Debreu theorems
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
economics Economics () is the social science that studies the production, distribution, and consumption of goods and services. Economics focuses on the behaviour and interactions of economic agents and how economies work. Microeconomics anal ...
, the Debreu theorems are several statements about the representation of a preference ordering by a real-valued function. The theorems were proved by Gerard Debreu during the 1950s.


Background

Suppose a person is asked questions of the form "Do you prefer A or B?" (when A and B can be options, actions to take, states of the world, consumption bundles, etc.). All the responses are recorded. Then, preferences of that person are represented by a numeric ''utility function'', such that the utility of option A is larger than option B if and only if the agent prefers A to B. The Debreu theorems come to answer the following basic question: what conditions on the preference relation of the agent guarantee that such representative utility function can be found?


Existence of ordinal utility function

The 1954 Theorems say, roughly, that every preference relation which is complete, transitive and continuous, can be represented by a continuous ordinal utility function.


Statement

The theorems are usually applied to spaces of finite commodities. However, they are applicable in a much more general setting. These are the general assumptions: * X is a
topological space In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called poin ...
. * \preceq is a relation on X which is total (all items are comparable) and transitive. * \preceq is ''continuous''. This means that the following equivalent conditions are satisfied: *# For every x\in X, the sets \ and \ are topologically closed in X. *# For every sequence (x_i) such that x_i \to x_\infty, if for all ''i'' x_i\preceq y then x_\infty\preceq y, and if for all ''i'' x_i\succeq y then x_\infty\succeq y Each one of the following conditions guarantees the existence of a real-valued continuous function that represents the preference relation \preceq. The conditions are increasingly general, so for example, condition 1 implies 2, which implies 3, which implies 4. 1. The set of
equivalence class In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
es of the relation \sim (defined by: x\sim y iff x\preceq y and x\succeq y) are a
countable set In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numb ...
. 2. There is a countable subset of X, Z=\, such that for every pair of non-equivalent elements x\prec y, there is an element z_i\in Z that separates them (x\preceq z_i \preceq y). 3. X is separable and connected. 4. X is
second countable In topology, a second-countable space, also called a completely separable space, is a topological space whose topology has a countable base. More explicitly, a topological space T is second-countable if there exists some countable collection \ma ...
. This means that there is a
countable set In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numb ...
S of open sets, such that every open set in X is the union of sets of the class S. The proof for the fourth result had a gap which Debreu later corrected.


Examples

A. Let X=\mathbb^2 with the standard topology (the Euclidean topology). Define the following preference relation: (x,y)\preceq (x',y') iff x+y \leq x'+y'. It is continuous because for every (x,y), the sets \ and \ are closed half-planes. Condition 1 is violated because the set of equivalence classes is uncountable. However, condition 2 is satisfied with Z as the set of pairs with rational coordinates. Condition 3 is also satisfied since X is separable and connected. Hence, there exists a continuous function which represents \preceq. An example of such function is u(x,y)=x+y. B. Let X=\mathbb^2 with the standard topology as above. The
lexicographic preferences In economics, lexicographic preferences or lexicographic orderings describe comparative preferences where an agent prefers any amount of one good (X) to any amount of another (Y). Specifically, if offered several bundles of goods, the agent will ch ...
relation is not continuous in that topology. For example, (5,1)\succ (5,0), but in every ball around (5,1) there are points with x<5 and these points are inferior to (5,0). Indeed, this relation cannot be represented by a continuous real-valued function.


Proofs

Proofs from. Notation: for any x, y \in X, define (x, y) = \, and similarly define other intervals.


Extensions

Diamond applied Debreu's theorem to the space X=\ell^\infty, the set of all bounded real-valued sequences with the topology induced by the supremum metric (see
L-infinity In mathematics, \ell^\infty, the (real or complex) vector space of bounded sequences with the supremum norm, and L^\infty = L^\infty(X,\Sigma,\mu), the vector space of essentially bounded measurable functions with the essential supremum norm, ar ...
). X represents the set of all utility streams with infinite horizon. In addition to the requirement that \preceq be total, transitive and continuous, He added a ''sensitivity'' requirement: * If a stream x is smaller than a stream y in every time period, then x\prec y. * If a stream x is smaller-than-or-equal-to a stream y in every time period, then x\preceq y. Under these requirements, every stream x is equivalent to a constant-utility stream, and every two constant-utility streams are separable by a constant-utility stream with a rational utility, so condition #2 of Debreu is satisfied, and the preference relation can be represented by a real-valued function. The existence result is valid even when the topology of X is changed to the topology induced by the discounted metric: d(x,y)=\sum_^\infty


Additivity of ordinal utility function

Theorem 3 of 1960 says, roughly, that if the commodity space contains 3 or more components, and every subset of the components is preferentially-independent of the other components, then the preference relation can be represented by an ''additive'' value function.


Statement

These are the general assumptions: * X, the space of all bundles, is a cartesian product of ''n'' commodity spaces: X = \times_^n (i.e., the space of bundles is a set of ''n''-tuples of commodities). * \preceq is a relation on X which is total (all items are comparable) and transitive. * \preceq is continuous (see above). * There exists an
ordinal utility In economics, an ordinal utility function is a function representing the preferences of an agent on an ordinal scale. Ordinal utility theory claims that it is only meaningful to ask which option is better than the other, but it is meaningless to ...
function, v, representing \preceq. The function v is called ''additive'' if it can be written as a sum of ''n'' ordinal utility functions on the ''n'' factors: ::::v(x_1,...,x_n)=\sum_^n where the k_i are constants. Given a set of indices I, the set of commodities (X_i)_ is called ''preferentially independent'' if the preference relation \preceq induced on (X_i)_, given constant quantities of the other commodities (X_i)_, does not depend on these constant quantities. If v is additive, then obviously all subsets of commodities are preferentially-independent. If all subsets of commodities are preferentially-independent AND at least three commodities are essential (meaning that their quantities have an influence on the preference relation \preceq), then v is additive. Moreover, in that case v is unique up to an increasing ''linear'' transformation. For an intuitive constructive proof, see Ordinal utility - Additivity with three or more goods.


Theorems on Cardinal utility

Theorem 1 of 1960 deals with preferences on lotteries. It can be seen as an improvement to the
von Neumann–Morgenstern utility theorem In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem shows that, under certain axioms of rational behavior, a decision-maker faced with risky (probabilistic) outcomes of different choices will behave as if he or she is maximizin ...
of 1947. The earlier theorem assumes that agents have preferences on lotteries with arbitrary probabilities. Debreu's theorem weakens this assumption and assumes only that agents have preferences on equal-chance lotteries (i.e., they can only answer questions of the form: "Do you prefer A over an equal-chance lottery between B and C?"). Formally, there is a set S of sure choices. The set of lotteries is S\times S. Debreu's theorem states that if: # The set of all sure choices S is a connected and
separable space In mathematics, a topological space is called separable if it contains a countable, dense subset; that is, there exists a sequence \_^ of elements of the space such that every nonempty open subset of the space contains at least one element of th ...
; # The preference relation on the set of lotteries S\times S is continuous - the sets \ and \ are topologically closed for all (A,B)\in S; # (A_1,B_2)\preceq (A_2,B_1) and (A_2,B_3)\preceq (A_3,B_2) implies (A_1,B_3)\preceq (A_3,B_1) Then there exists a
cardinal utility In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations. Two utility indices are related by an affine transformation if for the value u(x_i) of one i ...
function ''u'' that represents the preference relation on the set of lotteries, i.e.: :::u(A,B) = (u(A,A)+u(B,B))/2 Theorem 2 of 1960 deals with agents whose preferences are represented by frequency-of-choice. When they can choose between ''A'' and ''B'', they choose ''A'' with frequency p(A,B) and ''B'' with frequency p(B,A)=1-p(A,B). The value p(A,B) can be interpreted as measuring ''how much'' the agent prefers ''A'' over ''B''. Debreu's theorem states that if the agent's function ''p'' satisfies the following conditions: # Completeness: p(A,B)+p(B,A)=1 # Quadruple Condition: p(A,B)\leq p(C,D) \iff p(A,C)\leq p(B,D) # Continuity: if p(A,B)\leq q\leq p(A,D), then there exists ''C'' such that: p(A,C)=q. Then there exists a cardinal utility function ''u'' that represents ''p'', i.e: :::p(A,B)\leq p(C,D) \iff u(A)-u(B)\leq u(C)-u(D).


See also

*
Von Neumann–Morgenstern utility theorem In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem shows that, under certain axioms of rational behavior, a decision-maker faced with risky (probabilistic) outcomes of different choices will behave as if he or she is maximizin ...


References

{{reflist Utility Economics theorems