Kleene fixed-point theorem
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the
mathematical Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
areas of
order Order, ORDER or Orders may refer to: * Categorization, the process in which ideas and objects are recognized, differentiated, and understood * Heterarchy, a system of organization wherein the elements have the potential to be ranked a number of ...
and
lattice theory A lattice is an abstract structure studied in the mathematical subdisciplines of order theory and abstract algebra. It consists of a partially ordered set in which every pair of elements has a unique supremum (also called a least upper bou ...
, the Kleene fixed-point theorem, named after American mathematician Stephen Cole Kleene, states the following: :Kleene Fixed-Point Theorem. Suppose (L, \sqsubseteq) is a directed-complete partial order (dcpo) with a least element, and let f: L \to L be a
Scott-continuous In mathematics, given two partially ordered sets ''P'' and ''Q'', a function ''f'': ''P'' → ''Q'' between them is Scott-continuous (named after the mathematician Dana Scott) if it preserves all directed suprema. That is, for every directed subs ...
(and therefore
monotone Monotone refers to a sound, for example music or speech, that has a single unvaried tone. See: monophony. Monotone or monotonicity may also refer to: In economics *Monotone preferences, a property of a consumer's preference ordering. *Monotonic ...
) function. Then f has a least fixed point, which is the
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest ...
of the ascending Kleene chain of f. The ascending Kleene chain of ''f'' is the
chain A chain is a serial assembly of connected pieces, called links, typically made of metal, with an overall character similar to that of a rope in that it is flexible and curved in compression but linear, rigid, and load-bearing in tension. ...
:\bot \sqsubseteq f(\bot) \sqsubseteq f(f(\bot)) \sqsubseteq \cdots \sqsubseteq f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq \cdots obtained by iterating ''f'' on the least element ⊥ of ''L''. Expressed in a formula, the theorem states that :\textrm(f) = \sup \left(\left\\right) where \textrm denotes the least fixed point. Although Tarski's fixed point theorem does not consider how fixed points can be computed by iterating ''f'' from some seed (also, it pertains to
monotone function In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of order ...
s on complete lattices), this result is often attributed to
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician a ...
who proves it for additive functions Moreover, Kleene Fixed-Point Theorem can be extended to
monotone function In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of order ...
s using transfinite iterations.


Proof

We first have to show that the ascending Kleene chain of f exists in L. To show that, we prove the following: :Lemma. If L is a dcpo with a least element, and f: L \to L is Scott-continuous, then f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^(\bot), n \in \mathbb_0 :Proof. We use induction: :* Assume n = 0. Then f^0(\bot) = \bot \sqsubseteq f^1(\bot), since \bot is the least element. :* Assume n > 0. Then we have to show that f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^(\bot). By rearranging we get f(f^(\bot)) \sqsubseteq f(f^n(\bot)). By inductive assumption, we know that f^(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^n(\bot) holds, and because f is monotone (property of Scott-continuous functions), the result holds as well. As a corollary of the Lemma we have the following directed ω-chain: :\mathbb = \. From the definition of a dcpo it follows that \mathbb has a supremum, call it m. What remains now is to show that m is the least fixed-point. First, we show that m is a fixed point, i.e. that f(m) = m. Because f is
Scott-continuous In mathematics, given two partially ordered sets ''P'' and ''Q'', a function ''f'': ''P'' → ''Q'' between them is Scott-continuous (named after the mathematician Dana Scott) if it preserves all directed suprema. That is, for every directed subs ...
, f(\sup(\mathbb)) = \sup(f(\mathbb)), that is f(m) = \sup(f(\mathbb)). Also, since \mathbb = f(\mathbb)\cup\ and because \bot has no influence in determining the supremum we have: \sup(f(\mathbb)) = \sup(\mathbb). It follows that f(m) = m, making m a fixed-point of f. The proof that m is in fact the ''least'' fixed point can be done by showing that any element in \mathbb is smaller than any fixed-point of f (because by property of
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest ...
, if all elements of a set D \subseteq L are smaller than an element of L then also \sup(D) is smaller than that same element of L). This is done by induction: Assume k is some fixed-point of f. We now prove by induction over i that \forall i \in \mathbb: f^i(\bot) \sqsubseteq k. The base of the induction (i = 0) obviously holds: f^0(\bot) = \bot \sqsubseteq k, since \bot is the least element of L. As the induction hypothesis, we may assume that f^i(\bot) \sqsubseteq k. We now do the induction step: From the induction hypothesis and the monotonicity of f (again, implied by the Scott-continuity of f), we may conclude the following: f^i(\bot) \sqsubseteq k ~\implies~ f^(\bot) \sqsubseteq f(k). Now, by the assumption that k is a fixed-point of f, we know that f(k) = k, and from that we get f^(\bot) \sqsubseteq k.


See also

* Other fixed-point theorems


References

{{Reflist Order theory Fixed-point theorems