Quantum nonlocality
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
theoretical physics Theoretical physics is a branch of physics that employs mathematical models and abstractions of physical objects and systems to rationalize, explain and predict natural phenomena. This is in contrast to experimental physics, which uses experim ...
, quantum nonlocality refers to the phenomenon by which the
measurement Measurement is the quantification of attributes of an object or event, which can be used to compare with other objects or events. In other words, measurement is a process of determining how large or small a physical quantity is as compared ...
statistics of a multipartite quantum system do not admit an interpretation in terms of a local realistic theory. Quantum nonlocality has been experimentally verified under different physical assumptions. Any physical theory that aims at superseding or replacing quantum theory should account for such experiments and therefore cannot fulfill local realism; quantum nonlocality is a property of the universe that is independent of our description of nature. Quantum nonlocality does not allow for
faster-than-light communication Superluminal communication is a hypothetical process in which information is sent at faster-than-light (FTL) speeds. The current scientific consensus is that faster-than-light communication is not possible, and to date it has not been achieved i ...
, and hence is compatible with
special relativity In physics, the special theory of relativity, or special relativity for short, is a scientific theory regarding the relationship between space and time. In Albert Einstein's original treatment, the theory is based on two postulates: # The law ...
and its universal speed limit of objects. Thus, quantum theory is local in the strict sense defined by special relativity and, as such, the term "quantum nonlocality" is sometimes considered a misnomer. Still, it prompts many of the foundational discussions concerning quantum theory.


History


Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen

In 1935,
Einstein Albert Einstein ( ; ; 14 March 1879 – 18 April 1955) was a German-born Theoretical physics, theoretical physicist, widely acknowledged to be one of the greatest and most influential physicists of all time. Einstein is best known for d ...
, Podolsky and Rosen published a
thought experiment A thought experiment is a hypothetical situation in which a hypothesis, theory, or principle is laid out for the purpose of thinking through its consequences. History The ancient Greek ''deiknymi'' (), or thought experiment, "was the most anc ...
with which they hoped to expose the incompleteness of the
Copenhagen interpretation The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics, principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. It is one of the oldest of numerous proposed interpretations of quantum mechanics, as feat ...
of quantum mechanics in relation to the violation of local causality at the microscopic scale that it described. Afterwards, Einstein presented a variant of these ideas in a letter to
Erwin Schrödinger Erwin Rudolf Josef Alexander Schrödinger (, ; ; 12 August 1887 – 4 January 1961), sometimes written as or , was a Nobel Prize-winning Austrian physicist with Irish citizenship who developed a number of fundamental results in quantum theo ...
, which is the version that is presented here. The state and notation used here are more modern, and akin to
David Bohm David Joseph Bohm (; 20 December 1917 – 27 October 1992) was an American-Brazilian-British scientist who has been described as one of the most significant theoretical physicists of the 20th centuryPeat 1997, pp. 316-317 and who contributed ...
's take on EPR. The quantum state of the two particles prior to measurement can be written as :\left, \psi_\right\rang =\frac \bigg(\left, 0\right\rang_A \left, 1\right\rang_B - \left, 1\right\rang_A \left, 0\right\rang_B \bigg) =\frac \bigg(\left, +\right\rang_A \left, -\right\rang_B - \left, -\right\rang_A \left, +\right\rang_B \bigg) where \left, \pm\right\rangle=\frac\left(\left, 0\right\rangle\pm\left, 1\right\rangle\right). Here, subscripts “A” and “B” distinguish the two particles, though it is more convenient and usual to refer to these particles as being in the possession of two experimentalists called
Alice and Bob Alice and Bob are fictional characters commonly used as placeholders in discussions about cryptographic systems and protocols, and in other science and engineering literature where there are several participants in a thought experiment. The Al ...
. The rules of quantum theory give predictions for the outcomes of measurements performed by the experimentalists. Alice, for example, will measure her particle to be spin-up in an average of fifty percent of measurements. However, according to the Copenhagen interpretation, Alice's measurement causes the state of the two particles to
collapse Collapse or its variants may refer to: Concepts * Collapse (structural) * Collapse (topology), a mathematical concept * Collapsing manifold * Collapse, the action of collapsing or telescoping objects * Collapsing user interface elements ** ...
, so that if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the z-direction, that is with respect to the basis \ , then Bob's system will be left in one of the states \ . Likewise, if Alice performs a measurement of spin in the x-direction, that is, with respect to the basis \ , then Bob's system will be left in one of the states \ . Schrödinger referred to this phenomenon as "
steering Steering is a system of components, linkages, and other parts that allows a driver to control the direction of the vehicle. Introduction The most conventional steering arrangement allows a driver to turn the front wheels of a vehicle using ...
". This steering occurs in such a way that no signal can be sent by performing such a state update; quantum nonlocality cannot be used to send messages instantaneously and is therefore not in direct conflict with causality concerns in
special relativity In physics, the special theory of relativity, or special relativity for short, is a scientific theory regarding the relationship between space and time. In Albert Einstein's original treatment, the theory is based on two postulates: # The law ...
. In the Copenhagen view of this experiment, Alice's measurement—and particularly her measurement choice—has a direct effect on Bob's state. However, under the assumption of locality, actions on Alice's system do not affect the "true", or "ontic" state of Bob's system. We see that the ontic state of Bob's system must be compatible with one of the quantum states \left, \uparrow\right\rang_B or \left, \downarrow\right\rang_B , since Alice can make a measurement that concludes with one of those states being the quantum description of his system. At the same time, it must also be compatible with one of the quantum states \left, \leftarrow\right\rang_B or \left, \rightarrow\right\rang_B for the same reason. Therefore, the ontic state of Bob's system must be compatible with at least two quantum states; the quantum state is therefore not a complete descriptor of his system. Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen saw this as evidence of the incompleteness of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory, since the wavefunction is explicitly not a complete description of a quantum system under this assumption of locality. Their paper concludes: Although various authors (most notably
Niels Bohr Niels Henrik David Bohr (; 7 October 1885 – 18 November 1962) was a Danish physicist who made foundational contributions to understanding atomic structure and quantum theory, for which he received the Nobel Prize in Physics in 1922 ...
) criticised the ambiguous terminology of the EPR paper, the thought experiment nevertheless generated a great deal of interest. Their notion of a "complete description" was later formalised by the suggestion of hidden variables that determine the statistics of measurement results, but to which an observer does not have access.von Neumann, J. (1932/1955). In ''Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik'', Springer, Berlin, translated into English by Beyer, R.T., Princeton University Press, Princeton, cited by Baggott, J. (2004) ''Beyond Measure: Modern physics, philosophy, and the meaning of quantum theory'', Oxford University Press, Oxford, , pages 144–145. Bohmian mechanics provides such a completion of quantum mechanics, with the introduction of hidden variables; however the theory is explicitly nonlocal. The interpretation therefore does not give an answer to Einstein's question, which was whether or not a complete description of quantum mechanics could be given in terms of local hidden variables in keeping with the "Principle of Local Action".


Bell inequality

In 1964 John Bell answered Einstein's question by showing that such local hidden variables can never reproduce the full range of statistical outcomes predicted by quantum theory. Bell showed that a local hidden variable hypothesis leads to restrictions on the strength of correlations of measurement results. If the Bell inequalities are violated experimentally as predicted by quantum mechanics, then reality cannot be described by local hidden variables and the mystery of quantum nonlocal causation remains. According to Bell: Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt (CHSH) reformulated these inequalities in a manner that was more conducive to experimental testing (see
CHSH inequality In physics, the CHSH inequality can be used in the proof of Bell's theorem, which states that certain consequences of entanglement in quantum mechanics can not be reproduced by local hidden-variable theories. Experimental verification of the i ...
). In the scenario proposed by Bell (a Bell scenario), two experimentalists, Alice and Bob, conduct experiments in separate labs. At each run, Alice (Bob) conducts an experiment x (y) in her (his) lab, obtaining outcome a (b) . If Alice and Bob repeat their experiments several times, then they can estimate the probabilities P(a,b, x,y) , namely, the probability that Alice and Bob respectively observe the results a, b when they respectively conduct the experiments x,y. In the following, each such set of probabilities \ will be denoted by just P(a,b, x,y) . In the quantum nonlocality slang, P(a,b, x,y) is termed a box. Bell formalized the idea of a hidden variable by introducing the parameter \lambda to locally characterize measurement results on each system: "It is a matter of indifference ... whether λ denotes a single variable or a set ... and whether the variables are discrete or continuous". However, it is equivalent (and more intuitive) to think of \lambda as a local "strategy" or "message" that occurs with some probability \rho(\lambda) when Alice and Bob reboot their experimental setup. EPR's criteria of local separability then stipulates that each local strategy defines the distributions of independent outcomes if Alice conducts experiment x and Bob conducts experiment P(a,b, x,y,\lambda_A,\lambda_B)=P_A(a, x,\lambda_A) P_B(b, y,\lambda_B) Here P_A(a, x, \lambda_A) (P_B(b, y, \lambda_B)) denotes the probability that Alice (Bob) obtains the result a (b) when she (he) conducts experiment x (y) and the local variable describing her (his) experiment has value \lambda_A (\lambda_B). Suppose that \lambda_A,\lambda_B can take values from some set \Lambda. If each pair of values \lambda_A,\lambda_B\in\Lambda has an associated probability \rho(\lambda_A,\lambda_B) of being selected (shared randomness is allowed, i.e., \lambda_A,\lambda_B can be correlated), then one can average over this distribution to obtain a formula for the joint probability of each measurement result: P(a,b, x,y) =\sum_\rho(\lambda_A,\lambda_B)P_A(a, x,\lambda_A) P_B(b, y,\lambda_B) A box admitting such a decomposition is called a Bell local or a classical box. Fixing the number of possible values which a,b,x,y can each take, one can represent each box P(a,b, x,y) as a finite vector with entries \left(P(a,b, x,y)\right)_. In that representation, the set of all classical boxes forms a
convex polytope A convex polytope is a special case of a polytope, having the additional property that it is also a convex set contained in the n-dimensional Euclidean space \mathbb^n. Most texts. use the term "polytope" for a bounded convex polytope, and the w ...
. In the Bell scenario studied by CHSH, where a,b,x,y can take values within , any Bell local box P(a,b, x,y) must satisfy the CHSH inequality: S_\equiv E(0,0)+E(1,0)+E(0,1)-E(1,1)\leq 2, where E(x,y)\equiv\sum_(-1)^P(a,b, x,y). The above considerations apply to model a quantum experiment. Consider two parties conducting local polarization measurements on a bipartite photonic state. The measurement result for the polarization of a photon can take one of two values (informally, whether the photon is polarized in that direction, or in the orthogonal direction). If each party is allowed to choose between just two different polarization directions, the experiment fits within the CHSH scenario. As noted by CHSH, there exist a quantum state and polarization directions which generate a box P(a,b, x,y) with S_ equal to 2\sqrt\approx 2.828. This demonstrates an explicit way in which a theory with ontological states that are local, with local measurements and only local actions cannot match the probabilistic predictions of quantum theory, disproving Einstein's hypothesis. Experimentalists such as
Alain Aspect Alain Aspect (; born 15 June 1947) is a French physicist noted for his experimental work on quantum entanglement. Aspect was awarded the 2022 Nobel Prize in Physics, jointly with John Clauser and Anton Zeilinger, "for experiments with entangl ...
have verified the quantum violation of the CHSH inequality as well as other formulations of Bell's inequality, to invalidate the local hidden variables hypothesis and confirm that reality is indeed nonlocal in the EPR sense.


Possibilistic nonlocality

The demonstration of nonlocality due to Bell is probabilistic in the sense that it shows that the precise probabilities predicted by quantum mechanics for some entangled scenarios cannot be met by a local theory. (For short, here and henceforth "local theory" means "local hidden variables theory".) However, quantum mechanics permits an even stronger violation of local theories: a possibilistic one, in which local theories cannot even agree with quantum mechanics on which events are possible or impossible in an entangled scenario. The first proof of this kind was due to
Daniel Greenberger Daniel M. Greenberger (born 1932) is an American quantum physicist. He has been professor of physics at the City College of New York since 1964. He is also a fellow of the American Physical Society and—alongside Anton Zeilinger—founded the APS ...
, Michael Horne, and
Anton Zeilinger Anton Zeilinger (; born 20 May 1945) is an Austrian quantum physicist and Nobel laureate in physics of 2022. Zeilinger is professor of physics emeritus at the University of Vienna and senior scientist at the Institute for Quantum Optics and Qu ...
in 1993 The state involved is often called the
GHZ state The hertz (symbol: Hz) is the unit of frequency in the International System of Units (SI), equivalent to one event (or cycle) per second. The hertz is an SI derived unit whose expression in terms of SI base units is s−1, meaning that one he ...
. In 1993,
Lucien Hardy Lucien Hardy (born 1966) is a theoretical physicist, known for his work on the foundation of quantum physics including Hardy's paradox, a thought experiment he devised in 1992, and his widely cited 2001 axiomatic reconstruction of quantum theory th ...
demonstrated a logical proof of quantum nonlocality that, like the GHZ proof is a possibilistic proof. It starts with the observation that the state \left, \psi\right\rangle defined below can be written in a few suggestive ways: :\left, \psi\right\rangle=\frac\left(\left, 00\right\rangle+\left, 01\right\rangle+\left, 10\right\rangle\right)= \frac\sqrt\left(\sqrt\left, +0\right\rangle+\frac\left(\left, +1\right\rangle+\left, -1\right\rangle\right)\right)= \frac\sqrt\left(\sqrt\left, 0+\right\rangle+\frac\left(\left, 1+\right\rangle+\left, 1-\right\rangle\right)\right) where, as above, , \pm\rangle=\tfrac(\left, 0\right\rangle\pm\left, 1\right\rangle). The experiment consists of this entangled state being shared between two experimenters, each of whom has the ability to measure either with respect to the basis \ or \. We see that if they each measure with respect to \, then they never see the outcome \left, 11\right\rangle. If one measures with respect to \ and the other \, they never see the outcomes \left, -0\right\rangle, \left, 0-\right\rangle. However, sometimes they see the outcome \left, --\right\rangle when measuring with respect to \, since \langle--, \psi\rangle = -\tfrac1 \ne 0. This leads to the paradox: having the outcome , --\rangle we conclude that if one of the experimenters had measured with respect to the \ basis instead, the outcome must have been , 1\rangle or , 1-\rangle, since , 0\rangle and , 0-\rangle are impossible. But then, if they had both measured with respect to the \ basis, by locality the result must have been \left, 11\right\rangle, which is also impossible.


Nonlocal hidden variable models with a finite propagation speed

The work of Bancal et al. generalizes Bell's result by proving that correlations achievable in quantum theory are also incompatible with a large class of superluminal hidden variable models. In this framework, faster-than-light signaling is precluded. However, the choice of settings of one party can influence hidden variables at another party's distant location, if there is enough time for a superluminal influence (of finite, but otherwise unknown speed) to propagate from one point to the other. In this scenario, any bipartite experiment revealing Bell nonlocality can just provide lower bounds on the hidden influence's propagation speed. Quantum experiments with three or more parties can, nonetheless, disprove all such non-local hidden variable models.


Analogs of Bell’s theorem in more complicated causal structures

The random variables measured in a general experiment can depend on each other in complicated ways. In the field of causal inference, such dependencies are represented via
Bayesian network A Bayesian network (also known as a Bayes network, Bayes net, belief network, or decision network) is a probabilistic graphical model that represents a set of variables and their conditional dependencies via a directed acyclic graph (DAG). Ba ...
s: directed acyclic graphs where each node represents a variable and an edge from a variable to another signifies that the former influences the latter and not otherwise, see the figure. In a standard bipartite Bell experiment, Alice's (Bob's) setting x (y), together with her (his) local variable \lambda_A (\lambda_B), influence her (his) local outcome a (b). Bell's theorem can thus be interpreted as a separation between the quantum and classical predictions in a type of causal structures with just one hidden node (\lambda_A,\lambda_B). Similar separations have been established in other types of causal structures. The characterization of the boundaries for classical correlations in such extended Bell scenarios is challenging, but there exist complete practical computational methods to achieve it.


Entanglement and nonlocality

Quantum nonlocality is sometimes understood as being equivalent to entanglement. However, this is not the case. Quantum entanglement can be defined only within the formalism of quantum mechanics, i.e., it is a model-dependent property. In contrast, nonlocality refers to the impossibility of a description of observed statistics in terms of a local hidden variable model, so it is independent of the physical model used to describe the experiment. It is true that for any pure entangled state there exists a choice of measurements that produce Bell nonlocal correlations, but the situation is more complex for mixed states. While any Bell nonlocal state must be entangled, there exist (mixed) entangled states which do not produce Bell nonlocal correlations (although, operating on several copies of some of such states, or carrying out local post-selections, it is possible to witness nonlocal effects). Moreover, while there are
catalysts Catalysis () is the process of increasing the rate of a chemical reaction by adding a substance known as a catalyst (). Catalysts are not consumed in the reaction and remain unchanged after it. If the reaction is rapid and the catalyst recyc ...
for entanglement, there are none for nonlocality. Finally, reasonably simple examples of Bell inequalities have been found for which the quantum state giving the largest violation is never a maximally entangled state, showing that entanglement is, in some sense, not even proportional to nonlocality.


Quantum correlations

As shown, the statistics achievable by two or more parties conducting experiments in a classical system are constrained in a non-trivial way. Analogously, the statistics achievable by separate observers in a quantum theory also happen to be restricted. The first derivation of a non-trivial statistical limit on the set of quantum correlations, due to B. Tsirelson, is known as
Tsirelson's bound A Tsirelson bound is an upper limit to quantum mechanical correlations between distant events. Given that quantum mechanics violates Bell inequalities (i.e., it cannot be described by a local hidden-variable theory), a natural question to ask is ...
. Consider the CHSH Bell scenario detailed before, but this time assume that, in their experiments, Alice and Bob are preparing and measuring quantum systems. In that case, the CHSH parameter can be shown to be bounded by :-2\sqrt\leq \mathrm\leq 2\sqrt.


The sets of quantum correlations and Tsirelson’s problem

Mathematically, a box P(a,b, x,y) admits a quantum realization if and only if there exists a pair of Hilbert spaces H_A, H_B, a normalized vector \left, \psi\right\rangle\in H_A\otimes H_B and projection operators E^x_a:H_A\to H_A, F^y_b:H_B\to H_B such that # For all x,y, the sets \_a,\_b represent complete measurements. Namely, \sum_aE^x_a=_A, \sum_bF^y_b=_B. # P(a,b, x,y) =\left\langle\psi\E^x_a\otimes F^y_b\left, \psi\right\rangle, for all a,b,x,y. In the following, the set of such boxes will be called Q. Contrary to the classical set of correlations, when viewed in probability space, Q is not a polytope. On the contrary, it contains both straight and curved boundaries. In addition, Q is not closed: this means that there exist boxes P(a,b, x,y) which can be arbitrarily well approximated by quantum systems but are themselves not quantum. In the above definition, the space-like separation of the two parties conducting the Bell experiment was modeled by imposing that their associated operator algebras act on different factors H_A, H_B of the overall Hilbert space H=H_A\otimes H_B describing the experiment. Alternatively, one could model space-like separation by imposing that these two algebras commute. This leads to a different definition: P(a,b, x,y) admits a field quantum realization if and only if there exists a Hilbert space H, a normalized vector \left, \psi\right\rangle\in H and projection operators E^x_a:H\to H, F^y_b:H\to H such that # For all x,y, the sets \_a,\_b represent complete measurements. Namely, \sum_aE^x_a=, \sum_bF^y_b= . # P(a,b, x,y) =\left\langle\psi\E^x_a F^y_b\left, \psi\right\rangle, for all a,b,x,y. # ^x_a, F^y_b0, for all a,b,x,y. Call Q_c the set of all such correlations P(a,b, x,y). How does this new set relate to the more conventional Q defined above? It can be proven that Q_c is closed. Moreover, \bar \subseteq Q_c, where \bar denotes the closure of Q. Tsirelson's problem consists in deciding whether the inclusion relation \bar \subseteq Q_c is strict, i.e., whether or not \bar = Q_c. This problem only appears in infinite dimensions: when the Hilbert space H in the definition of Q_c is constrained to be finite-dimensional, the closure of the corresponding set equals \bar. In January 2020, Ji, Natarajan, Vidick, Wright, and Yuen claimed a result in
quantum complexity theory Quantum complexity theory is the subfield of computational complexity theory that deals with complexity classes defined using quantum computers, a computational model based on quantum mechanics. It studies the hardness of computational proble ...
that would imply that \bar \neq Q_c , thus solving Tsirelson's problem. Tsirelson's problem can be shown equivalent to
Connes embedding problem Connes' embedding problem, formulated by Alain Connes in the 1970s, is a major problem in von Neumann algebra theory. During that time, the problem was reformulated in several different areas of mathematics. Dan Voiculescu developing his free entro ...
, a famous conjecture in the theory of operator algebras.


Characterization of quantum correlations

Since the dimensions of H_A and H_B are, in principle, unbounded, determining whether a given box P(a,b, x,y) admits a quantum realization is a complicated problem. In fact, the dual problem of establishing whether a quantum box can have a perfect score at a non-local game is known to be undecidable. Moreover, the problem of deciding whether P(a,b, x,y) can be approximated by a quantum system with precision 1/\operatorname(, X, , Y, ) is NP-hard. Characterizing quantum boxes is equivalent to characterizing the cone of completely positive semidefinite matrices under a set of linear constraints. For small fixed dimensions d_A, d_B, one can explore, using variational methods, whether P(a,b, x,y) can be realized in a bipartite quantum system H_A\otimes H_B, with \dim(H_A)=d_A, \dim(H_B)=d_B. That method, however, can just be used to prove the realizability of P(a,b, x,y), and not its unrealizability with quantum systems. To prove unrealizability, the most known method is the Navascués–Pironio–Acín (NPA) hierarchy. This is an infinite decreasing sequence of sets of correlations Q^1\supset Q^2\supset Q^3\supset... with the properties: # If P(a,b, x,y)\in Q_c, then P(a,b, x,y)\in Q^k for all k. # If P(a,b, x,y)\not\in Q_c, then there exists k such that P(a,b, x,y)\not\in Q^k. # For any k, deciding whether P(a,b, x,y)\in Q^k can be cast as a semidefinite program. The NPA hierarchy thus provides a computational characterization, not of Q, but of Q_c. If Tsirelson's problem is solved in the affirmative, namely, \bar=Q_c, then the above two methods would provide a practical characterization of \bar. If, on the contrary, \bar\not=Q_c, then a new method to detect the non-realizability of the correlations in Q_c- \bar is needed.


The physics of supra-quantum correlations

The works listed above describe what the quantum set of correlations looks like, but they do not explain why. Are quantum correlations unavoidable, even in post-quantum physical theories, or on the contrary, could there exist correlations outside \bar which nonetheless do not lead to any unphysical operational behavior? In their seminal 1994 paper, Popescu and Rohrlich explore whether quantum correlations can be explained by appealing to relativistic causality alone. Namely, whether any hypothetical box P(a,b, x,y)\not\in\bar would allow building a device capable of transmitting information faster than the speed of light. At the level of correlations between two parties, Einstein's causality translates in the requirement that Alice's measurement choice should not affect Bob's statistics, and vice versa. Otherwise, Alice (Bob) could signal Bob (Alice) instantaneously by choosing her (his) measurement setting x (y) appropriately. Mathematically, Popescu and Rohrlich's no-signalling conditions are: : \sum_aP(a,b, x,y)= \sum_aP(a,b, x^\prime,y)=:P_B(b, y), :\sum_bP(a,b, x,y)= \sum_bP(a,b, x,y^\prime)=:P_A(a, x). Like the set of classical boxes, when represented in probability space, the set of no-signalling boxes forms a
polytope In elementary geometry, a polytope is a geometric object with flat sides ('' faces''). Polytopes are the generalization of three-dimensional polyhedra to any number of dimensions. Polytopes may exist in any general number of dimensions as an ...
. Popescu and Rohrlich identified a box P(a,b, x,y) that, while complying with the no-signalling conditions, violates Tsirelson's bound, and is thus unrealizable in quantum physics. Dubbed the PR-box, it can be written as: P(a,b, x,y)=\frac\delta_. Here a,b,x,y take values in , and a\oplus b denotes the sum modulo two. It can be verified that the CHSH value of this box is 4 (as opposed to the Tsirelson bound of 2\sqrt\approx 2.828). This box had been identified earlier, by Rastall and Khalfin and Tsirelson. In view of this mismatch, Popescu and Rohrlich pose the problem of identifying a physical principle, stronger than the no-signalling conditions, that allows deriving the set of quantum correlations. Several proposals followed: # Non-trivial communication complexity (NTCC). This principle stipulates that nonlocal correlations should not be so strong as to allow two parties to solve all 1-way communication problems with some probability p>1/2 using just one bit of communication. It can be proven that any box violating Tsirelson's bound by more than 2\sqrt\left(\frac-1\right)\approx 0.4377 is incompatible with NTCC. # No Advantage for Nonlocal Computation (NANLC). The following scenario is considered: given a function f_^n\to 1, two parties are distributed the strings of n bits x,y and asked to output the bits a,b so that a\oplus b is a good guess for f(x\oplus y). The principle of NANLC states that non-local boxes should not give the two parties any advantage to play this game. It is proven that any box violating Tsirelson's bound would provide such an advantage. #
Information Causality Information causality is a physical principle suggested in 2009. Information Causality states that information gain that a receiver (Bob) can reach about data, previously unknown to him, from a sender (Alice), by using all his local resources and n ...
(IC). The starting point is a bipartite communication scenario where one of the parts (Alice) is handed a random string x of n bits. The second part, Bob, receives a random number k\in\. Their goal is to transmit Bob the bit x_k, for which purpose Alice is allowed to transmit Bob s bits. The principle of IC states that the sum over k of the mutual information between Alice's bit and Bob's guess cannot exceed the number s of bits transmitted by Alice. It is shown that any box violating Tsirelson's bound would allow two parties to violate IC. # Macroscopic Locality (ML). In the considered setup, two separate parties conduct extensive low-resolution measurements over a large number of independently prepared pairs of correlated particles. ML states that any such “macroscopic” experiment must admit a local hidden variable model. It is proven that any microscopic experiment capable of violating Tsirelson's bound would also violate standard Bell nonlocality when brought to the macroscopic scale. Besides Tsirelson's bound, the principle of ML fully recovers the set of all two-point quantum correlators. # Local Orthogonality (LO). This principle applies to multipartite Bell scenarios, where n parties respectively conduct experiments x_1,...,x_n in their local labs. They respectively obtain the outcomes a_1,...,a_n. The pair of vectors (\bar, \bar) is called an event. Two events (\bar, \bar), (\bar^\prime, \bar^\prime) are said to be locally orthogonal if there exists k such that x_k=x_k^\prime and a_k\not=a_k^\prime . The principle of LO states that, for any multipartite box, the sum of the probabilities of any set of pair-wise locally orthogonal events cannot exceed 1. It is proven that any bipartite box violating Tsirelson's bound by an amount of 0.052 violates LO. All these principles can be experimentally falsified under the assumption that we can decide if two or more events are space-like separated. This sets this research program aside from the axiomatic reconstruction of quantum mechanics via Generalized Probabilistic Theories. The works above rely on the implicit assumption that any physical set of correlations must be closed under wirings. This means that any effective box built by combining the inputs and outputs of a number of boxes within the considered set must also belong to the set. Closure under wirings does not seem to enforce any limit on the maximum value of CHSH. However, it is not a void principle: on the contrary, in it is shown that many simple, intuitive families of sets of correlations in probability space happen to violate it. Originally, it was unknown whether any of these principles (or a subset thereof) was strong enough to derive all the constraints defining \bar. This state of affairs continued for some years until the construction of the almost quantum set \tilde. \tilde is a set of correlations that is closed under wirings and can be characterized via semidefinite programming. It contains all correlations in Q_c\supset \bar, but also some non-quantum boxes P(a,b, x,y)\not\in Q_c. Remarkably, all boxes within the almost quantum set are shown to be compatible with the principles of NTCC, NANLC, ML and LO. There is also numerical evidence that almost-quantum boxes also comply with IC. It seems, therefore, that, even when the above principles are taken together, they do not suffice to single out the quantum set in the simplest Bell scenario of two parties, two inputs and two outputs.


Device independent protocols

Nonlocality can be exploited to conduct quantum information tasks which do not rely on the knowledge of the inner workings of the prepare-and-measurement apparatuses involved in the experiment. The security or reliability of any such protocol just depends on the strength of the experimentally measured correlations P(a,b, x,y). These protocols are termed device-independent.


Device-independent quantum key distribution

The first device-independent protocol proposed was device-independent quantum key distribution (QKD). In this primitive, two distant parties, Alice and Bob, are distributed an entangled quantum state, that they probe, thus obtaining the statistics P(a,b, x,y). Based on how non-local the box P(a,b, x,y) happens to be, Alice and Bob estimate how much knowledge an external quantum adversary Eve (the eavesdropper) could possess on the value of Alice and Bob's outputs. This estimation allows them to devise a reconciliation protocol at the end of which Alice and Bob share a perfectly correlated one-time pad of which Eve has no information whatsoever. The one-time pad can then be used to transmit a secret message through a public channel. Although the first security analyses on device-independent QKD relied on Eve carrying out a specific family of attacks, all such protocols have been recently proven unconditionally secure.


Device-independent randomness certification, expansion and amplification

Nonlocality can be used to certify that the outcomes of one of the parties in a Bell experiment are partially unknown to an external adversary. By feeding a partially random seed to several non-local boxes, and, after processing the outputs, one can end up with a longer (potentially unbounded) string of comparable randomness or with a shorter but more random string. This last primitive can be proven impossible in a classical setting.


Self-testing

Sometimes, the box P(a,b, x,y) shared by Alice and Bob is such that it only admits a unique quantum realization. This means that there exist measurement operators E^x_a, F^y_b and a quantum state \left, \psi\right\rangle giving rise to P(a,b, x,y) such that any other physical realization \tilde^x_a, \tilde^y_b ,\left, \tilde\right\rangle of P(a,b, x,y) is connected to E^x_a, F^y_b ,\left, \psi\right\rangle via local unitary transformations. This phenomenon, that can be interpreted as an instance of device-independent quantum tomography, was first pointed out by Tsirelson and named self-testing by Mayers and Yao. Self-testing is known to be robust against systematic noise, i.e., if the experimentally measured statistics are close enough to P(a,b, x,y), one can still determine the underlying state and measurement operators up to error bars.


Dimension witnesses

The degree of non-locality of a quantum box P(a,b, x,y) can also provide lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension of the local systems accessible to Alice and Bob. This problem is equivalent to deciding the existence of a matrix with low completely positive semidefinite rank. Finding lower bounds on the Hilbert space dimension based on statistics happens to be a hard task, and current general methods only provide very low estimates. However, a Bell scenario with five inputs and three outputs suffices to provide arbitrarily high lower bounds on the underlying Hilbert space dimension. Quantum communication protocols which assume a knowledge of the local dimension of Alice and Bob's systems, but otherwise do not make claims on the mathematical description of the preparation and measuring devices involved are termed semi-device independent protocols. Currently, there exist semi-device independent protocols for quantum key distribution and randomness expansion.


See also

*
Action at a distance In physics, action at a distance is the concept that an object can be affected without being physically touched (as in mechanical contact) by another object. That is, it is the non-local interaction of objects that are separated in space. Non- ...
* Popper's experiment *
Quantum pseudo-telepathy Quantum pseudo-telepathy is the fact that in certain Bayesian games with asymmetric information, players who have access to a shared physical system in an entangled quantum state, and who are able to execute strategies that are contingent upon m ...
*
Quantum contextuality Quantum contextuality is a feature of the phenomenology of quantum mechanics whereby measurements of quantum observables cannot simply be thought of as revealing pre-existing values. Any attempt to do so in a realistic hidden-variable theory leads ...
*
Quantum foundations Quantum foundations is a discipline of science that seeks to understand the most counter-intuitive aspects of quantum theory, reformulate it and even propose new generalizations thereof. Contrary to other physical theories, such as general relati ...


References


Further reading

* * * {{Quantum mechanics topics Nonlocality Nonlocality Theoretical physics