Natural Law and Natural Rights
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

''Natural Law and Natural Rights'' (1980; second edition 2011) is a book by
John Finnis John Mitchell Finnis, , (born 28 July 1940) is an Australian legal philosopher, jurist and scholar specializing in jurisprudence and the philosophy of law. He is the Biolchini Family Professor of Law, emeritus, at Notre Dame Law School and a ...
first published by
Oxford University Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the university press of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world, and its printing history dates back to the 1480s. Having been officially granted the legal right to print books ...
, as part of the Clarendon Law Series. Finnis develops a philosophy of Law in the tradition of
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ph ...
and
Thomas Aquinas Thomas Aquinas, OP (; it, Tommaso d'Aquino, lit=Thomas of Aquino; 1225 – 7 March 1274) was an Italian Dominican friar and priest who was an influential philosopher, theologian and jurist in the tradition of scholasticism; he is known wit ...
– Natural Law.  His presentation and defence of Natural Law can be explored from three perspectives. First, polemical, by contradistinction with other philosophies of Law.  Second, through its particular methodology, based on practical reasoning.  Third, through its substantive content in the form of basic human goods.  This article offers a brief overview of each of these perspectives. In addition, his 2011 edition included an extensive Postcript, which is briefly discussed in the 4th Section. A brief appraisal of the book is included in the final section.


Polemical

Finnis critiques a number of authors and philosophical traditions, thereby offering polemical support for his conception of Natural Law. An illustration of this (by no means exhaustive) follows below. *
Consequentialism In ethical philosophy, consequentialism is a class of normative, teleological ethical theories that holds that the consequences of one's conduct are the ultimate basis for judgment about the rightness or wrongness of that conduct. Thus, fro ...
(and
utilitarianism In ethical philosophy, utilitarianism is a family of normative ethical theories that prescribe actions that maximize happiness and well-being for all affected individuals. Although different varieties of utilitarianism admit different chara ...
). Finnis argues that consequentialist arguments are frustrated by the impossibility of double-guessing consequences and the impossibility of maximising incommensurable ends and choices. *
David Hume David Hume (; born David Home; 7 May 1711 NS (26 April 1711 OS) – 25 August 1776) Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 999br>David Hume" ''Encyclopædia Britannica''. Retrieved 18 May 2020. was a Scottish Enlightenment phil ...
.  Finnis acknowledges the validity of Hume's critique of
Samuel Clarke Samuel Clarke (11 October 1675 – 17 May 1729) was an English philosopher and Anglican cleric. He is considered the major British figure in philosophy between John Locke and George Berkeley. Early life and studies Clarke was born in Norwich, ...
's Natural Law on the basis that it derives moral obligations (“ought”) from the fact of things or actions being “good” (“is”).  However, Finnis claims that this is not applicable to his own version of Natural Law where the moral obligation (“ought”) and its “goodness” derive from practical reasoning. *
Francisco Suarez Francisco is the Spanish and Portuguese form of the masculine given name ''Franciscus''. Nicknames In Spanish, people with the name Francisco are sometimes nicknamed "Paco". San Francisco de Asís was known as ''Pater Comunitatis'' (father of ...
.  Finnis criticises Suarez for misinterpreting Aquinas by, among other things, adopting a “rationalist” view of Natural Law focused on the (presumed) ability of the intellect to recognise whether a given choice accords with human nature or not. *
H. L. A. Hart Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (18 July 190719 December 1992), known simply as H. L. A. Hart, was an English legal philosopher. He was Professor of Jurisprudence (University of Oxford), Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford University an ...
.  Hart was Finnis’ PhD supervisor and the force behind his writing the book.  However, he regrets that Hart's ''The concept of Law'' refuses to engage with moral content and fails to recognise moral purpose in legal punishment (as opposed to mere vindictiveness). *
Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant (, , ; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and ...
.  Finnis argues that Kant reduces human nature to
practical reason In philosophy, practical reason is the use of reason to decide how to act. It contrasts with theoretical reason, often called speculative reason, the use of reason to decide what to follow. For example, agents use practical reason to decide whethe ...
devoid of moral content. *
John Rawls John Bordley Rawls (; February 21, 1921 – November 24, 2002) was an American moral, legal and political philosopher in the liberal tradition. Rawls received both the Schock Prize for Logic and Philosophy and the National Humanities Medal in ...
: Finnis argues that Rawls’ ''
original position The original position (OP), often referred to as the veil of ignorance, is a thought experiment used for reasoning about the principles that should structure a society based on mutual dependence. The phrases ''original position'' and ''veil of i ...
'' in ''A Theory of Justice'' excludes the possibility of adopting positions as matter of principle, e.g., including positions that might clash with those of others. The result is an impoverished view of human flourishing. *
Joseph Raz Joseph Raz (; he, יוסף רז; born Zaltsman; 21 March 19392 May 2022) was an Israeli legal, moral and political philosopher. He was an advocate of legal positivism and is known for his conception of perfectionist liberalism. Raz spent mos ...
.  Finnis corrects Raz's ''Practical Reason and Norms''s'' misinterpretation of his Natural Law. * Robert Nozick: Finnis argues against Nozick's notion of coercive State (in ''Anarchy, State and Utopia'') noting that individuals (and not only the State) owe a duty of distributive justice to other individuals. *
Plato Plato ( ; grc-gre, Πλάτων ; 428/427 or 424/423 – 348/347 BC) was a Greek philosopher born in Athens during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. He founded the Platonist school of thought and the Academy, the first institution ...
.  Finnis attributes to Plato the origin of Natural Law conceptions, further developed by Aristotle and Aquinas.  This includes a contemplative notion of man's relation to the divine. Yet, Finnis critiques communistic conceptions of human society based on Plato's ''Republic'' because they overlook the importance of human commitment. He distinguishes such notions from subsidiarity. * Ronald Dworkin.  Finnis critiques Dworkin for emptying the legal institution of moral content. Among others, Finnis critiques
Thomas Hobbes Thomas Hobbes ( ; 5/15 April 1588 – 4/14 December 1679) was an English philosopher, considered to be one of the founders of modern political philosophy. Hobbes is best known for his 1651 book ''Leviathan'', in which he expounds an influ ...
,
Jeremy Bentham Jeremy Bentham (; 15 February 1748 Old_Style_and_New_Style_dates">O.S._4_February_1747.html" ;"title="Old_Style_and_New_Style_dates.html" ;"title="nowiki/>Old Style and New Style dates">O.S. 4 February 1747">Old_Style_and_New_Style_dates.htm ...
, and both critiques and praises,
John Austin John Austin may refer to: Arts and entertainment * John P. Austin (1906–1997), American set decorator * Johnny Austin (1910–1983), American musician * John Austin (author) (fl. 1940s), British novelist Military * John Austin (soldier) (180 ...
, W.N. Hohfeld and Max Weber. Whilst following them, he also notes substantive limitations in Aquinas’ and Aristotle's accounts of Natural Law.


Methodology

The methodology that gives rise to Finnis's conception of Natural Law is based on practical reasoning or reasonableness.  For Finnis, practical reasoning is the making of choices about the kind of life that we want to live.  Such choices are guided through participation in (through a natural apprehension of), and (subsequent) reflection on, the basic goods (listed in the next section).  Choices, and acts that follow from such choices, may prioritise some basic goods over others but cannot overlook any of them, or involve arbitrary preferences among persons – such arbitrariness is avoided through a benevolent impartial judgment (as distinguished from the ‘
veil of ignorance The original position (OP), often referred to as the veil of ignorance, is a thought experiment used for reasoning about the principles that should structure a society based on mutual dependence. The phrases ''original position'' and ''veil of i ...
') - and will seek the good of the whole community or
common good In philosophy, economics, and political science, the common good (also commonwealth, general welfare, or public benefit) is either what is shared and beneficial for all or most members of a given community, or alternatively, what is achieved by c ...
. The common good includes distributive and commutative obligations of justice to others. Morality is practical reasoning which makes life worth living by respecting these conditions, This same logic applies to the making of laws.  However, like day-to-day choices, the making of laws, may on a peremptory basis be guided by more immediate reasons.  Yet, such reasons will be ultimately grounded in practical reasoning, and this will reveal itself now and then in legal argumentation, as it does in the effort of individuals to explain their choices.  However, there may be laws (as human choices more generally) that do not take account of all the conditions of practical reasoning described above.  Thereby, they lose their moral authority since individuals will be inclined to disregard them as not satisfying their own understanding of a good life. Nevertheless, such laws remain legally binding through the enforcement procedures provided by the legal system and through their importance for peaceful coexistence.  Through the junction of legal and moral, Natural Law becomes the focal meaning of law. Practical reasoning ultimately is insufficient to give us certainty that our choices are worth making.  Thus, we tend to assume metaphysical justifications, which point to some external state of affairs ''D''.  This D is God. Incidentally, Finnis argues that people should not despair from failing in their life goals, provided they have participated in the basic goods.


Basic Goods

The list of basic forms of human good or basic goods is as follows: * practical reasoning or reasonableness, as described above; * life, including the procreation of children; * knowledge, meaning the desire to know truth from confusion; * play, as an activity that is absorbing but has no utility beyond the participation in the activity itself; * aesthetic experience, that is, beauty in things or actions; * sociability (friendship), involving commitment to the interests and well-being of others; * religion, which concerns the metaphysical (as described above); and * marriage, added in the Postcript. The basic goods are distinguished from virtues, which are ways of pursuing the basic goods.


Postcript

The Postcript systematically reviews all the arguments in the book, expanding and clarifying them by reference to Finnis' other writings. It is significant that in p. 425, Finnis notes that "the book has significant weaknesses. But its main purposes and main positions remain intact." Some issues discussed in the Poscript are noted below. * The good of the person is the unifying theme for all basic goods. * Marriage is a basic good, because it is a multiple source of human flourishing. * The basic good of play indicates excellence in work or play. * Finnis notes that, in his later writings, "aesthetic experience" is included in the basic good of knowledge. In addition, religion is redefined as "harmony with the widest reaches and most ultimate source of all reality, including meaning and value." (p. 448) He argues that his account of what can be rationally said about God is too limited (and it is further explored by Aquinas). * Friendship includes "fellow-feeling among human persons." (p. 457) * Finnis suggests that his amended list of basic goods is likely to be complete. * There is priority among the basic goods. Life is a precondition of the others and practical reasonableness structures the pursuit and realization of the other basic goods. * Incommensurability applies between basic goods, as well as within each basic good and between persons. * "Social justice" ( Quadragesimo Anno) replaces
Cajetan Cajetan and Kajetan is the Anglicized and Germanized form of the Italian given name Gaetano. People with this name include: * Thomas Cajetan (1469–1534), Italian Dominican theologian, cardinal, and opponent of Martin Luther * Saint Cajetan (Gaet ...
's legal justice, standing in addition to distributive and commutative justice. Social justice tends to unity by begging of individuals the question "to ''which'' community do I really belong in a contest of allegiances?" (p. 462). * The common good is the outcome of pursuit of the basic goods (especially friendship, which leads to cooperation). It can be enforced by the State when conceived as a "public good".


General comments on the book

The book is written as a collection of essays on a wide range of topics guided by an overall theme, though this may not become fully apparent until the end.  The essays are partly descriptive and partly polemical. The arguments are elaborated in excruciating detail, which makes the book, at times, an arduous read.  The breadth of subjects and viewpoints delivers a compendium of jurisprudential knowledge, as well as a substantive presentation and defence of the notion of Natural Law.  


References

{{reflist 1980 non-fiction books Books by John Finnis Contemporary philosophical literature English-language books English non-fiction books Oxford University Press books Philosophy of law