Prior Analytics
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The ''Prior Analytics'' ( grc-gre, Ἀναλυτικὰ Πρότερα; la, Analytica Priora) is a work by
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ...
on
reasoning Reason is the capacity of consciously applying logic by drawing conclusions from new or existing information, with the aim of seeking the truth. It is closely associated with such characteristically human activities as philosophy, science, langu ...
, known as his
syllogistic A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true. ...
, composed around 350 BCE. Being one of the six extant Aristotelian writings on logic and scientific method, it is part of what later
Peripatetics The Peripatetic school was a school of philosophy in Ancient Greece. Its teachings derived from its founder, Aristotle (384–322 BC), and ''peripatetic'' is an adjective ascribed to his followers. The school dates from around 335 BC when Aristo ...
called the '' Organon''. Modern work on Aristotle's logic builds on the tradition started in 1951 with the establishment by
Jan Łukasiewicz Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logic. ...
of a revolutionary paradigm. His approach was replaced in the early 1970s in a series of papers by John Corcoran and
Timothy Smiley Timothy John Smiley FBA (born 13 November 1930) is a British philosopher, appointed Emeritus Knightbridge Professor of Philosophy at Clare College, Cambridge University. He works primarily in philosophy of mathematics and logic. Life and car ...
—which inform modern translations of ''Prior Analytics'' by Robin Smith in 1989 and Gisela Striker in 2009. The term ''analytics'' comes from the Greek words ''analytos'' (ἀναλυτός, 'solvable') and ''analyo'' (ἀναλύω, 'to solve', literally 'to loose'). However, in Aristotle's corpus, there are distinguishable differences in the meaning of ἀναλύω and its cognates. There is also the possibility that Aristotle may have borrowed his use of the word "analysis" from his teacher
Plato Plato ( ; grc-gre, Πλάτων ; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BC) was a Greek philosopher born in Athens during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. He founded the Platonist school of thought and the Academy, the first institution ...
. On the other hand, the meaning that best fits the ''Analytics'' is one derived from the study of Geometry and this meaning is very close to what Aristotle calls '' episteme'' (επιστήμη), knowing the reasoned facts. Therefore, Analysis is the process of finding the reasoned facts. Aristotle's ''Prior Analytics'' represents the first time in history when Logic is scientifically investigated. On those grounds alone, Aristotle could be considered the Father of Logic for as he himself says in ''
Sophistical Refutations ''Sophistical Refutations'' ( el, Σοφιστικοὶ Ἔλεγχοι, Sophistikoi Elenchoi; la, De Sophisticis Elenchis) is a text in Aristotle's ''Organon'' in which he identified thirteen fallacies.Sometimes listed as twelve. According to ...
'', "When it comes to this subject, it is not the case that part had been worked out before in advance and part had not; instead, nothing existed at all." A problem in meaning arises in the study of ''Prior Analytics'' for the word ''syllogism'' as used by Aristotle in general does not carry the same narrow connotation as it does at present; Aristotle defines this term in a way that would apply to a wide range of
valid argument In logic, specifically in deductive reasoning, an argument is valid if and only if it takes a form that makes it impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion nevertheless to be false. It is not required for a valid argument to have ...
s. Some scholars prefer to use the word "deduction" instead as the meaning given by Aristotle to the Greek word ''syllogismos'' (συλλογισμός). At present, ''syllogism'' is used exclusively as the method used to reach a conclusion which is really the narrow sense in which it is used in the Prior Analytics dealing as it does with a much narrower class of arguments closely resembling the "syllogisms" of traditional logic texts: two premises followed by a conclusion each of which is a categorical sentence containing all together three terms, two extremes which appear in the conclusion and one middle term which appears in both premises but not in the conclusion. In the ''Analytics'' then, ''Prior Analytics'' is the first theoretical part dealing with the science of deduction and the ''
Posterior Analytics The ''Posterior Analytics'' ( grc-gre, Ἀναλυτικὰ Ὕστερα; la, Analytica Posteriora) is a text from Aristotle's '' Organon'' that deals with demonstration, definition, and scientific knowledge. The demonstration is distinguis ...
'' is the second demonstratively practical part. ''Prior Analytics'' gives an account of deductions in general narrowed down to three basic syllogisms while ''Posterior Analytics'' deals with demonstration. In the ''Prior Analytics'', Aristotle defines syllogism as "a deduction in a discourse in which, certain things being supposed, something different from the things supposed results of necessity because these things are so." In modern times, this definition has led to a debate as to how the word "syllogism" should be interpreted. Scholars
Jan Lukasiewicz Jan, JaN or JAN may refer to: Acronyms * Jackson, Mississippi (Amtrak station), US, Amtrak station code JAN * Jackson-Evers International Airport, Mississippi, US, IATA code * Jabhat al-Nusra (JaN), a Syrian militant group * Japanese Article Numb ...
, Józef Maria Bocheński and Günther Patzig have sided with the Protasis- Apodosis
dichotomy A dichotomy is a partition of a whole (or a set) into two parts (subsets). In other words, this couple of parts must be * jointly exhaustive: everything must belong to one part or the other, and * mutually exclusive: nothing can belong simul ...
while John Corcoran prefers to consider a syllogism as simply a deduction. In the third century AD, Alexander of Aphrodisias's commentary on the ''Prior Analytics'' is the oldest extant and one of the best of the ancient tradition and is available in the English language. In the sixth century,
Boethius Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, commonly known as Boethius (; Latin: ''Boetius''; 480 – 524 AD), was a Roman senator, consul, ''magister officiorum'', historian, and philosopher of the Early Middle Ages. He was a central figure in the t ...
composed the first known Latin translation of the ''Prior Analytics''. No Westerner between Boethius and Bernard of Utrecht is known to have read the ''Prior Analytics''. The so-called ''Anonymus Aurelianensis III'' from the second half of the twelfth century is the first extant Latin commentary, or rather fragment of a commentary.


The syllogism

The ''Prior Analytics'' represents the first formal study of logic, where logic is understood as the study of arguments. An argument is a series of true or false statements which lead to a true or false conclusion. In the ''Prior Analytics'', Aristotle identifies valid and invalid forms of arguments called syllogisms. A syllogism is an argument that consists of at least three sentences: at least two premises and a conclusion. Although Aristotle does not call them " categorical sentences," tradition does; he deals with them briefly in the ''Analytics'' and more extensively in '' On Interpretation''. Each proposition (statement that is a thought of the kind expressible by a declarative sentence) of a syllogism is a categorical sentence which has a subject and a predicate connected by a verb. The usual way of connecting the subject and predicate of a categorical sentence as Aristotle does in ''On Interpretation'' is by using a linking verb e.g. P is S. However, in the Prior Analytics Aristotle rejects the usual form in favor of three of his inventions: 1) P belongs to S, 2) P is predicated of S and 3) P is said of S. Aristotle does not explain why he introduces these innovative expressions but scholars conjecture that the reason may have been that it facilitates the use of letters instead of terms avoiding the ambiguity that results in Greek when letters are used with the linking verb. In his formulation of syllogistic propositions, instead of the copula ("All/some... are/are not..."), Aristotle uses the expression, "... belongs to/does not belong to all/some..." or "... is said/is not said of all/some..." There are four different types of categorical sentences: universal affirmative (A), particular affirmative (I), universal negative (E) and particular negative (O). *A - A belongs to every B *E - A belongs to no B *I - A belongs to some B *O - A does not belong to some B A method of symbolization that originated and was used in the Middle Ages greatly simplifies the study of the Prior Analytics. Following this tradition then, let: :a = belongs to every :e = belongs to no :i = belongs to some :o = does not belong to some Categorical sentences may then be abbreviated as follows: :AaB = A belongs to every B (Every B is A) :AeB = A belongs to no B (No B is A) :AiB = A belongs to some B (Some B is A) :AoB = A does not belong to some B (Some B is not A) From the viewpoint of modern logic, only a few types of sentences can be represented in this way.


The three figures

Depending on the position of the middle term, Aristotle divides the syllogism into three kinds: syllogism in the first, second, and third figure. If the Middle Term is subject of one premise and predicate of the other, the premises are in the First Figure. If the Middle Term is predicate of both premises, the premises are in the Second Figure. If the Middle Term is subject of both premises, the premises are in the Third Figure. Symbolically, the Three Figures may be represented as follows:


The fourth figure

In Aristotelian syllogistic (''Prior Analytics'', Bk I Caps 4-7), syllogisms are divided into three figures according to the position of the middle term in the two premises. The fourth figure, in which the middle term is the predicate in the major premise and the subject in the minor, was added by Aristotle's pupil
Theophrastus Theophrastus (; grc-gre, Θεόφραστος ; c. 371c. 287 BC), a Greek philosopher and the successor to Aristotle in the Peripatetic school. He was a native of Eresos in Lesbos.Gavin Hardy and Laurence Totelin, ''Ancient Botany'', Routle ...
and does not occur in Aristotle's work, although there is evidence that Aristotle knew of fourth-figure syllogisms.


Syllogism in the first figure

In the ''Prior Analytics'' translated by A. J. Jenkins as it appears in volume 8 of the Great Books of the Western World, Aristotle says of the First Figure: "... If A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, A must be predicated of all C." In the ''Prior Analytics'' translated by Robin Smith, Aristotle says of the first figure: "... For if A is predicated of every B and B of every C, it is necessary for A to be predicated of every C." Taking ''a'' = ''is predicated of all'' = ''is predicated of every'', and using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages, then the first figure is simplified to: :If AaB : :and BaC : :then AaC. Or what amounts to the same thing: :AaB, BaC; therefore AaC When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the first figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the first figure: :AaB, BaC; therefore, AaC :AeB, BaC; therefore, AeC :AaB, BiC; therefore, AiC :AeB, BiC; therefore, AoC In the Middle Ages, for
mnemonic A mnemonic ( ) device, or memory device, is any learning technique that aids information retention or retrieval (remembering) in the human memory for better understanding. Mnemonics make use of elaborative encoding, retrieval cues, and image ...
reasons they were called "Barbara", "Celarent", "Darii" and "Ferio" respectively. The difference between the first figure and the other two figures is that the syllogism of the first figure is complete while that of the second and fourth is not. This is important in Aristotle's theory of the syllogism for the first figure is axiomatic while the second and third require proof. The proof of the second and third figure always leads back to the first figure.


Syllogism in the second figure

This is what Robin Smith says in English that Aristotle said in Ancient Greek: "... If M belongs to every N but to no X, then neither will N belong to any X. For if M belongs to no X, neither does X belong to any M; but M belonged to every N; therefore, X will belong to no N (for the first figure has again come about)." The above statement can be simplified by using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages: :If MaN : :but MeX : :then NeX. : :For if MeX : :then XeM : :but MaN : :therefore XeN. When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the second figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the second figure: :MaN, MeX; therefore NeX :MeN, MaX; therefore NeX :MeN, MiX; therefore NoX :MaN, MoX; therefore NoX In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons they were called respectively "Camestres", "Cesare", "Festino" and "Baroco".


Syllogism in the third figure

Aristotle says in the Prior Analytics, "... If one term belongs to all and another to none of the same thing, or if they both belong to all or none of it, I call such figure the third." Referring to universal terms, "... then when both P and R belongs to every S, it results of necessity that P will belong to some R." Simplifying: :If PaS : :and RaS : :then PiR. When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the third figure, Aristotle develops six more valid forms of deduction: :PaS, RaS; therefore PiR :PeS, RaS; therefore PoR :PiS, RaS; therefore PiR :PaS, RiS; therefore PiR :PoS, RaS; therefore PoR :PeS, RiS; therefore PoR In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons, these six forms were called respectively: "Darapti", "Felapton", "Disamis", "Datisi", "Bocardo" and "Ferison".


Table of syllogisms


Boole’s acceptance of Aristotle

George Boole's unwavering acceptance of Aristotle's logic is emphasized by the historian of logic John Corcoran in an accessible introduction to ''Laws of Thought'' Corcoran also wrote a point-by-point comparison of ''Prior Analytics'' and ''Laws of Thought''.John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288. According to Corcoran, Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic. Boole's goals were “to go under, over, and beyond” Aristotle's logic by: # providing it with mathematical foundations involving equations; # extending the class of problems it could treat—from assessing validity to solving equations; and # expanding the range of applications it could handle—e.g. from propositions having only two terms to those having arbitrarily many. More specifically, Boole agreed with what
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ...
said; Boole's ‘disagreements’, if they might be called that, concern what Aristotle did not say. First, in the realm of foundations, Boole reduced the four propositional forms of Aristotle's logic to formulas in the form of equations—-by itself a revolutionary idea. Second, in the realm of logic's problems, Boole's addition of equation solving to logic—-another revolutionary idea—-involved Boole's doctrine that Aristotle's rules of inference (the “perfect syllogisms”) must be supplemented by rules for equation solving. Third, in the realm of applications, Boole's system could handle multi-term propositions and arguments whereas Aristotle could handle only two-termed subject-predicate propositions and arguments. For example, Aristotle's system could not deduce “No quadrangle that is a square is a rectangle that is a rhombus” from “No square that is a quadrangle is a rhombus that is a rectangle” or from “No rhombus that is a rectangle is a square that is a quadrangle”.


See also

* Law of identity * '' Reductio ad absurdum''


Notes


Bibliography

; Greek text * Aristotle. ''Analytica Priora et Posteriora''. Ed. Ross and Minio-Paluello. Oxford University Press, 1981. ISBN 9780198145622. * Aristotle. ''Categories; On Interpretation; Prior Analytics''. Greek text with translation by H. P. Cooke, Hugh Tredennick. Loeb Classical Library 325. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1938. ISBN 9780674993594. ; Translations * Aristotle, ''Prior Analytics'', translated by Robin Smith, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989. * Aristotle, ''Prior Analytics Book I'', translated by Gisela Striker, Oxford: Clarendon Press 2009. ; Studies * Corcoran, John (ed.), 1974. ''Ancient Logic and its Modern Interpretations.'', Dordrecht: Reidel. * Corcoran, John, 1974a. "Aristotle's Natural Deduction System". ''Ancient Logic and its Modern Interpretations'', pp. 85-131. * Lukasiewicz, Jan, 1957. ''Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic.'' 2nd edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press. * Smiley, Timothy. 1973. "What Is a Syllogism?", ''Journal of Philosophical Logic'', 2, pp.136-154.


External links

* The text of the ''Prior Analytics'' is availabl
from the MIT classics archive

''Prior Analytics''
trans. by A. J. Jenkinson *
Prior Analytics - Uncompressed Audiobook

Aristotle: Logic
entry by Louis Groarke in the
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''IEP'') is a scholarly online encyclopedia, dealing with philosophy, philosophical topics, and philosophers. The IEP combines open access publication with peer reviewed publication of original p ...
*
Aristotle's Prior Analytics: the Theory of Categorical Syllogism
an annotated bibliography on Aristotle's syllogistic {{Authority control Works by Aristotle Term logic History of logic Logic literature Syllogism