ is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If \lambda were a
successor ordinal In set theory, the successor of an ordinal number ''α'' is the smallest ordinal number greater than ''α''. An ordinal number that is a successor is called a successor ordinal. The ordinals 1, 2, and 3 are the first three successor ordinals ...
, then \aleph_ would be a
successor cardinal In set theory, one can define a successor operation on cardinal numbers in a similar way to the successor operation on the ordinal numbers. The cardinal successor coincides with the ordinal successor for finite cardinals, but in the infinite case th ...
and hence not weakly inaccessible. If \lambda were a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
less than \kappa then its
cofinality In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf(''A'') of a partially ordered set ''A'' is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of ''A''. Formally, :\operatorname(A) = \inf \ This definition of cofinality relies o ...
(and thus the cofinality of \aleph_\lambda) would be less than \kappa and so \kappa would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus \lambda \ge \kappa and consequently \lambda = \kappa which makes it a fixed point.


Role of axiom of choice

The cardinality of any infinite
ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its
initial ordinal The von Neumann cardinal assignment is a cardinal assignment that uses ordinal numbers. For a well-orderable set ''U'', we define its cardinal number to be the smallest ordinal number equinumerous to ''U'', using the von Neumann definition of an ...
. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is
equinumerous In mathematics, two sets or classes ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous if there exists a one-to-one correspondence (or bijection) between them, that is, if there exists a function from ''A'' to ''B'' such that for every element ''y'' of ''B'', ...
with an ordinal and is thus
well-order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set is a total ordering on with the property that every non-empty subset of has a least element in this ordering. The set together with the ordering is then calle ...
able. Each
finite set In mathematics, particularly set theory, a finite set is a set that has a finite number of elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example, is a finite set with five elements. Th ...
is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality. Over ZF, the assumption that the cardinality of each
infinite set In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers. When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of
Scott's trick In set theory, Scott's trick is a method for giving a definition of equivalence classes for equivalence relations on a proper class (Jech 2003:65) by referring to levels of the cumulative hierarchy. The method relies on the axiom of regularity bu ...
is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define \text(S) to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank. This has the property that \text(S) = \text(T) if and only if S and T have the same cardinality. (The set \text(S) does not have the same cardinality of S in general, but all its elements do.)


See also

*
Beth number In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the beth numbers are a certain sequence of infinite cardinal numbers (also known as transfinite numbers), conventionally written \beth_0, \beth_1, \beth_2, \beth_3, \dots, where \beth is the Hebrew lett ...
*
Gimel function In axiomatic set theory, the gimel function is the following function mapping cardinal numbers to cardinal numbers: :\gimel\colon\kappa\mapsto\kappa^ where cf denotes the cofinality function; the gimel function is used for studying the continuum ...
*
Regular cardinal In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite ...
*
Infinity Infinity is something which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is denoted by \infty, called the infinity symbol. From the time of the Ancient Greek mathematics, ancient Greeks, the Infinity (philosophy), philosophic ...
*
Transfinite number In mathematics, transfinite numbers or infinite numbers are numbers that are " infinite" in the sense that they are larger than all finite numbers. These include the transfinite cardinals, which are cardinal numbers used to quantify the size of i ...
*
Ordinal number In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...


Notes


References


External links

* * {{DEFAULTSORT:Aleph Number Cardinal numbers Hebrew alphabet Infinity