Indirect proof
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premise ...
and mathematics, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the
truth Truth is the property of being in accord with fact or reality.Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionarytruth 2005 In everyday language, truth is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise correspond to it, such as belie ...
or the validity of a
proposition In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
, by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a
contradiction In traditional logic, a contradiction occurs when a proposition conflicts either with itself or established fact. It is often used as a tool to detect disingenuous beliefs and bias. Illustrating a general tendency in applied logic, Aristotle's ...
. Proof by contradiction is also known as indirect proof, proof by assuming the opposite, and ''reductio ad impossibile''. It is an example of the weaker logical refutation ''
reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical arguments'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absu ...
''. A mathematical proof employing proof by contradiction usually proceeds as follows: #The proposition to be proved is ''P''. #We assume ''P'' to be false, i.e., we assume ''¬P''. #It is then shown that ''¬P'' implies falsehood. This is typically accomplished by deriving two mutually contradictory assertions, ''Q'' and ''¬Q'', and appealing to the Law of noncontradiction. #Since assuming ''P'' to be false leads to a contradiction, it is concluded that ''P'' is in fact true. An important special case is the
existence proof In mathematics, a constructive proof is a method of proof that demonstrates the existence of a mathematical object by creating or providing a method for creating the object. This is in contrast to a non-constructive proof (also known as an existenc ...
by contradiction: in order to demonstrate the existence of an object satisfying a given property, we assume that no such object exists and derive a contradiction. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical proofs, not every school of mathematical thought accepts this kind of
nonconstructive proof In mathematics, a constructive proof is a method of proof that demonstrates the existence of a mathematical object by creating or providing a method for creating the object. This is in contrast to a non-constructive proof (also known as an existenc ...
as universally valid.


Formalization

The principle may be formally expressed as the
propositional formula In propositional logic, a propositional formula is a type of syntactic formula which is well formed and has a truth value. If the values of all variables in a propositional formula are given, it determines a unique truth value. A propositional for ...
''¬¬P ⇒ P'', equivalently ''(¬P ⇒ ⊥) ⇒ P'', which reads: "If assuming ''P'' to be false implies falsehood, then ''P'' is true." In
natural deduction In logic and proof theory, natural deduction is a kind of proof calculus in which logical reasoning is expressed by inference rules closely related to the "natural" way of reasoning. This contrasts with Hilbert-style systems, which instead use ax ...
the principle takes the form of the rule of inference : \cfrac which reads: "If \lnot\lnot P is proved, then P may be concluded." In
sequent calculus In mathematical logic, sequent calculus is a style of formal logical argumentation in which every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhard Gentzen) instead of an unconditional tautology. Each conditional tautology i ...
the principle is expressed by the sequent : \Gamma, \lnot\lnot P \vdash P, \Delta which reads: "Hypotheses \Gamma ''and'' \lnot\lnot P entail the conclusion P ''or'' \Delta."


Justification

In classical logic the principle may be justified by the examination of the
truth table A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional argumen ...
of the proposition ''¬¬P ⇒ P'', which demonstrates it to be a tautology: Another way to justify the principle is to derive it from the
Law of the excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradi ...
, as follows. We assume ''¬¬P'' and seek to prove ''P''. By the law of excluded middle ''P'' either holds or it does not: # if ''P'' holds, then of course ''P'' holds. # if ''¬P'' holds, then we derive falsehood by applying the law of noncontradiction to ''¬P'' and ''¬¬P'', after which the
principle of explosion In classical logic, intuitionistic logic and similar logical systems, the principle of explosion (, 'from falsehood, anything ollows; or ), or the principle of Pseudo-Scotus, is the law according to which any statement can be proven from a ...
allows us to conclude ''P''. In either case, we established ''P''. It turns out that, conversely, proof by contradiction can be used to derive the law of excluded middle. In classical sequent calculus LK proof by contradiction is derivable from the inference rules for negation: : \cfrac \; (L)


Relationship with other proof techniques


Refutation by contradiction

Proof by contradiction is frequently confused with the similar-looking refutation by contradiction, a.k.a. proof of negation, which states that ''¬P'' is proved as follows: # The proposition to be proved is ''¬P''. # Assume ''P''. # Derive falsehood. # Conclude ''¬P''. In contrast, proof by contradiction proceeds as follows: # The proposition to be proved is ''P''. # Assume ''¬P''. # Derive falsehood. # Conclude ''P''. Refutation by contradiction applies only when the proposition to be proved is negated, whereas proof by contradiction may be applied to any proposition whatsoever. Confusingly, in mathematical practice, both proof by contradiction and refutation by contradiction are referred to as "proof by contradiction", as they proceed in a similar manner. However, they are not equivalent—unless we assume the law of excluded middle, in which case they become equivalent.


Law of non-contradiction

The law of noncontradiction was first formalized as a metaphysical principle by
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ph ...
. It states that a proposition and its negation cannot both be true. Equivalently, it states that a proposition cannot be both true and false. Formally the law of non-contradiction is written as ''¬(Q ∧ ¬Q)'' and read as "it is not the case that a proposition is both true and false". The law of non-contradiction neither follows nor is implied by the principle of Proof by contradiction.


Law of the excluded middle

Proof by contradiction is equivalent to the
law of the excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradi ...
, also first formulated by Aristotle, which states that either an assertion or its negation is true, ''P ∨ ¬P''. Combined with the principle of noncontradiction, this means that exactly one of ''P'' and ''¬P'' is true.


Proof by contradiction in intuitionistic logic

In
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
proof by contradiction is not generally valid, although some particular instances can be derived. In contrast, proof of negation and principle of noncontradiction are both intuitionistically valid.
Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation In mathematical logic, the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, or BHK interpretation, of intuitionistic logic was proposed by L. E. J. Brouwer and Arend Heyting, and independently by Andrey Kolmogorov. It is also sometimes called the rea ...
of proof by contradiction gives the following intuitionistic validity condition: :"If there is no method for establishing that a proposition is false, then there is a method for establishing that the proposition is true." If we take "method" to mean
algorithm In mathematics and computer science, an algorithm () is a finite sequence of rigorous instructions, typically used to solve a class of specific problems or to perform a computation. Algorithms are used as specifications for performing ...
, then the condition is not acceptable, as it would allow us to solve the
Halting problem In computability theory, the halting problem is the problem of determining, from a description of an arbitrary computer program and an input, whether the program will finish running, or continue to run forever. Alan Turing proved in 1936 that a ...
. To see how, consider the statement ''H(M)'' stating "
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer algori ...
''M'' halts or does not halt". Its negation ''¬H(M)'' states that "''M'' neither halts nor does not halt", which is false by the law of noncontradiction (which is intuitionistically valid). If proof by contradiction were intuitionistically valid, we would obtain an algorithm for deciding whether an arbitrary Turing machine ''M'' halts, thereby violating the (intuitionistically valid) proof of non-solvability of the
Halting problem In computability theory, the halting problem is the problem of determining, from a description of an arbitrary computer program and an input, whether the program will finish running, or continue to run forever. Alan Turing proved in 1936 that a ...
. A proposition ''P'' which satisfies \lnot\lnot P \Rightarrow P is known as a ''¬¬-stable proposition''. Thus in intuitionistic logic proof by contradiction is not universally valid, but can only be applied to the ¬¬-stable propositions. An instance of such a proposition is a decidable one, i.e., satisfying P \lor \lnot P. Indeed, the above proof that the law of excluded middle implies proof by contradiction can be repurposed to show that a decidable proposition is ¬¬-stable. A typical example of a decidable proposition is a statement that can be checked by direct computation, such as "n is prime" or "a divides b".


Examples of proofs by contradiction


Euclid's Elements

An early occurrence of proof by contradiction can be found in
Euclid's Elements The ''Elements'' ( grc, Στοιχεῖα ''Stoikheîa'') is a mathematical treatise consisting of 13 books attributed to the ancient Greek mathematician Euclid in Alexandria, Ptolemaic Egypt 300 BC. It is a collection of definitions, postulat ...
, Book 1, Proposition 6: : If in a triangle two angles equal one another, then the sides opposite the equal angles also equal one another. The proof proceeds by assuming that the opposite angles are not equal, and derives a contradiction.


Hilbert's Nullstellensatz

An influential proof by contradiction was given by David Hilbert. His Nullstellensatz states: : If f_1,\ldots,f_k are
polynomial In mathematics, a polynomial is an expression consisting of indeterminates (also called variables) and coefficients, that involves only the operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and positive-integer powers of variables. An example ...
s in indeterminates with
complex Complex commonly refers to: * Complexity, the behaviour of a system whose components interact in multiple ways so possible interactions are difficult to describe ** Complex system, a system composed of many components which may interact with each ...
coefficients, which have no common complex zeros, then there are polynomials g_1,\ldots, g_k such that f_1g_1+\ldots +f_kg_k=1. Hilbert proved the statement by assuming that there are no such polynomials g_1, \ldots, g_k and derived a contradiction.


Infinitude of primes

Euclid's theorem Euclid's theorem is a fundamental statement in number theory that asserts that there are infinitely many prime numbers. It was first proved by Euclid in his work ''Elements''. There are several proofs of the theorem. Euclid's proof Euclid offered ...
states that there are infinitely many primes. In
Euclid's Elements The ''Elements'' ( grc, Στοιχεῖα ''Stoikheîa'') is a mathematical treatise consisting of 13 books attributed to the ancient Greek mathematician Euclid in Alexandria, Ptolemaic Egypt 300 BC. It is a collection of definitions, postulat ...
the theorem is stated in Book IX, Proposition 20: : Prime numbers are more than any assigned multitude of prime numbers. Depending on how we formally write the above statement, the usual proof takes either the form of a proof by contradiction or a refutation by contradiction. We present here the former, see below how the proof is done as refutation by contradiction. If we formally express Euclid's theorem as saying that for every natural number n there is a prime bigger than it, then we employ proof by contradiction, as follows. Given any number n, we seek to prove that there is a prime larger than n. Suppose to the contrary that no such ''p'' exists (an application of proof by contradiction). Then all primes are smaller than or equal to n, and we may form the list p_1, \ldots, p_k of them all. Let P = p_1 \cdot \ldots \cdot p_k be the product of all primes and Q = P + 1. Because Q is larger than all prime numbers it is not prime, hence it must be divisible by one of them, say p_i. Now both P and Q are divisible by p_i, hence so is their difference Q - P = 1, but this cannot be because 1 is not divisible by any primes. Hence we have a contradiction and so there is a prime number bigger than n


Examples of refutations by contradiction

Because proof by contradiction is frequently conflated with refutation by contradiction, the following are often erroneously claimed to be proofs by contradiction, but they really are refutations by contradiction (and therefore intuitionistically valid).


Infinitude of primes

Let us take a second look at
Euclid's theorem Euclid's theorem is a fundamental statement in number theory that asserts that there are infinitely many prime numbers. It was first proved by Euclid in his work ''Elements''. There are several proofs of the theorem. Euclid's proof Euclid offered ...
– Book IX, Proposition 20: : Prime numbers are more than any assigned multitude of prime numbers. We may read the statement as saying that for every finite list of primes, there is another prime not on that list, which is arguably closer to and in the same spirit as Euclid's original formulation. In this case Euclid's proof applies refutation by contradiction at one step, as follows. Consider any finite list of prime numbers p_1, \ldots, p_n. It will be shown that at least one additional prime number not in this list exists. Let P = p_1 \cdot p_2 \cdots p_n be the product of all the prime numbers in the list and Q = P + 1. Then Q is either prime or not: * If Q is prime, then Q itself is a prime not in the list, as it is greater than all primes in the list. * If Q is not prime, then it has a prime factor p. We claim that p is not in the given list of primes. Suppose to the contrary that it were (an application of refutation by contradiction). Then p would divide P, and because it also divides Q it divides their difference Q - P = 1. This gives a contradiction, since no prime number divides 1. Thus p is a prime number not in the list.


Irrationality of the square root of 2

The classic proof that the square root of 2 is irrational is a refutation by contradiction. Indeed, we set out to prove the negation ''¬ ∃ a, b ∈ \mathbb . a/b = '' by assuming that there exist natural numbers ''a'' and ''b'' whose ratio is the square root of two, and derive a contradiction.


Proof by infinite descent

Proof by infinite descent In mathematics, a proof by infinite descent, also known as Fermat's method of descent, is a particular kind of proof by contradiction used to show that a statement cannot possibly hold for any number, by showing that if the statement were to hold f ...
is a method of proof whereby a smallest object with desired property is shown not to exist as follows: * Assume that there is a smallest object with the desired property. * Demonstrate that an even smaller object with the desired property exists, thereby deriving a contradiction. Such a proof is not a proof by contradiction but once again a refutation by contradiction. A typical example is the proof of the proposition "there is no smallest positive rational number": assume there is a smallest positive rational number ''q'' and derive a contradiction by observing that is even smaller than ''q'' and still positive.


Russell's paradox

Russell's paradox In mathematical logic, Russell's paradox (also known as Russell's antinomy) is a set-theoretic paradox discovered by the British philosopher and mathematician Bertrand Russell in 1901. Russell's paradox shows that every set theory that contains ...
, stated set-theoretically as "there is no set whose elements are precisely those sets that do not contain themselves", is a negated statement whose usual proof is a refutation by contradiction.


Notation

Proofs by contradiction sometimes end with the word "Contradiction!". Isaac Barrow and Baermann used the notation Q.E.A., for "''quod est absurdum''" ("which is absurd"), along the lines of Q.E.D., but this notation is rarely used today. A graphical symbol sometimes used for contradictions is a downwards zigzag arrow "lightning" symbol (U+21AF: ↯), for example in Davey and Priestley. Others sometimes used include a pair of opposing arrows (as \rightarrow\!\leftarrow or \Rightarrow\!\Leftarrow), struck-out arrows (\nleftrightarrow), a stylized form of hash (such as U+2A33: ⨳), or the "reference mark" (U+203B: ※), or \times\!\!\!\!\times.The Comprehensive LaTeX Symbol List, pg. 20. http://www.ctan.org/tex-archive/info/symbols/comprehensive/symbols-a4.pdf


Hardy's view

G. H. Hardy described proof by contradiction as "one of a mathematician's finest weapons", saying "It is a far finer gambit than any chess gambit: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game." G. H. Hardy, '' A Mathematician's Apology; Cambridge University Press, 1992. .
PDF p.19


See also

*
Law of excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the so-called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradi ...
* Law of noncontradiction *
Proof by exhaustion Proof by exhaustion, also known as proof by cases, proof by case analysis, complete induction or the brute force method, is a method of mathematical proof in which the statement to be proved is split into a finite number of cases or sets of equiv ...
*
Proof by infinite descent In mathematics, a proof by infinite descent, also known as Fermat's method of descent, is a particular kind of proof by contradiction used to show that a statement cannot possibly hold for any number, by showing that if the statement were to hold f ...
*
Modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "method of removing by taking away") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens' ...


References


Further reading and external links

*
Proof by Contradiction
from Larry W. Cusick'


Reductio ad Absurdum
Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy; ISSN 2161-0002 {{DEFAULTSORT:Proof By Contradiction Mathematical proofs Methods of proof Theorems in propositional logic