Quantum logic
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the mathematical study of logic and the physical analysis of quantum foundations, quantum logic is a set of rules for manipulation of
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
s inspired by the structure of
quantum theory Quantum theory may refer to: Science *Quantum mechanics, a major field of physics *Old quantum theory, predating modern quantum mechanics * Quantum field theory, an area of quantum mechanics that includes: ** Quantum electrodynamics ** Quantum ...
. The field takes as its starting point an observation of
Garrett Birkhoff Garrett Birkhoff (January 19, 1911 – November 22, 1996) was an American mathematician. He is best known for his work in lattice theory. The mathematician George Birkhoff (1884–1944) was his father. Life The son of the mathematician Ge ...
and John von Neumann, that the structure of experimental tests in classical mechanics forms a
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
, but the structure of experimental tests in quantum mechanics forms a much more complicated structure. Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher Hilary Putnam, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper " Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the epistemological status of the rules of propositional logic. Modern philosophers reject quantum logic as a basis for reasoning, because it lacks a
material conditional The material conditional (also known as material implication) is an operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \rightarrow is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \rightarrow Q is true unless P is true and Q i ...
; a common alternative is the system of linear logic, of which quantum logic is a fragment. Mathematically, quantum logic is formulated by weakening the
distributive law In mathematics, the distributive property of binary operations generalizes the distributive law, which asserts that the equality x \cdot (y + z) = x \cdot y + x \cdot z is always true in elementary algebra. For example, in elementary arithmetic, ...
for a Boolean algebra, resulting in an orthocomplemented lattice. Quantum-mechanical
observable In physics, an observable is a physical quantity that can be measured. Examples include position and momentum. In systems governed by classical mechanics, it is a real-valued "function" on the set of all possible system states. In quantum phy ...
s and states can be defined in terms of functions on or to the lattice, giving an alternate
formalism Formalism may refer to: * Form (disambiguation) * Formal (disambiguation) * Legal formalism, legal positivist view that the substantive justice of a law is a question for the legislature rather than the judiciary * Formalism (linguistics) * Scie ...
for quantum computations.


Introduction

The most notable difference between quantum logic and classical logic is the failure of the propositional
distributive law In mathematics, the distributive property of binary operations generalizes the distributive law, which asserts that the equality x \cdot (y + z) = x \cdot y + x \cdot z is always true in elementary algebra. For example, in elementary arithmetic, ...
: :''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r''), where the symbols ''p'', ''q'' and ''r'' are propositional variables. To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the
reduced Planck's constant The Planck constant, or Planck's constant, is a fundamental physical constant of foundational importance in quantum mechanics. The constant gives the relationship between the energy of a photon and its frequency, and by the mass-energy equivalen ...
is 1) letDue to technical reasons, it is not possible to represent these propositions as quantum-mechanical operators. They are presented here because they are simple enough to enable intuition, and can be considered as limiting cases of operators that ''are'' feasible. See ''et seq.'' for details. : ''p'' = "the particle has momentum in the interval " : ''q'' = "the particle is in the interval " : ''r'' = "the particle is in the interval " We might observe that: : ''p'' and (''q'' or ''r'') = ''true'' in other words, that the state of the particle is a weighted superposition of momenta between 0 and +1/6 and positions between −1 and +3. On the other hand, the propositions "''p'' and ''q''" and "''p'' and ''r''" each assert tighter restrictions on simultaneous values of position and momentum than are allowed by the
uncertainty principle In quantum mechanics, the uncertainty principle (also known as Heisenberg's uncertainty principle) is any of a variety of mathematical inequalities asserting a fundamental limit to the accuracy with which the values for certain pairs of physic ...
(they each have uncertainty 1/3, which is less than the allowed minimum of 1/2). So there are no states that can support either proposition, and : (''p'' and ''q'') or (''p'' and ''r'') = ''false''


History and modern criticism

In his classic 1932 treatise ''
Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics The book ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'' (1932) by John von Neumann is an important early work in the development of quantum theory. Publication history The book was originally published in German in 1932 by Julius Springer, un ...
'', John von Neumann noted that projections on a Hilbert space can be viewed as propositions about physical observables; that is, as potential ''yes-or-no questions'' an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions that could be settled by some measurement. Principles for manipulating these quantum propositions were then called ''quantum logic'' by von Neumann and Birkhoff in a 1936 paper.
George Mackey George Whitelaw Mackey (February 1, 1916 – March 15, 2006) was an American mathematician known for his contributions to quantum logic, representation theory, and noncommutative geometry. Career Mackey earned his bachelor of arts at Rice Unive ...
, in his 1963 book (also called ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics''), attempted to axiomatize quantum logic as the structure of an orthocomplemented lattice, and recognized that a physical observable could be ''defined'' in terms of quantum propositions. Although Mackey's presentation still assumed that the orthocomplemented lattice is the
lattice Lattice may refer to: Arts and design * Latticework, an ornamental criss-crossed framework, an arrangement of crossing laths or other thin strips of material * Lattice (music), an organized grid model of pitch ratios * Lattice (pastry), an orna ...
of closed linear subspaces of a separable Hilbert space, Constantin Piron, Günther Ludwig and others later developed axiomatizations that do not assume an underlying Hilbert space. Inspired by Hans Reichenbach's recent defence of
general relativity General relativity, also known as the general theory of relativity and Einstein's theory of gravity, is the geometric theory of gravitation published by Albert Einstein in 1915 and is the current description of gravitation in modern physics ...
, the philosopher Hilary Putnam popularized Mackey's work in two papers in 1968 and 1975, in which he attributed the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with a failure of logic itself to his coauthor, physicist
David Finkelstein David Ritz Finkelstein (July 19, 1929 – January 24, 2016) was an emeritus professor of physics at the Georgia Institute of Technology. Biography Born in New York City, Finkelstein obtained his Ph.D. in physics at the Massachusetts Institute ...
. Putnam hoped to develop a possible alternative to
hidden variables Hidden variables may refer to: * Confounding, in statistics, an extraneous variable in a statistical model that correlates (directly or inversely) with both the dependent variable and the independent variable * Hidden transformation, in computer ...
or
wavefunction collapse In quantum mechanics, wave function collapse occurs when a wave function—initially in a superposition of several eigenstates—reduces to a single eigenstate due to interaction with the external world. This interaction is called an ''observa ...
in the problem of
quantum measurement In quantum physics, a measurement is the testing or manipulation of a physical system to yield a numerical result. The predictions that quantum physics makes are in general probabilistic. The mathematical tools for making predictions about what ...
, but Gleason's theorem presents severe difficulties for this goal. Later, Putnam retracted his views, albeit with much less fanfare, but the damage had been done. While Birkhoff and von Neumann's original work only attempted to organize the calculations associated with the
Copenhagen interpretation The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics, principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. It is one of the oldest of numerous proposed interpretations of quantum mechanics, as feat ...
of quantum mechanics, a school of researchers had now sprung up, either hoping that quantum logic would provide a viable hidden-variable theory, or obviate the need for one. Their work proved fruitless, and now lies in poor repute. Most philosophers find quantum logic an unappealing competitor to classical logic. It is far from evident that quantum logic is a ''logic'', in the sense of describing a process of reasoning, as opposed to a particularly convenient language to summarize the measurements performed by quantum apparatuses. (However, others argue that they ''are'' logics and satisfy all the canonical conditions logicians require to call an abstract object a logic.) In particular, modern
philosophers of science Philosophy of science is a branch of philosophy concerned with the foundations, methods, and implications of science. The central questions of this study concern what qualifies as science, the reliability of scientific theories, and the ultim ...
argue that quantum logic attempts to substitute metaphysical difficulties for unsolved problems in physics, rather than properly solving the physics problems.
Tim Maudlin Tim William Eric Maudlin (born April 23, 1958) is an American philosopher of science who has done influential work on the metaphysical foundations of physics and logic. Education and career Maudlin graduated from Sidwell Friends School, W ...
writes that quantum "logic "solves" the easurementproblem by making the problem impossible to state." Quantum logic remains in limited use among logicians as an extremely pathological counterexample (Dalla Chiara and Giuntini: "Why quantum logics? Simply because 'quantum logics are there!'"). Although the central insight to quantum logic remains
mathematical folklore In common mathematical parlance, a mathematical result is called folklore if it is an unpublished result with no clear originator, but which is well-circulated and believed to be true among the specialists. More specifically, folk mathematics, or ...
as an intuition pump for categorification, discussions rarely mention quantum logic.


Algebraic structure

Quantum logic can be axiomatized as the theory of propositions modulo the following identities: * ''a''¬¬''a'' * ∨ is
commutative In mathematics, a binary operation is commutative if changing the order of the operands does not change the result. It is a fundamental property of many binary operations, and many mathematical proofs depend on it. Most familiar as the name of ...
and associative. * There is a maximal element ⊤, and ⊤''b''∨¬''b'' for any ''b''. * ''a''∨¬(¬''a''∨''b'')''a''. ("¬" is the traditional notation for " not", "∨" the notation for " or", and "∧" the notation for " and".) Some authors restrict to orthomodular lattices, which additionally satisfy the orthomodular law: * If ⊤¬(¬''a''∨¬''b'')∨¬(''a''∨''b'') then ''a'b''. ("⊤" is the traditional notation for
truth Truth is the property of being in accord with fact or reality.Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionarytruth 2005 In everyday language, truth is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise correspond to it, such as belie ...
and ""⊥" the traditional notation for
falsity Deception or falsehood is an act or statement that misleads, hides the truth, or promotes a belief, concept, or idea that is not true. It is often done for personal gain or advantage. Deception can involve dissimulation, propaganda and sleight o ...
.) Alternative formulations include propositions derivable via a
natural deduction In logic and proof theory, natural deduction is a kind of proof calculus in which logical reasoning is expressed by inference rules closely related to the "natural" way of reasoning. This contrasts with Hilbert-style systems, which instead use ax ...
,
sequent calculus In mathematical logic, sequent calculus is a style of formal logical argumentation in which every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhard Gentzen) instead of an unconditional tautology. Each conditional tautology i ...
or
tableaux The International Conference on Automated Reasoning with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods (TABLEAUX) is an annual international academic conference that deals with all aspects of automated reasoning with analytic tableaux. Periodically, it jo ...
system. Despite the relatively developed proof theory, quantum logic is not known to be decidable.


Quantum logic as the logic of observables

The remainder of this article assumes the reader is familiar with the
spectral theory In mathematics, spectral theory is an inclusive term for theories extending the eigenvector and eigenvalue theory of a single square matrix to a much broader theory of the structure of operators in a variety of mathematical spaces. It is a result ...
of
self-adjoint operator In mathematics, a self-adjoint operator on an infinite-dimensional complex vector space ''V'' with inner product \langle\cdot,\cdot\rangle (equivalently, a Hermitian operator in the finite-dimensional case) is a linear map ''A'' (from ''V'' to its ...
s on a Hilbert space. However, the main ideas can be understood in the finite-dimensional case.


The logic of classical mechanics

The
Hamiltonian Hamiltonian may refer to: * Hamiltonian mechanics, a function that represents the total energy of a system * Hamiltonian (quantum mechanics), an operator corresponding to the total energy of that system ** Dyall Hamiltonian, a modified Hamiltonian ...
formulations of
classical mechanics Classical mechanics is a physical theory describing the motion of macroscopic objects, from projectiles to parts of machinery, and astronomical objects, such as spacecraft, planets, stars, and galaxies. For objects governed by classi ...
have three ingredients: states,
observable In physics, an observable is a physical quantity that can be measured. Examples include position and momentum. In systems governed by classical mechanics, it is a real-valued "function" on the set of all possible system states. In quantum phy ...
s and dynamics. In the simplest case of a single particle moving in R3, the state space is the position-momentum space R6. An observable is some real-valued function ''f'' on the state space. Examples of observables are position, momentum or energy of a particle. For classical systems, the value ''f''(''x''), that is the value of ''f'' for some particular system state ''x'', is obtained by a process of measurement of ''f''. The
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
s concerning a classical system are generated from basic statements of the form :"Measurement of ''f'' yields a value in the interval 'a'', ''b''for some real numbers ''a'', ''b''." through the conventional arithmetic operations and pointwise limits. It follows easily from this characterization of propositions in classical systems that the corresponding logic is identical to the
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
of Borel subsets of the state space. They thus obey the laws of classical
propositional logic Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
(such as de Morgan's laws) with the set operations of union and intersection corresponding to the Boolean conjunctives and subset inclusion corresponding to material implication. In fact, a stronger claim is true: they must obey the
infinitary logic An infinitary logic is a logic that allows infinitely long statements and/or infinitely long proofs. Some infinitary logics may have different properties from those of standard first-order logic. In particular, infinitary logics may fail to be co ...
. We summarize these remarks as follows: The proposition system of a classical system is a lattice with a distinguished ''orthocomplementation'' operation: The lattice operations of ''meet'' and ''join'' are respectively set intersection and set union. The orthocomplementation operation is set complement. Moreover, this lattice is ''sequentially complete'', in the sense that any sequence ''i'' of elements of the lattice has a least upper bound, specifically the set-theoretic union: \operatorname(\) = \bigcup_^\infty E_i\text


The propositional lattice of a quantum mechanical system

In the Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics as presented by von Neumann, a physical observable is represented by some (possibly unbounded) densely defined
self-adjoint operator In mathematics, a self-adjoint operator on an infinite-dimensional complex vector space ''V'' with inner product \langle\cdot,\cdot\rangle (equivalently, a Hermitian operator in the finite-dimensional case) is a linear map ''A'' (from ''V'' to its ...
''A'' on a Hilbert space ''H''. ''A'' has a spectral decomposition, which is a
projection-valued measure In mathematics, particularly in functional analysis, a projection-valued measure (PVM) is a function defined on certain subsets of a fixed set and whose values are self-adjoint projections on a fixed Hilbert space. Projection-valued measures are ...
E defined on the Borel subsets of R. In particular, for any bounded Borel function ''f'' on R, the following extension of ''f'' to operators can be made: : f(A) = \int_ f(\lambda) \, d \operatorname(\lambda). In case ''f'' is the indicator function of an interval 'a'', ''b'' the operator ''f''(''A'') is a self-adjoint projection onto the subspace of
generalized eigenvector In linear algebra, a generalized eigenvector of an n\times n matrix A is a vector which satisfies certain criteria which are more relaxed than those for an (ordinary) eigenvector. Let V be an n-dimensional vector space; let \phi be a linear map ...
s of ''A'' with eigenvalue in . That subspace can be interpreted as the quantum analogue of the classical proposition * Measurement of ''A'' yields a value in the interval 'a'', ''b'' This suggests the following quantum mechanical replacement for the orthocomplemented lattice of propositions in classical mechanics, essentially Mackey's ''Axiom VII'': * The propositions of a quantum mechanical system correspond to the lattice of closed subspaces of ''H''; the negation of a proposition ''V'' is the orthogonal complement ''V''. The space ''Q'' of quantum propositions is also sequentially complete: any pairwise disjoint sequence''i'' of elements of ''Q'' has a least upper bound. Here disjointness of ''W''1 and ''W''2 means ''W''2 is a subspace of ''W''1. The least upper bound of ''i'' is the closed internal direct sum.


Standard semantics

The standard semantics of quantum logic is that quantum logic is the logic of
projection operator In linear algebra and functional analysis, a projection is a linear transformation P from a vector space to itself (an endomorphism) such that P\circ P=P. That is, whenever P is applied twice to any vector, it gives the same result as if it wer ...
s in a separable
Hilbert David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician, one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many ...
or pre-Hilbert space, where an observable ''p'' is associated with the set of quantum states for which ''p'' (when measured) has
eigenvalue In linear algebra, an eigenvector () or characteristic vector of a linear transformation is a nonzero vector that changes at most by a scalar factor when that linear transformation is applied to it. The corresponding eigenvalue, often denoted ...
1. From there, * ''¬p'' is the
orthogonal complement In the mathematical fields of linear algebra and functional analysis, the orthogonal complement of a subspace ''W'' of a vector space ''V'' equipped with a bilinear form ''B'' is the set ''W''⊥ of all vectors in ''V'' that are orthogonal to every ...
of ''p'' (since for those states, the probability of observing ''p'', P(''p'') = 0), * ''p''∧''q'' is the intersection of ''p'' and ''q'', and * ''p''∨''q'' = ¬(¬''p''∧¬''q'') refers to states that superpose ''p'' and ''q''. This semantics has the nice property that the pre-Hilbert space is complete (i.e., Hilbert) if and only if the propositions satisfy the orthomodular law, a result known as the
Solèr theorem In mathematics, Solèr's theorem is a result concerning certain infinite-dimensional vector spaces. It states that any orthomodular form that has an infinite orthonormal set is a Hilbert space over the real numbers, complex numbers or quaternions. ...
. The orthomodular semantics and syntax of quantum logic is due to, has a completeness theorem and it fails for the deduction theorem. Although much of the development of quantum logic has been motivated by the standard semantics, it is not the characterized by the latter; there are additional properties satisfied by that lattice that need not hold in quantum logic.


Differences with classical logic

The structure of ''Q'' immediately points to a difference with the partial order structure of a classical proposition system. In the classical case, given a proposition ''p'', the equations :⊤=''p''∨''q'' and :"⊥=''p''∧''q'' have exactly one solution, namely the set-theoretic complement of ''p''. In the case of the lattice of projections there are infinitely many solutions to the above equations (any closed, algebraic complement of ''p'' solves it; it need not be the orthocomplement). More generally, propositional valuation has unusual properties in quantum logic. An orthocomplemented lattice admitting a total lattice homomorphism to must be Boolean. A standard workaround is to study maximal partial homomorphisms ''q'' with a filtering property: :if ''a''≤''b'' and ''q''(''a'')=⊤, then ''q''(''b'')=⊤.


Failure of distributivity

Expressions in quantum logic describe observables using a syntax that resembles classical logic. However, unlike classical logic, the distributive law ''a'' ∧ (''b'' ∨ ''c'') = (''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') fails when dealing with noncommuting observables, such as position and momentum. This occurs because measurement affects the system, and measurement of whether a disjunction holds does not measure which of the disjuncts is true. For example, consider a simple one-dimensional particle with position denoted by ''x'' and momentum by ''p'', and define observables: * ''a'' — , ''p'', ≤ 1 (in some units) * ''b'' — x < 0 * ''c'' — x ≥ 0 Now, position and momentum are Fourier transforms of each other, and the Fourier transform of a
square-integrable In mathematics, a square-integrable function, also called a quadratically integrable function or L^2 function or square-summable function, is a real- or complex-valued measurable function for which the integral of the square of the absolute value ...
nonzero function with a compact support is
entire Entire may refer to: * Entire function, a function that is holomorphic on the whole complex plane * Entire (animal), an indication that an animal is not neutered * Entire (botany) This glossary of botanical terms is a list of definitions of ...
and hence does not have non-isolated zeroes. Therefore, there is no wave function that is both normalizable in momentum space and vanishes on precisely ''x'' ≥ 0. Thus, ''a'' ∧ ''b'' and similarly ''a'' ∧ ''c'' are false, so (''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') is false. However, ''a'' ∧ (''b'' ∨ ''c'') equals ''a'', which is certainly not false (there are states for which it is a viable measurement outcome). Moreover: if the relevant Hilbert space for the particle's dynamics only admits momenta no greater than 1, then ''a'' is true. To understand more, let ''p''1 and ''p''2 be the momenta for the restriction of the particle wave function to ''x'' < 0 and ''x'' ≥ 0 respectively (with the wave function zero outside of the restriction). Let , ''p'', ↾>1 be the restriction of , ''p'', to momenta that are (in absolute value) >1. (''a'' ∧ ''b'') ∨ (''a'' ∧ ''c'') corresponds to states with , ''p''1, ↾>1 = , ''p''2, ↾>1 = 0 (this holds even if we defined ''p'' differently so as to make such states possible; also, ''a'' ∧ ''b'' corresponds to , ''p''1, ↾>1=0 and ''p''2=0). As an ''operator'', ''p''=''p''1+''p''2, and nonzero , ''p''1, ↾>1 and , ''p''2, ↾>1 might interfere to produce zero , ''p'', ↾>1. Such interference is key to the richness of quantum logic and quantum mechanics.


Relationship to quantum measurement


Mackey observables

Given a orthocomplemented lattice ''Q'', a Mackey observable φ is a countably additive homomorphism from the orthocomplemented lattice of Borel subsets of R to ''Q''. In symbols, this means that for any sequence ''i'' of pairwise disjoint Borel subsets of R, ''i'' are pairwise orthogonal propositions (elements of ''Q'') and : \varphi\left(\bigcup_^\infty S_i\right) = \sum_^\infty \varphi(S_i). Equivalently, a Mackey observable is a
projection-valued measure In mathematics, particularly in functional analysis, a projection-valued measure (PVM) is a function defined on certain subsets of a fixed set and whose values are self-adjoint projections on a fixed Hilbert space. Projection-valued measures are ...
on R. Theorem (
Spectral theorem In mathematics, particularly linear algebra and functional analysis, a spectral theorem is a result about when a linear operator or matrix can be diagonalized (that is, represented as a diagonal matrix in some basis). This is extremely useful ...
). If ''Q'' is the lattice of closed subspaces of Hilbert ''H'', then there is a bijective correspondence between Mackey observables and densely defined self-adjoint operators on ''H''.


Quantum probability measures

A ''quantum probability measure'' is a function P defined on ''Q'' with values in ,1such that P("⊥)=0, P(⊤)=1 and if ''i'' is a sequence of pairwise orthogonal elements of ''Q'' then : \operatorname\!\left(\bigvee_^\infty E_i\right) = \sum_^\infty \operatorname(E_i). Every quantum probability measure on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space is induced by a
density matrix In quantum mechanics, a density matrix (or density operator) is a matrix that describes the quantum state of a physical system. It allows for the calculation of the probabilities of the outcomes of any measurement performed upon this system, using ...
 — a nonnegative operator of trace 1. Formally, :Theorem. Suppose ''Q'' is the lattice of closed subspaces of a separable Hilbert space of complex dimension at least 3. Then for any quantum probability measure ''P'' on ''Q'' there exists a unique
trace class In mathematics, specifically functional analysis, a trace-class operator is a linear operator for which a trace may be defined, such that the trace is a finite number independent of the choice of basis used to compute the trace. This trace of trace ...
operator ''S'' such that \operatorname(E) = \operatorname(S E) for any self-adjoint projection ''E'' in ''Q''.


Relationship to other logics

Quantum logic embeds into linear logicVaughan Pratt,
Linear logic for generalized quantum mechanics
" in ''Workshop on Physics and Computation (PhysComp '92)'' proceedings. See also the discussion at ''n''Lab
Revision 42
which cites G.D. Crown, "On some orthomodular posets of vector bundles," ''Journ. of Natural Sci. and Math.'', vol. 15 issue 1-2: pp. 11–25, 1975.
and the modal logic ''B''. The orthocomplemented lattice of any set of quantum propositions can be embedded into a Boolean algebra, which is then amenable to classical logic.


Limitations

Although many treatments of quantum logic assume that the underlying lattice must be orthomodular, such logics cannot handle multiple interacting quantum systems. In an example due to Foulis and Randall, there are orthomodular propositions with finite-dimensional Hilbert models whose pairing admits no orthomodular model. Quantum logic admits no reasonable
material conditional The material conditional (also known as material implication) is an operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \rightarrow is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \rightarrow Q is true unless P is true and Q i ...
; any connective that is monotone in a certain technical sense reduces the class of propositions to a
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
. Consequently, quantum logic struggles to represent the passage of time. One possible workaround is the theory of quantum filtrations developed in the late 1970s and 1980s by Belavkin. It is known, however, that System BV, a
deep inference Deep inference names a general idea in structural proof theory that breaks with the classical sequent calculus by generalising the notion of structure to permit inference to occur in contexts of high structural complexity. The term ''deep inferenc ...
fragment of linear logic that is very close to quantum logic, can handle arbitrary discrete spacetimes.Richard Blute, Alessio Guglielmi, Ivan T. Ivanov, Prakash Panangaden, Lutz Straßburger, "A Logical Basis for Quantum Evolution and Entanglement" in ''Categories and Types in Logic, Language, and Physics: Essays Dedicated to Jim Lambek on the Occasion of His 90th Birthday''; Springer, 2014. pp. 90-107. DOI:&nbs
10.1007/978-3-642-54789-8_6
HAL&nbs
01092279


See also

* Fuzzy logic * HPO formalism (An approach to temporal quantum logic) * Linear logic *
Mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics The mathematical formulations of quantum mechanics are those mathematical formalisms that permit a rigorous description of quantum mechanics. This mathematical formalism uses mainly a part of functional analysis, especially Hilbert spaces, which ...
*
Multi-valued logic Many-valued logic (also multi- or multiple-valued logic) refers to a propositional calculus in which there are more than two truth values. Traditionally, in Aristotle's logical calculus, there were only two possible values (i.e., "true" and "false ...
* Quantum Bayesianism * Quantum cognition * Quantum contextuality * Quantum field theory *
Quantum probability The Born rule (also called Born's rule) is a key postulate of quantum mechanics which gives the probability that a measurement of a quantum system will yield a given result. In its simplest form, it states that the probability density of findi ...
* Quasi-set theory * Solèr's theorem * Vector logic


Notes


Citations


Further reading


Historical works

:''Organized chronologically'' * * * * * * *


Modern philosophical perspectives

* * * *


Mathematical study

* * * N. Papanikolaou,
Reasoning Formally About Quantum Systems: An Overview
, ''ACM SIGACT News'', 36(3), 2005. pp. 51–66. arXi
cs/0508005


Quantum foundations

* D. Cohen, ''An Introduction to Hilbert Space and Quantum Logic'', Springer-Verlag, 1989. Elementary and well-illustrated; suitable for advanced undergraduates. * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Quantum Logic Mathematical logic Systems of formal logic Non-classical logic Quantum mechanics