Quasi-quotation
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Quasi-quotation or Quine quotation is a linguistic device in
formal languages In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of string (computer science), strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "#Definition, alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbol ...
that facilitates rigorous and terse formulation of general rules about linguistic expressions while properly observing the use–mention distinction. It was introduced by the
philosopher Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
and logician
Willard Van Orman Quine Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century" ...
in his book ''Mathematical Logic'', originally published in 1940. Put simply, quasi-quotation enables one to introduce symbols that ''stand for'' a linguistic expression in a given instance and are ''used as'' that linguistic expression in a different instance. For example, one can use quasi-quotation to illustrate an instance of substitutional quantification, like the following: ::"Snow is white" is true if and only if snow is white. ::Therefore, there is some sequence of symbols that makes the following sentence true when every instance of φ is replaced by that sequence of symbols: "φ" is true if and only if φ. Quasi-quotation is used to indicate (usually in more complex formulas) that the φ and "φ" in this sentence are ''related'' things, that one is the
iteration Iteration is the repetition of a process in order to generate a (possibly unbounded) sequence of outcomes. Each repetition of the process is a single iteration, and the outcome of each iteration is then the starting point of the next iteration. ...
of the other in a metalanguage. Quine introduced quasiquotes because he wished to avoid the use of variables, and work only with closed sentences (expressions not containing any free variables). However, he still needed to be able to talk about sentences with arbitrary predicates in them, and thus, the quasiquotes provided the mechanism to make such statements. Quine had hoped that, by avoiding variables and schemata, he would minimize confusion for the readers, as well as staying closer to the language that mathematicians actually use. Quasi-quotation is sometimes denoted using the symbols ⌜ and ⌝ (called "Quine quotes" or "Quine corners",
Unicode Unicode or ''The Unicode Standard'' or TUS is a character encoding standard maintained by the Unicode Consortium designed to support the use of text in all of the world's writing systems that can be digitized. Version 16.0 defines 154,998 Char ...
U+231C, U+231D), or double square brackets, ⟦ ⟧ ("Oxford brackets", Unicode U+27E6, U+27E7), instead of ordinary quotation marks. Scott, D. and Strachey, C.: 1971, Toward a mathematical semantics for computer languages, Oxford University Computing Laboratory, Programming Research Group.


How it works

Quasi-quotation is particularly useful for stating formation rules for
formal languages In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of string (computer science), strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "#Definition, alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbol ...
. Suppose, for example, that one wants to define the
well-formed formula In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language. The abbreviation wf ...
s (wffs) of a new formal language, ''L'', with only a single logical operation,
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
, via the following recursive definition: # Any lowercase Roman letter (with or without subscripts) is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. # If φ is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', then '~φ' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. # Nothing else is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. Interpreted literally, rule 2 does not express what is apparently intended. For '~φ' (that is, the result of concatenating '~' and 'φ', in that order, from left to right) is not a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', because no
Greek letter The Greek alphabet has been used to write the Greek language since the late 9th or early 8th century BC. It was derived from the earlier Phoenician alphabet, and is the earliest known alphabetic script to systematically write vowels as wel ...
can occur in well-formed formulas (wffs), according to the apparently intended meaning of the rules. In other words, our second rule says "If some sequence of symbols φ (for example, the sequence of 3 symbols φ = '~~''p) is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', then the sequence of 2 symbols '~φ' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''". Rule 2 needs to be changed so that the second occurrence of 'φ' (in quotes) be not taken literally. Quasi-quotation is introduced as shorthand to capture the fact that what the formula expresses isn't precisely quotation, but instead something about the concatenation of symbols. Our replacement for rule 2 using quasi-quotation looks like this: :2'. If φ is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', then ⌜~φ⌝ is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. The quasi-quotation marks '⌜' and '⌝' are interpreted as follows. Where 'φ' denotes a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', '⌜~φ⌝' denotes the result of concatenating '~' and ''the well-formed formula (wff) denoted by'' 'φ' (in that order, from left to right). Thus rule 2' (unlike rule 2) entails, e.g., that if '''p''' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L'', then '~''p''' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. Similarly, we could not define a language with
disjunction In logic, disjunction (also known as logical disjunction, logical or, logical addition, or inclusive disjunction) is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is ...
by adding this rule: :2.5. If φ and ψ are well-formed formulas (wffs) of ''L'', then '(φ v ψ)' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. But instead: :2.5'. If φ and ψ are well-formed formulas (wffs) of ''L'', then ⌜(φ v ψ)⌝ is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''. The quasi-quotation marks here are interpreted just the same. Where 'φ' and 'ψ' denote well-formed formulas (wffs) of ''L'', '⌜(φ v ψ)⌝' denotes the result of concatenating left parenthesis, the well-formed formula (wff) denoted by 'φ', space, 'v', space, the well-formed formula (wff) denoted by 'ψ', and right parenthesis (in that order, from left to right). Just as before, rule 2.5' (unlike rule 2.5) entails, e.g., that if '''p''' and '''q''' are well-formed formulas (wffs) of ''L'', then '(''p'' v ''q'')' is a well-formed formula (wff) of ''L''.


Scope issues

It does not make sense to quantify into quasi-quoted contexts using variables that range over things other than character strings (e.g.
number A number is a mathematical object used to count, measure, and label. The most basic examples are the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, and so forth. Numbers can be represented in language with number words. More universally, individual numbers can ...
s,
people The term "the people" refers to the public or Common people, common mass of people of a polity. As such it is a concept of human rights law, international law as well as constitutional law, particularly used for claims of popular sovereignty. I ...
,
electrons The electron (, or in nuclear reactions) is a subatomic particle with a negative one elementary charge, elementary electric charge. It is a fundamental particle that comprises the ordinary matter that makes up the universe, along with up qua ...
). Suppose, for example, that one wants to express the idea that '''s''(0)' denotes the successor of 0, s''(1)' denotes the successor of 1, etc. One might be tempted to say: * If ''φ'' is a
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
, then ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ denotes the successor of ''φ''. Suppose, for example, ''φ'' = 7. What is ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ in this case? The following tentative interpretations would all be equally absurd: # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(7)', # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(111)' (in the binary system, '111' denotes the integer 7), # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(VII)', # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(seven)', # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(семь)' ('семь' means 'seven' in Russian), # ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(the number of days in one week)'. On the other hand, if ''φ'' = '7', then ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(7)', and if ''φ'' = 'seven', then ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ = 's(seven)'. The expanded version of this statement reads as follows: * If ''φ'' is a natural number, then the result of concatenating '''s''', left parenthesis, ''φ'', and right parenthesis (in that order, from left to right) denotes the successor of ''φ''. This is a category mistake, because a
number A number is a mathematical object used to count, measure, and label. The most basic examples are the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, and so forth. Numbers can be represented in language with number words. More universally, individual numbers can ...
is not the sort of thing that can be concatenated (though a numeral is). The proper way to state the principle is: * If ''φ'' is an Arabic numeral that ''denotes'' a natural number, then ⌜''s''(''φ'')⌝ denotes the successor of the number denoted by ''φ''. It is tempting to characterize quasi-quotation as a device that allows quantification into quoted contexts, but this is incorrect: quantifying into quoted contexts is ''always'' illegitimate. Rather, quasi-quotation is just a convenient shortcut for formulating ordinary quantified expressions—the kind that can be expressed in first-order logic. As long as these considerations are taken into account, it is perfectly harmless to "abuse" the corner quote notation and simply use it whenever something like quotation is necessary but ordinary quotation is clearly not appropriate.


See also

* Self-evaluating forms and quoting in Lisp, where "quasi-quotation" has been adopted for metaprogramming * String interpolation * Truth-value semantics (substitution interpretation) * Template processor


References


Notes


Bibliography

*{{cite book , last=Quine , first=W. V. , title=Mathematical Logic , orig-year=1940 , edition=Revised , year=2003 , publisher=Harvard University Press , location=Cambridge, MA , isbn=0-674-55451-5


External links


Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on quotation
Formal languages