St. Petersburg Paradox
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The St. Petersburg paradox or St. Petersburg lottery is a
paradox A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictory or a logically u ...
involving the game of flipping a coin where the expected payoff of the theoretical
lottery A lottery is a form of gambling that involves the drawing of numbers at random for a prize. Some governments outlaw lotteries, while others endorse it to the extent of organizing a national or state lottery. It is common to find some degree of ...
game approaches infinity but nevertheless seems to be worth only a very small amount to the participants. The St. Petersburg paradox is a situation where a naive decision criterion that takes only the expected value into account predicts a course of action that presumably no actual person would be willing to take. Several resolutions to the paradox have been proposed. The problem was invented by
Nicolas Bernoulli Nicolaus Bernoulli (also spelled Nicolas or Nikolas; 21 October 1687, Basel – 29 November 1759, Basel) was a Swiss mathematician and was one of the many prominent mathematicians in the Bernoulli family. Biography He was the son of Nicolaus Bern ...
, who stated it in a letter to Pierre Raymond de Montmort on September 9, 1713. as translated and posted at However, the paradox takes its name from its analysis by Nicolas' cousin
Daniel Bernoulli Daniel Bernoulli FRS (; – 27 March 1782) was a Swiss mathematician and physicist and was one of the many prominent mathematicians in the Bernoulli family from Basel. He is particularly remembered for his applications of mathematics to mecha ...
, one-time resident of the eponymous Russian city, who in 1738 published his thoughts about the problem in the ''Commentaries of the Imperial Academy of Science of
Saint Petersburg Saint Petersburg ( rus, links=no, Санкт-Петербург, a=Ru-Sankt Peterburg Leningrad Petrograd Piter.ogg, r=Sankt-Peterburg, p=ˈsankt pʲɪtʲɪrˈburk), formerly known as Petrograd (1914–1924) and later Leningrad (1924–1991), i ...
''.


The St. Petersburg game

A casino offers a game of chance for a single player in which a fair coin is tossed at each stage. The initial stake begins at 2 dollars and is doubled every time heads appears. The first time tails appears, the game ends and the player wins whatever is the current stake. Thus the player wins 2 dollars if tails appears on the first toss, 4 dollars if heads appears on the first toss and tails on the second, 8 dollars if heads appears on the first two tosses and tails on the third, and so on. Mathematically, the player wins 2^ dollars, where k is the number of consecutive head tosses. What would be a fair price to pay the casino for entering the game? To answer this, one needs to consider what would be the expected payout at each stage: with probability , the player wins 2 dollars; with probability the player wins 4 dollars; with probability the player wins 8 dollars, and so on. Assuming the game can continue as long as the coin toss results in heads and, in particular, that the casino has unlimited resources, the
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
is thus Assuming the game can continue indefinitely, this sum grows without bound, and so the expected win is an infinite amount of money.Peterson, Martin (2011). "A New Twist to the St. Petersburg Paradox". ''Journal of Philosophy'' 108 (12):697–699. However each dollar increment in the player's expected winnings require the casino's bankroll to be twice as large.


The paradox

Considering nothing but the expected value of the net change in one's monetary wealth, one should therefore play the game at any price if offered the opportunity. Yet,
Daniel Bernoulli Daniel Bernoulli FRS (; – 27 March 1782) was a Swiss mathematician and physicist and was one of the many prominent mathematicians in the Bernoulli family from Basel. He is particularly remembered for his applications of mathematics to mecha ...
, after describing the game with an initial stake of one
ducat The ducat () coin was used as a trade coin in Europe from the later Middle Ages from the 13th to 19th centuries. Its most familiar version, the gold ducat or sequin containing around of 98.6% fine gold, originated in Venice in 1284 and gained ...
, stated, "Although the standard calculation shows that the value of he player'sexpectation is infinitely great, it has ... to be admitted that any fairly reasonable man would sell his chance, with great pleasure, for twenty ducats." Robert Martin quotes
Ian Hacking Ian MacDougall Hacking (born February 18, 1936) is a Canadian philosopher specializing in the philosophy of science. Throughout his career, he has won numerous awards, such as the Killam Prize for the Humanities and the Balzan Prize, and been ...
as saying, "Few of us would pay even $25 to enter such a game", and he says most commentators would agree. The apparent paradox is the discrepancy between what people seem willing to pay to enter the game and the infinite expected value. The St. Petersburg paradox is a
veridical paradox A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictory or a logically u ...
but not a contradiction, as no false statement is derived. It is often presented as a counterexample against the principle of maximizing the expected value, although it depends on the unrealistic assumption of a casino with infinite bankroll.


Solutions

Several approaches have been proposed for solving the paradox.


Expected utility theory

The classical resolution of the paradox involved the explicit introduction of a
utility function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
, an
expected utility hypothesis The expected utility hypothesis is a popular concept in economics that serves as a reference guide for decisions when the payoff is uncertain. The theory recommends which option rational individuals should choose in a complex situation, based on the ...
, and the presumption of diminishing marginal utility of money. In Daniel Bernoulli's words: A common utility model, suggested by Daniel Bernoulli, is the
logarithmic function In mathematics, the logarithm is the inverse function to exponentiation. That means the logarithm of a number  to the base  is the exponent to which must be raised, to produce . For example, since , the ''logarithm base'' 10 ...
(known as ''log utility''). It is a function of the gambler's total wealth , and the concept of diminishing marginal utility of money is built into it. The expected utility hypothesis posits that a utility function exists that provides a good criterion for real people's behavior; i.e. a function that returns a positive or negative value indicating if the wager is a good gamble. For each possible event, the change in utility will be weighted by the probability of that event occurring. Let be the cost charged to enter the game. The expected incremental utility of the lottery now converges to a finite value: This formula gives an implicit relationship between the gambler's wealth and how much he should be willing to pay (specifically, any that gives a positive change in expected utility). For example, with natural log utility, a
millionaire A millionaire is an individual whose net worth or wealth is equal to or exceeds one million units of currency. Depending on the currency, a certain level of prestige is associated with being a millionaire. In countries that use the short scal ...
($1,000,000) should be willing to pay up to $20.88, a person with $1,000 should pay up to $10.95, a person with $2 should borrow $1.35 and pay up to $3.35. Before Daniel Bernoulli published, in 1728, a mathematician from
Geneva Geneva ( ; french: Genève ) frp, Genèva ; german: link=no, Genf ; it, Ginevra ; rm, Genevra is the second-most populous city in Switzerland (after Zürich) and the most populous city of Romandy, the French-speaking part of Switzerland. Situa ...
,
Gabriel Cramer Gabriel Cramer (; 31 July 1704 – 4 January 1752) was a Genevan mathematician. He was the son of physician Jean Cramer and Anne Mallet Cramer. Biography Cramer showed promise in mathematics from an early age. At 18 he received his doctorat ...
, had already found parts of this idea (also motivated by the St. Petersburg paradox) in stating that He demonstrated in a letter to Nicolas Bernoulli that a square root function describing the diminishing marginal benefit of gains can resolve the problem. However, unlike Daniel Bernoulli, he did not consider the total wealth of a person, but only the gain by the lottery. This solution by Cramer and Bernoulli, however, is not completely satisfying, as the lottery can easily be changed in a way such that the paradox reappears. To this aim, we just need to change the game so that it gives even more rapidly increasing payoffs. For any unbounded utility function, one can find a lottery that allows for a variant of the St. Petersburg paradox, as was first pointed out by Menger. Recently, expected utility theory has been extended to arrive at more behavioral decision models. In some of these new theories, as in
cumulative prospect theory Cumulative prospect theory (CPT) is a model for descriptive decisions under risk and uncertainty which was introduced by Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman in 1992 (Tversky, Kahneman, 1992). It is a further development and variant of prospect theory. ...
, the St. Petersburg paradox again appears in certain cases, even when the utility function is concave, but not if it is bounded.


Probability weighting

Nicolas Bernoulli himself proposed an alternative idea for solving the paradox. He conjectured that people will neglect unlikely events. Since in the St. Petersburg lottery only unlikely events yield the high prizes that lead to an infinite expected value, this could resolve the paradox. The idea of probability weighting resurfaced much later in the work on prospect theory by
Daniel Kahneman Daniel Kahneman (; he, דניאל כהנמן; born March 5, 1934) is an Israeli-American psychologist and economist notable for his work on the psychology of judgment and decision-making, as well as behavioral economics, for which he was award ...
and
Amos Tversky Amos Nathan Tversky ( he, עמוס טברסקי; March 16, 1937 – June 2, 1996) was an Israeli cognitive and mathematical psychologist and a key figure in the discovery of systematic human cognitive bias and handling of risk. Much of his ...
. Paul Weirich similarly wrote that risk aversion could solve the paradox. Weirich went on to write that increasing the prize actually decreases the chance of someone paying to play the game, stating "there is some number of birds in hand worth more than any number of birds in the bush". However, this has been rejected by some theorists because, as they point out, some people enjoy the risk of gambling and because it is illogical to assume that increasing the prize will lead to more risks.
Cumulative prospect theory Cumulative prospect theory (CPT) is a model for descriptive decisions under risk and uncertainty which was introduced by Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman in 1992 (Tversky, Kahneman, 1992). It is a further development and variant of prospect theory. ...
is one popular generalization of
expected utility theory The expected utility hypothesis is a popular concept in economics that serves as a reference guide for decisions when the payoff is uncertain. The theory recommends which option rational individuals should choose in a complex situation, based on the ...
that can predict many behavioral regularities. However, the overweighting of small probability events introduced in cumulative prospect theory may restore the St. Petersburg paradox. Cumulative prospect theory avoids the St. Petersburg paradox only when the power coefficient of the
utility As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosophe ...
function is lower than the power coefficient of the probability weighting function. Intuitively, the utility function must not simply be concave, but it must be concave relative to the probability weighting function to avoid the St. Petersburg paradox. One can argue that the formulas for the prospect theory are obtained in the region of less than $400. This is not applicable for infinitely increasing sums in the St. Petersburg paradox.


Finite St. Petersburg lotteries

The classical St. Petersburg game assumes that the casino or banker has infinite resources. This assumption has long been challenged as unrealistic.Jeffery 1983, p.154. "Our rebuttal of the St. Petersburg paradox consists in the remark that anyone who offers to let the agent play the Saint Petersburg game is a liar for he is pretending to have an indefinitely large bank." Alexis Fontaine des Bertins pointed out in 1754 that the resources of any potential backer of the game are finite. More importantly, the expected value of the game only grows logarithmically with the resources of the casino. As a result, the expected value of the game, even when played against a casino with the largest bankroll realistically conceivable, is quite modest. In 1777,
Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon (; 7 September 1707 – 16 April 1788) was a French naturalist, mathematician, cosmologist, and encyclopédiste. His works influenced the next two generations of naturalists, including two prominent ...
calculated that after 29 rounds of play there would not be enough money in the Kingdom of France to cover the bet. Reprinted in ''Oeuvres Philosophiques de Buffon'', Paris, 1906, cited in Dutka, 1988 If the casino has finite resources, the game must end once those resources are exhausted. Suppose the total resources (or maximum jackpot) of the casino are ''W'' dollars (more generally, ''W'' is measured in units of half the game's initial stake). Then the maximum number of times the casino can play before it no longer can fully cover the next bet is . Assuming the game ends when the casino can no longer cover the bet, the expected value ''E'' of the lottery then becomes: :\begin E &= \sum_^ \frac \cdot 2^k = L\,. \end The following table shows the expected value ''E'' of the game with various potential bankers and their bankroll ''W'': Note: Under game rules which specify that if the player wins more than the casino's bankroll they will be paid all the casino has, the additional expected value is less than it would be if the casino had enough funds to cover one more round, i.e. less than $1. For the player to win he must be allowed to play round . So the additional expected value is . The premise of infinite resources produces a variety of apparent paradoxes in economics. In the martingale betting system, a gambler betting on a tossed coin doubles his bet after every loss so that an eventual win would cover all losses; this system fails with any finite bankroll. The
gambler's ruin The gambler's ruin is a concept in statistics. It is most commonly expressed as follows: A gambler playing a game with negative expected value will eventually go broke, regardless of their betting system. The concept was initially stated: A pers ...
concept shows that a persistent gambler who raises his bet to a fixed fraction of his bankroll when he wins, but does not reduce his bet when he loses, will eventually and inevitably go broke—even if the game has a positive
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
.


Ignore events with small probability

Buffon argued that a theory of rational behavior must correspond to what a rational decision-maker would do in real life, and since reasonable people regularly ignore events that are unlikely enough, a rational decision-maker should also ignore such rare events. As an estimate of the threshold of ignorability, he argued that, since a 56-year-old man ignores the possibility of dying in the next 24 hours, which has a probability of 1/10189 according to the
mortality tables In actuarial science and demography, a life table (also called a mortality table or actuarial table) is a table which shows, for each age, what the probability is that a person of that age will die before their next birthday ("probability of de ...
, events with less than 1/10,000 probability could be ignored. Assuming that, the St Petersburg game has an expected payoff of only \sum_^ 2^k\frac = 13.


Rejection of mathematical expectation

Various authors, including
Jean le Rond d'Alembert Jean-Baptiste le Rond d'Alembert (; ; 16 November 1717 – 29 October 1783) was a French mathematician, mechanician, physicist, philosopher, and music theorist. Until 1759 he was, together with Denis Diderot, a co-editor of the '' Encyclopéd ...
and
John Maynard Keynes John Maynard Keynes, 1st Baron Keynes, ( ; 5 June 1883 – 21 April 1946), was an English economist whose ideas fundamentally changed the theory and practice of macroeconomics and the economic policies of governments. Originally trained in ...
, have rejected maximization of expectation (even of utility) as a proper rule of conduct.Keynes, John Maynard; A Treatise on Probability (1921), Pt IV Ch XXVI §9. Keynes, in particular, insisted that the ''
relative risk The relative risk (RR) or risk ratio is the ratio of the probability of an outcome in an exposed group to the probability of an outcome in an unexposed group. Together with risk difference and odds ratio, relative risk measures the association be ...
'' of an alternative could be sufficiently high to reject it even if its expectation were enormous. Recently, some researchers have suggested to replace the expected value by the
median In statistics and probability theory, the median is the value separating the higher half from the lower half of a data sample, a population, or a probability distribution. For a data set, it may be thought of as "the middle" value. The basic f ...
as the fair value.


Ergodicity

Ergodicity economics rejects the use of mathematical expectation unless it can be justified by dynamic arguments.
Ergodicity In mathematics, ergodicity expresses the idea that a point of a moving system, either a dynamical system or a stochastic process, will eventually visit all parts of the space that the system moves in, in a uniform and random sense. This implies tha ...
is a property which ensures that the
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
of a fluctuating quantity is also its long-time average. This property is believed to hold in equilibrium
statistical mechanics In physics, statistical mechanics is a mathematical framework that applies statistical methods and probability theory to large assemblies of microscopic entities. It does not assume or postulate any natural laws, but explains the macroscopic b ...
, but it generally does not hold for models of personal wealth. According to ergodicity economics, to find the price of St. Petersburg game, one computes the time-average growth rate of wealth which results from playing the lottery at a given price and wealth. The price where the time-average growth rate is zero for realistic dynamics is a realistic value for the maximum a player may be willing to pay. This is different from the growth experienced by the
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
for any dynamic which is not additive. In detail, assuming the player has wealth w and pays c for the game, then the expected growth rate of the player is\bar g(w, c) = \sum_^\infty \frac \ln \fracand the player would be willing to pay up to c(w), where it satisfies \bar g(w, c(w)) = 0. An early resolution containing the essential mathematical arguments assuming multiplicative dynamics was put forward in 1870 by William Allen Whitworth. An explicit link to the ergodicity problem was made by Peters in 2011. These solutions are mathematically similar to using the
Kelly criterion In probability theory, the Kelly criterion (or Kelly strategy or Kelly bet), is a formula that determines the optimal theoretical size for a bet. It is valid when the expected returns are known. The Kelly bet size is found by maximizing the expe ...
or logarithmic utility. Conceptually, however, they are different because they emphasize the interpretation of
expected value In probability theory, the expected value (also called expectation, expectancy, mathematical expectation, mean, average, or first moment) is a generalization of the weighted average. Informally, the expected value is the arithmetic mean of a ...
as an
ensemble average In physics, specifically statistical mechanics, an ensemble (also statistical ensemble) is an idealization consisting of a large number of virtual copies (sometimes infinitely many) of a system, considered all at once, each of which represents ...
and identify as a more relevant criterion the growth of the player's wealth as experienced over time. General dynamics beyond the purely multiplicative case can correspond to non-logarithmic utility functions, as was pointed out by Carr and Cherubini in 2020.


Recent discussions

Although this paradox is three centuries old, new arguments have still been introduced in recent years.


Feller

A solution involving sampling was offered by
William Feller William "Vilim" Feller (July 7, 1906 – January 14, 1970), born Vilibald Srećko Feller, was a Croatian-American mathematician specializing in probability theory. Early life and education Feller was born in Zagreb to Ida Oemichen-Perc, a C ...
. Intuitively Feller's answer is "to perform this game with a large number of people and calculate the expected value from the sample extraction". In this method, when the games of infinite number of times are possible, the expected value will be infinity, and in the case of finite, the expected value will be a much smaller value.


Samuelson

Paul Samuelson Paul Anthony Samuelson (May 15, 1915 – December 13, 2009) was an American economist who was the first American to win the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences. When awarding the prize in 1970, the Swedish Royal Academies stated that he " ...
resolves the paradox by arguing that, even if an entity had infinite resources, the game would never be offered. If the lottery represents an infinite expected gain to the player, then it also represents an infinite expected loss to the host. No one could be observed paying to play the game because it would never be offered. As Samuelson summarized the argument: "Paul will never be willing to give as much as Peter will demand for such a contract; and hence the indicated activity will take place at the equilibrium level of zero intensity."


Variants

Many variants of the St Petersburg game are proposed to counter proposed solutions to the game. For example, the "Pasadena game": let n be the number of coin-flips; if n is odd, the player gains units of \frac; else the player loses \frac units of utility. The expected utility from the game is then \sum_^\infty (-1)^n \frac = \ln 2. However, since the sum is not absolutely convergent, it may be rearranged to sum to any number, including positive or negative infinity. This suggests that the expected utility of the Pasadena game depends on the summation order, but standard decision theory does not provide a principled way to choose a summation order.


See also

*
Ellsberg paradox In decision theory, the Ellsberg paradox (or Ellsberg's paradox) is a paradox in which people's decisions are inconsistent with subjective expected utility theory. Daniel Ellsberg popularized the paradox in his 1961 paper, “Risk, Ambiguity, and ...
*
Exponential growth Exponential growth is a process that increases quantity over time. It occurs when the instantaneous rate of change (that is, the derivative) of a quantity with respect to time is proportional to the quantity itself. Described as a function, a ...
*
Gambler's ruin The gambler's ruin is a concept in statistics. It is most commonly expressed as follows: A gambler playing a game with negative expected value will eventually go broke, regardless of their betting system. The concept was initially stated: A pers ...
*
Kelly criterion In probability theory, the Kelly criterion (or Kelly strategy or Kelly bet), is a formula that determines the optimal theoretical size for a bet. It is valid when the expected returns are known. The Kelly bet size is found by maximizing the expe ...
*
Martingale (betting system) A martingale is a class of betting strategies that originated from and were popular in 18th-century France. The simplest of these strategies was designed for a game in which the gambler wins the stake if a coin comes up heads and loses if it co ...
* Pascal's mugging * Two envelopes problem *
Zeno's paradoxes Zeno's paradoxes are a set of philosophical problems generally thought to have been devised by Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea (c. 490–430 BC) to support Parmenides' doctrine that contrary to the evidence of one's senses, the belief in plural ...


References


Notes


Further reading

* * * * *(Chapter 4) * * * * * * * * *


External links


Online simulation of the St. Petersburg lottery
{{Economic paradoxes Paradoxes in economics Behavioral finance Mathematical economics Probability theory paradoxes Decision-making paradoxes Coin flipping Paradoxes of infinity