Independence of irrelevant alternatives
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

The independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA), also known as binary independence or the independence axiom, is an axiom of
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
and various
social sciences Social science is one of the branches of science, devoted to the study of societies and the relationships among individuals within those societies. The term was formerly used to refer to the field of sociology, the original "science of so ...
. The term is used in different connotation in several contexts. Although it always attempts to provide an account of rational individual behavior or aggregation of individual preferences, the exact formulation differs widely in both language and exact content. Perhaps the easiest way to understand the axiom is how it pertains to casting a ballot. There the axiom says that if Charlie (the irrelevant alternative) enters a race between
Alice and Bob Alice and Bob are fictional characters commonly used as placeholders in discussions about cryptographic systems and protocols, and in other science and engineering literature where there are several participants in a thought experiment. The Al ...
, with Alice (leader) liked better than Bob (runner-up), then the individual voter who likes Charlie less than Alice will not switch his vote from Alice to Bob. Because of this, a violation of IIA is commonly referred to as the "
spoiler effect Vote splitting is an electoral effect in which the distribution of votes among multiple similar candidates reduces the chance of winning for any of the similar candidates, and increases the chance of winning for a dissimilar candidate. Vote spl ...
": support for Charlie "spoils" the election for Alice, while it "logically" should not have. After all, Alice ''was'' liked better than Bob, and Charlie ''was'' liked less than Alice. In collective decision making contexts, the axiom takes a more refined form, and is mathematically intimately tied with
Condorcet method A Condorcet method (; ) is an election method that elects the candidate who wins a majority of the vote in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates, that is, a candidate preferred by more voters than any others, whenever ...
s, the
Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem In social choice theory, the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem is a result published independently by philosopher Allan Gibbard in 1973 and economist Mark Satterthwaite in 1975. It deals with deterministic ordinal electoral systems that choose a s ...
, and the Arrow Impossibility theorem. They all have to do with cyclical majorities between ranked sets, and the related proofs take the same basic form. Behavioral economics has shown the axiom to be commonly violated by humans.


The many forms of IIA

In individual choice theory, IIA sometimes refers to Chernoff's condition or Sen's α (alpha): if an alternative ''x'' is chosen from a set ''T'', and ''x'' is also an element of a subset ''S'' of ''T'', then ''x'' must be chosen from ''S''. That is, eliminating some of the unchosen alternatives shouldn't affect the selection of ''x'' as the best option. In
social choice theory Social choice theory or social choice is a theoretical framework for analysis of combining individual opinions, preferences, interests, or welfares to reach a ''collective decision'' or ''social welfare'' in some sense.Amartya Sen (2008). "Soci ...
, Arrow's IIA is one of the conditions in
Arrow's impossibility theorem Arrow's impossibility theorem, the general possibility theorem or Arrow's paradox is an impossibility theorem in social choice theory that states that when voters have three or more distinct alternatives (options), no ranked voting electoral syst ...
, which states that it is impossible to aggregate individual rank-order preferences ("votes") satisfying IIA in addition to certain other reasonable conditions. Arrow defines IIA thus: :The social preferences between alternatives ''x'' and ''y'' depend only on the individual preferences between ''x'' and ''y''. In
social choice theory Social choice theory or social choice is a theoretical framework for analysis of combining individual opinions, preferences, interests, or welfares to reach a ''collective decision'' or ''social welfare'' in some sense.Amartya Sen (2008). "Soci ...
, IIA is defined as: :If ''A'' is selected over ''B'' out of the choice set by a voting rule for given voter preferences of ''A'', ''B'', and an unavailable third alternative ''X'', then if only preferences for ''X'' change, the voting rule must not lead to ''Bs being selected over ''A''. In voting theory this often happens because of
perverse incentive A perverse incentive is an incentive that has an unintended and undesirable result that is contrary to the intentions of its designers. The cobra effect is the most direct kind of perverse incentive, typically because the incentive unintentional ...
s caused by the voting method. But in fact people violate the axiom for psychological reasons as well. For example in microeconomics, the axiom is further connected to the theory of revealed preference and formalised instrumental rationality: in
neoclassical economics Neoclassical economics is an approach to economics in which the production, consumption and valuation (pricing) of goods and services are observed as driven by the supply and demand model. According to this line of thought, the value of a good ...
it is generally held to be true, as a basic, predictive part of the framework, and something which theoretically stops
Dutch book In gambling, a Dutch book or lock is a set of odds and bets, established by the bookmaker, that ensures that the bookmaker will profit—at the expense of the gamblers—regardless of the outcome of the event (a horse race, for example) on which ...
s from happening. However, since it is
empirically In philosophy, empiricism is an epistemological theory that holds that knowledge or justification comes only or primarily from sensory experience. It is one of several views within epistemology, along with rationalism and skepticism. Empir ...
speaking either unsound or at best a crude approximation of live
human behavior Human behavior is the potential and expressed capacity ( mentally, physically, and socially) of human individuals or groups to respond to internal and external stimuli throughout their life. Kagan, Jerome, Marc H. Bornstein, and Richard M. ...
, the axiom continues to evoke lively debate. Not the least because it can further be argued that in order for a person to ''be'' ''rational'', they ''should'' abide by the axiom—thus making the axiom also a matter of
moral philosophy Ethics or moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy that "involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior".''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' The field of ethics, along with aesthetics, concerns ...
and axiology.


Voting theory

In
voting systems An electoral system or voting system is a set of rules that determine how elections and referendums are conducted and how their results are determined. Electoral systems are used in politics to elect governments, while non-political elections m ...
, independence from irrelevant alternatives is often interpreted as, if one candidate (''X'') would win an election, and if a new candidate (''Y'') were added to the ballot, then either ''X'' or ''Y'' would win the election. Approval voting, range voting, and
majority judgment Majority judgment (MJ) is a single-winner voting system proposed in 2007 by Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki. It is a highest median rule, i.e., a cardinal voting system that elects the candidate with the highest median rating. Unlike other v ...
satisfy the IIA criterion if it is assumed that voters rate candidates individually and independently of knowing the available alternatives in the election, using their own absolute scale. This assumption implies that some voters having meaningful preferences in an election with only two alternatives will necessarily cast a vote which has little or no voting power, or necessarily abstain. If it is assumed to be at least possible that any voter having preferences might not abstain, or vote their favorite and least favorite candidates at the top and bottom ratings respectively, then these systems fail IIA. Allowing either of these conditions alone causes failure. Another cardinal system,
cumulative voting Cumulative voting (also accumulation voting, weighted voting or multi-voting) is a multiple-winner method intended to promote more proportional representation than winner-take-all elections such as block voting or first past the post. Cumulativ ...
, does not satisfy the criterion regardless of either assumption. An alternative interpretation for the cardinal case is that the ballots themselves pass IIA (i.e. altering the ballot after they have been cast), but not the internal voter preferences (i.e. changing the context in which the ballots were created). Under the assumption of sincerity, the ranked information in ranked ballots and a voter's preference order are the same, so this distinction is not made and both sets of ranked information are assumed to be one and the same. Under the cardinal voting scenario, the context of the election and relative intensity of preferences is what leads to a specific cardinal ballot (and not an absolute scale), and thus, changing the context would change the ballot. Under this interpretation, there is no need for the assumption that voters cast ballots that independently evaluate each candidate on an absolute scale, as the information in the cardinal ballot represents a relative comparative scale. This interpretation is empirically supported by how individuals respond to cardinal comparative evaluations. An anecdote that illustrates a violation of IIA has been attributed to
Sidney Morgenbesser Sidney Morgenbesser (September 22, 1921 – August 1, 2004) was a Jewish American philosopher and professor at Columbia University. He wrote little but is remembered by many for his philosophical witticisms. Life and career Sidney Morgenbesser ...
: :After finishing dinner, Sidney Morgenbesser decides to order dessert. The waitress tells him he has two choices: apple pie and blueberry pie. Sidney orders the apple pie. After a few minutes the waitress returns and says that they also have cherry pie at which point Morgenbesser says "In that case I'll have the blueberry pie." All voting systems have some degree of inherent susceptibility to strategic nomination considerations. Some regard these considerations as less serious unless the voting system fails the easier-to-satisfy
independence of clones criterion In voting systems theory, the independence of clones criterion measures an election method's robustness to strategic nomination. Nicolaus Tideman was the first to formulate this criterion, which states that the winner must not change due to the ...
.


Local independence

A criterion weaker than IIA proposed by H. Peyton Young and A. Levenglick is called local independence from irrelevant alternatives (LIIA). LIIA requires that both of the following conditions always hold: *If the option that finished in last place is deleted from all the votes, then the order of finish of the remaining options must not change. (The winner must not change.) *If the winning option is deleted from all the votes, the order of finish of the remaining options must not change. (The option that finished in second place must become the winner.) An equivalent way to express LIIA is that if a subset of the options are in consecutive positions in the order of finish, then their relative order of finish must not change if all other options are deleted from the votes. For example, if all options except those in 3rd, 4th and 5th place are deleted, the option that finished 3rd must win, the 4th must finish second, and 5th must finish 3rd. Another equivalent way to express LIIA is that if two options are consecutive in the order of finish, the one that finished higher must win if all options except those two are deleted from the votes. LIIA is weaker than IIA because satisfaction of IIA implies satisfaction of LIIA, but not vice versa. Despite being a weaker criterion (i.e. easier to satisfy) than IIA, LIIA is satisfied by very few voting methods. These include Kemeny-Young and
ranked pairs Ranked pairs (sometimes abbreviated "RP") or the Tideman method is an electoral system developed in 1987 by Nicolaus Tideman that selects a single winner using votes that express preferences. The ranked-pairs procedure can also be used to create ...
, but not Schulze. Just as with IIA, LIIA compliance for rating methods such as approval voting, range voting, and
majority judgment Majority judgment (MJ) is a single-winner voting system proposed in 2007 by Michel Balinski and Rida Laraki. It is a highest median rule, i.e., a cardinal voting system that elects the candidate with the highest median rating. Unlike other v ...
require the assumption that voters rate each alternative individually and independently of knowing any other alternatives, on an absolute scale (calibrated prior to the election), even when this assumption implies that voters having meaningful preferences in a two candidate election will necessarily abstain.


Criticism of IIA

IIA is largely incompatible with the
majority criterion The majority criterion is a single-winner voting system criterion, used to compare such systems. The criterion states that "if one candidate is ranked first by a majority (more than 50%) of voters, then that candidate must win". Some methods that ...
unless there are only two alternatives. Consider a scenario in which there are three candidates ''A'', ''B'', & ''C'', and the voters' preferences are as follows: :25% of the voters prefer ''A'' over ''B'', and ''B'' over ''C''. (''A''>''B''>''C'') :40% of the voters prefer ''B'' over ''C'', and ''C'' over ''A''. (''B''>''C''>''A'') :35% of the voters prefer ''C'' over ''A'', and ''A'' over ''B''. (''C''>''A''>''B'') (These are preferences, not votes, and thus are independent of the voting method.) 75% prefer ''C'' over ''A'', 65% prefer ''B'' over ''C'', and 60% prefer ''A'' over ''B''. The presence of this societal
intransitivity In mathematics, intransitivity (sometimes called nontransitivity) is a property of binary relations that are not transitive relations. This may include any relation that is not transitive, or the stronger property of antitransitivity, which descri ...
is the
voting paradox The Condorcet paradox (also known as the voting paradox or the paradox of voting) in social choice theory is a situation noted by the Marquis de Condorcet in the late 18th century, in which collective preferences can be cyclic, even if the prefer ...
. Regardless of the voting method and the actual votes, there are only three cases to consider: *Case 1: ''A'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 75% who prefer ''C'' over ''A'' would elect ''C'' if ''B'' were not a candidate. *Case 2: ''B'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 60% who prefer ''A'' over ''B'' would elect ''A'' if ''C'' were not a candidate. *Case 3: ''C'' is elected. IIA is violated because the 65% who prefer ''B'' over ''C'' would elect ''B'' if ''A'' were not a candidate. To show failure, it is only assumed at least possible that enough voters in the majority might cast a minimally positive vote for their preferred candidate when there are only two candidates, rather than abstain. Most ranked ballot methods and Plurality voting satisfy the Majority Criterion, and therefore fail IIA automatically by the example above. Meanwhile, passage of IIA by Approval and Range voting requires in certain cases that voters in the majority are necessarily excluded from voting (they are assumed to necessarily abstain in a two candidate race, despite having a meaningful preference between the alternatives). So even if IIA is desirable, requiring its satisfaction seems to allow only voting methods that are undesirable in some other way, such as treating one of the voters as a dictator. Thus the goal must be to find which voting methods are best, rather than which are perfect. An argument can be made that IIA is itself undesirable. IIA assumes that when deciding whether ''A'' is likely to be better than ''B'', information about voters' preferences regarding ''C'' is irrelevant and should not make a difference. However, the heuristic that leads to majority rule when there are only two options is that the larger the number of people who think one option is better than the other, the greater the likelihood that it is better, all else being equal (see
Condorcet's Jury Theorem Condorcet's jury theorem is a political science theorem about the relative probability of a given group of individuals arriving at a correct decision. The theorem was first expressed by the Marquis de Condorcet in his 1785 work ''Essay on the App ...
). A majority is more likely than the opposing minority to be right about which of the two candidates is better, all else being equal, hence the use of majority rule. The same heuristic implies that the larger the majority, the more likely it is that they are right. It would seem to also imply that when there is more than one majority, larger majorities are more likely to be right than smaller majorities. Assuming this is so, the 75% who prefer ''C'' over ''A'' and the 65% who prefer ''B'' over ''C'' are more likely to be right than the 60% who prefer ''A'' over ''B'', and since it is not possible for all three majorities to be right, the smaller majority (who prefer ''A'' over ''B'') are more likely to be wrong, and less likely than their opposing minority to be right. Rather than being irrelevant to whether ''A'' is better than ''B'', the additional information about the voters' preferences regarding ''C'' provides a strong hint that this is a situation where all else is not equal.


In social choice

From
Kenneth Arrow Kenneth Joseph Arrow (23 August 1921 – 21 February 2017) was an American economist, mathematician, writer, and political theorist. He was the joint winner of the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences with John Hicks in 1972. In economics ...
, each "voter" ''i'' in the society has an ordering Ri that ranks the (conceivable) objects of
social choice Social choice theory or social choice is a theoretical framework for analysis of combining individual opinions, preferences, interests, or welfares to reach a ''collective decision'' or ''social welfare'' in some sense.Amartya Sen (2008). "Soci ...
—''x'', ''y'', and ''z'' in simplest case—from high to low. An ''aggregation rule'' (''voting rule'') in turn maps each ''profile'' or
tuple In mathematics, a tuple is a finite ordered list (sequence) of elements. An -tuple is a sequence (or ordered list) of elements, where is a non-negative integer. There is only one 0-tuple, referred to as ''the empty tuple''. An -tuple is defi ...
(R1, ...,Rn) of voter preferences (orderings) to a ''social ordering'' R that determines the social preference (ranking) of ''x'', ''y'', and ''z''. Arrow's IIA requires that whenever a pair of alternatives is ranked the same way in two preference profiles (over the same choice set), then the aggregation rule must order these alternatives identically across the two profiles. For example, suppose an aggregation rule ranks ''a'' above ''b'' at the profile given by *(''acbd'', ''dbac''), (i.e., the first individual prefers ''a'' first, ''c'' second, ''b'' third, ''d'' last; the second individual prefers ''d'' first, ..., and ''c'' last). Then, if it satisfies IIA, it must rank ''a'' above ''b'' at the following three profiles: *(''abcd'', ') *(''abcd'', ') *(''acdb'', '). The last two forms of profiles (placing the two at the top; and placing the two at the top and bottom) are especially useful in the proofs of theorems involving IIA. Arrow's IIA does not imply an IIA similar to those different from this at the top of this article nor conversely. In the first edition of his book, Arrow misinterpreted IIA by considering the removal of a choice from the consideration set. Among the objects of choice, he distinguished those that by hypothesis are specified as ''feasible'' and ''infeasible''. Consider two possible sets of voter orderings (''R_1, ...,R_n '') and (''R_1', ...,R_n''') such that the ranking of ''X'' and ''Y'' for each voter ''i'' is the same for ''R_i'' and ''R_i'''. The voting rule generates corresponding social orderings ''R'' and ''R'.'' Now suppose that ''X'' and ''Y'' are feasible but ''Z'' is infeasible (say, the candidate is not on the ballot or the social state is outside the production possibility curve). Arrow required that the voting rule that ''R'' and ''R' ''select the same (top-ranked) ''social choice'' from the feasible set (X, Y), and that this requirement holds no matter what the ranking is of infeasible ''Z'' relative to ''X'' and ''Y'' in the two sets of orderings. IIA does not allow "removing" an alternative from the available set (a candidate from the ballot), and it says nothing about what would happen in such a case: all options are assumed to be "feasible."


Examples


Borda count

In a
Borda count The Borda count is a family of positional voting rules which gives each candidate, for each ballot, a number of points corresponding to the number of candidates ranked lower. In the original variant, the lowest-ranked candidate gets 0 points, the ...
election, 5 voters rank 5 alternatives 'A'', ''B'', ''C'', ''D'', ''E'' 3 voters rank 'A''>''B''>''C''>''D''>''E'' 1 voter ranks 'C''>''D''>''E''>''B''>''A'' 1 voter ranks 'E''>''C''>''D''>''B''>''A'' Borda count (''a''=0, ''b''=1): ''C''=13, ''A''=12, ''B''=11, ''D''=8, ''E''=6. ''C'' wins. Now, the voter who ranks 'C''>''D''>''E''>''B''>''A''instead ranks 'C''>''B''>''E''>''D''>''A'' and the voter who ranks 'E''>''C''>''D''>''B''>''A''instead ranks 'E''>''C''>''B''>''D''>''A'' They change their preferences only over the pairs 'B'', ''D'' 'B'', ''E''and 'D'', ''E'' The new Borda count: ''B''=14, ''C''=13, ''A''=12, ''E''=6, ''D''=5. ''B'' wins. The social choice has changed the ranking of 'B'', ''A''and 'B'', ''C'' The changes in the social choice ranking are dependent on irrelevant changes in the preference profile. In particular, ''B'' now wins instead of ''C'', even though no voter changed their preference over 'B'', ''C''


=Borda count and strategic voting

= Consider an election in which there are three candidates, ''A'', ''B'', and ''C'', and only two voters. Each voter ranks the candidates in order of preference. The highest ranked candidate in a voter's preference is given 2 points, the second highest 1, and the lowest ranked 0; the overall ranking of a candidate is determined by the total score it gets; the highest ranked candidate wins. Considering two profiles: *In profiles 1 and 2, the first voter casts his votes in the order ''BAC'', so ''B'' receives 2 points, ''A'' receives 1, and ''C'' receives 0 from this voter. *In profile 1, the second voter votes ''ACB'', so ''A'' will win outright (the total scores: ''A'' 3, ''B'' 2, ''C'' 1). *In profile 2, the second voter votes ''ABC'', so ''A'' and ''B'' will tie (the total scores: ''A'' 3, ''B'' 3, ''C'' 0). Thus, if the second voter wishes ''A'' to be elected, he had better vote ''ACB'' regardless of his actual opinion of ''C'' and ''B''. This violates the idea of "independence from irrelevant alternatives" because the voter's comparative opinion of ''C'' and ''B'' affects whether ''A'' is elected or not. In both profiles, the rankings of ''A'' relative to ''B'' are the same for each voter, but the social rankings of ''A'' relative to ''B'' are different.


Copeland

This example shows that Copeland's method violates IIA. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D with 6 voters with the following preferences: The results would be tabulated as follows: * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the column caption to the one in the row caption * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the row caption to the one in the column caption Result: A has two wins and one defeat, while no other candidate has more wins than defeats. Thus, A is elected Copeland winner.


= Change of irrelevant preferences

= Now, assume all voters would raise D over B and C without changing the order of A and D. The preferences of the voters would now be: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: D wins against all three opponents. Thus, D is elected Copeland winner.


= Conclusion

= The voters changed only their preference orders over B, C and D. As a result, the outcome order of D and A changed. A turned from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, Copeland's method fails the IIA criterion.


Instant-runoff voting

In an instant-runoff election, 5 voters rank 3 alternatives 'A'', ''B'', ''C'' 2 voters rank 'A''>''B''>''C'' 2 voters rank 'C''>''B''>''A'' 1 voter ranks 'B''>''A''>''C'' Round 1: ''A''=2, ''B''=1, ''C''=2; ''B'' eliminated. Round 2: ''A''=3, ''C''=2; ''A'' wins. Now, the two voters who rank 'C''>''B''>''A''instead rank 'B''>''C''>''A'' They change only their preferences over ''B'' and ''C''. Round 1: ''A''=2, ''B''=3, ''C''=0; ''B'' wins with a majority of the vote. The social choice ranking of 'A'', ''B''is dependent on preferences over the irrelevant alternatives 'B'', ''C''


Kemeny–Young method

This example shows that the Kemeny–Young method violates the IIA criterion. Assume three candidates A, B and C with 7 voters and the following preferences: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: The ranking scores of all possible rankings are: Result: The ranking A > B > C has the highest ranking score. Thus, A wins ahead of B and C.


= Change of irrelevant preferences

= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > C > A would change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table: The ranking scores of all possible rankings are: Result: The ranking C > A > B has the highest ranking score. Thus, C wins ahead of A and B.


= Conclusion

= The two voters changed only their preferences over B and C, but this resulted in a change of the order of A and C in the result, turning A from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Kemeny-Young method fails the IIA criterion.


Minimax

This example shows that the Minimax method violates the IIA criterion. Assume four candidates A, B and C and 13 voters with the following preferences: Since all preferences are strict rankings (no equals are present), all three Minimax methods (winning votes, margins and pairwise opposite) elect the same winners. The results would be tabulated as follows: * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the column caption to the one in the row caption * indicates voters who preferred the candidate in the row caption to the one in the column caption Result: A has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, A is elected Minimax winner.


= Change of irrelevant preferences

= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > A > C change the preferences over the pair A and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The results would be tabulated as follows: Result: Now, B has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, B is elected Minimax winner.


= Conclusion

= So, by changing the order of A and C in the preferences of some voters, the order of A and B in the result changed. B is turned from loser to winner without any change of the voters' preferences regarding B. Thus, the Minimax method fails the IIA criterion.


Plurality voting system

In a plurality voting system 7 voters rank 3 alternatives (''A'', ''B'', ''C''). *3 voters rank (''A''>''B''>''C'') *2 voters rank (''B''>''A''>''C'') *2 voters rank (''C''>''B''>''A'') In an election, initially only ''A'' and ''B'' run: ''B'' wins with 4 votes to ''As 3, but the entry of ''C'' into the race makes ''A'' the new winner. The relative positions of ''A'' and ''B'' are reversed by the introduction of ''C'', an "irrelevant" alternative.


Ranked pairs

This example shows that the Ranked pairs method violates the IIA criterion. Assume three candidates A, B and C and 7 voters with the following preferences: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: A > B and B > C are locked in (and C > A cannot be locked in after that), so the full ranking is A > B > C. Thus, A is elected Ranked pairs winner.


= Change of irrelevant preferences

= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences B > C > A change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: The results would be tabulated as follows: The sorted list of victories would be: Result: All three duels are locked in, so the full ranking is C > A > B. Thus, the Condorcet winner C is elected Ranked pairs winner.


= Conclusion

= So, by changing their preferences over B and C, the two voters changed the order of A and C in the result, turning A from winner to loser without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Ranked pairs method fails the IIA criterion.


Schulze method

This example shows that the Schulze method violates the IIA criterion. Assume four candidates A, B, C and D and 12 voters with the following preferences: The pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified, e.g. the path D > A > B is stronger than the direct path D > B (which is nullified, since it is a tie). Result: The full ranking is C > D > A > B. Thus, C is elected Schulze winner and D is preferred over A.


= Change of irrelevant preferences

= Now, assume the two voters (marked bold) with preferences C > B > D > A change their preferences over the pair B and C. The preferences of the voters would then be in total: Hence, the pairwise preferences would be tabulated as follows: Now, the strongest paths have to be identified: Result: Now, the full ranking is A > B > C > D. Thus, A is elected Schulze winner and is preferred over D.


= Conclusion

= So, by changing their preferences over B and C, the two voters changed the order of A and D in the result, turning A from loser to winner without any change of the voters' preferences regarding A. Thus, the Schulze method fails the IIA criterion.


Two-round system

A probable example of the two-round system failing this criterion was the
2002 French presidential election Presidential elections were held in France on 21 April 2002, with a runoff election between the top two candidates, incumbent Jacques Chirac of the Rally for the Republic and Jean-Marie Le Pen of the National Front, on 5 May. This presidential ...
. Polls leading up to the election have suggested a runoff between centre-right candidate Jacques Chirac and centre-left candidate
Lionel Jospin Lionel Robert Jospin (; born 12 July 1937) is a French politician who served as Prime Minister of France from 1997 to 2002. Jospin was First Secretary of the Socialist Party from 1995 to 1997 and the party's candidate for President of France in ...
, in which Jospin has been expected to win. However, the first round was contested by an unprecedented 16 candidates, including left-wing candidates who intended to support Jospin in the runoff, eventually resulting in the far-right candidate,
Jean-Marie Le Pen Jean Louis Marie Le Pen (, born 20 June 1928) is a French far-right politician who served as President of the National Front from 1972 to 2011. He also served as Honorary President of the National Front from 2011 to 2015. Le Pen graduated fro ...
, finishing second and entering the runoff instead of Jospin, which Chirac won by a large margin. Thus, the presence of many candidates who did not intend to win in the election changed which of the candidates won.


Criticisms of the IIA assumption

IIA implies that adding another option or changing the characteristics of a third option does not affect the relative odds between the two options considered. This implication is not realistic for applications with similar options. Consider the Red Bus/Blue Bus example, due to Daniel McFadden. Commuter John Doe faces a decision between taking a car or a red bus. Suppose he chooses between these two options with equal probability on a given day (because of weather or whim). The odds ratio between car and red bus then equals 1:1. Now add a third alternative: blue bus. If Doe does not care about bus color, we would expect the probability of car to remain .5, while the probability of each of the two bus types would be 0.25. But IIA rules that out. It says that the new choice must not change the odds ratio of 1:1 between car and red bus. Since Doe's indifference to color requires the odds of red and blue bus to be equal, the new probabilities must be: car 0.33, red bus 0.33, blue bus 0.33. The overall probability of car travel has fallen from .5 to .33, which is absurd. The problem with the IIA axiom is that it takes no account of the fact that red bus and blue bus are perfect substitutes. The failure of this assumption has also been observed in practice, for example in the opinion polling for the 2019 European Elections held in the United Kingdom. In one survey, 21% of potential voters expressed support for the Labour Party under the scenario where there were three smaller Anti-Brexit parties to choose from, but under a scenario where two of those three parties did not stand candidates, the support for Labour dropped to 18%. This means at least 3% of potential voters stopped supporting their preferred party when a less preferred party dropped out.


In econometrics

IIA is a direct consequence of the assumptions underlying the
multinomial logit In statistics, multinomial logistic regression is a classification method that generalizes logistic regression to multiclass problems, i.e. with more than two possible discrete outcomes. That is, it is a model that is used to predict the prob ...
and the conditional logit models in
econometrics Econometrics is the application of statistical methods to economic data in order to give empirical content to economic relationships. M. Hashem Pesaran (1987). "Econometrics," '' The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics'', v. 2, p. 8 p. 8 ...
. If these models are used in situations which in fact violate independence (such as multicandidate elections in which preferences exhibit
cycling Cycling, also, when on a two-wheeled bicycle, called bicycling or biking, is the use of cycles for transport, recreation, exercise or sport. People engaged in cycling are referred to as "cyclists", "bicyclists", or "bikers". Apart from t ...
or situations mimicking the Red Bus/Blue Bus example given above) then these
estimators In statistics, an estimator is a rule for calculating an estimate of a given quantity based on observed data: thus the rule (the estimator), the quantity of interest (the estimand) and its result (the estimate) are distinguished. For example, the ...
become invalid. Many modeling advances have been motivated by a desire to alleviate the concerns raised by IIA. Generalized extreme value, multinomial probit (also called conditional probit) and mixed logit are models for nominal outcomes that relax IIA, but they often have assumptions of their own that may be difficult to meet or are computationally infeasible. IIA can be relaxed by specifying a hierarchical model, ranking the choice alternatives. The most popular of these is the
nested logit In economics, discrete choice models, or qualitative choice models, describe, explain, and predict choices between two or more discrete alternatives, such as entering or not entering the labor market, or choosing between modes of transport. Such ...
model. Generalized extreme value and multinomial probit models possess another property, the Invariant Proportion of Substitution,Steenburgh 2008 which suggests similarly counterintuitive individual choice behavior.


Choice under uncertainty

In the
expected utility The expected utility hypothesis is a popular concept in economics that serves as a reference guide for decisions when the payoff is uncertain. The theory recommends which option rational individuals should choose in a complex situation, based on the ...
theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern, four axioms together imply that individuals act in situations of risk as if they maximize the expected value of a
utility function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
. One of the axioms is an independence axiom analogous to the IIA axiom: :If \,L\prec M, then for any \,N and \,p\in(0,1], ::\,pL+(1-p)N \prec pM+(1-p)N, where ''p'' is a probability, ''pL''+(1-''p'')''N'' means a gamble with probability ''p'' of yielding ''L'' and probability (1-''p'') of yielding ''N'', and \,L\prec M means that ''M'' is preferred over ''L''. This axiom says that if one outcome (or lottery ticket) ''L'' is considered to be not as good as another (''M''), then having a chance with probability ''p'' of receiving ''L'' rather than ''N'' is considered to be not as good as having a chance with probability ''p'' of receiving ''M'' rather than ''N''.


In nature

Natural selection Natural selection is the differential survival and reproduction of individuals due to differences in phenotype. It is a key mechanism of evolution, the change in the heritable traits characteristic of a population over generations. Cha ...
can favor animals' non-IIA-type choices, thought to be due to occasional availability of foodstuffs, according to a study published in January 2014.


See also

*
Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives (ISDA, also known as Smith- IIA or Weak independence of irrelevant alternatives) is a voting system criterion defined such that its satisfaction by a voting system occurs when the selection of the win ...
*
Luce's choice axiom In probability theory, Luce's choice axiom, formulated by R. Duncan Luce (1959), states that the probability of selecting one item over another from a pool of many items is not affected by the presence or absence of other items in the pool. Selecti ...
* Sure-thing principle * Menu dependence ** Decoy effect ** Predictably Irrational#The Truth about Relativity


Footnotes


References

* * * * * Discusses and deduces the not always recognized differences between various formulations of IIA.


Further reading

* * {{voting systems Electoral system criteria Econometric modeling Social choice theory