HOME
The Info List - Cosmopolitanism


--- Advertisement ---



Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
is the ideology that all human beings belong to a single community, based on a shared morality. A person who adheres to the idea of cosmopolitanism in any of its forms is called a cosmopolitan or cosmopolite. A cosmopolitan community might be based on an inclusive morality, a shared economic relationship, or a political structure that encompasses different nations. In a cosmopolitan community individuals from different places (e.g. nation-states) form relationships of mutual respect. As an example, Kwame Anthony Appiah
Kwame Anthony Appiah
suggests the possibility of a cosmopolitan community in which individuals from varying locations (physical, economic, etc.) enter relationships of mutual respect despite their differing beliefs (religious, political, etc.).[1] Various cities and locales, past or present, have been or are defined as "cosmopolitan"; that does not necessarily mean that all or most of their inhabitants consciously embrace the above philosophy. Rather, locales could be defined as "cosmopolitan" simply by the fact of being where people of various ethnic, cultural and/or religious background live in proximity and interact with each other.

Contents

1 Etymology 2 Definitions 3 Philosophical

3.1 Philosophical roots 3.2 Modern cosmopolitan thinkers 3.3 Contemporary cosmopolitan thinkers

4 Political and sociological 5 Political rhetoric 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 External links

Etymology[edit] The word derives from the Ancient Greek: κοσμοπολίτης, or kosmopolitês, formed from "κόσμος", kosmos, i.e. "world", "universe", or "cosmos", and πολίτης, "politês", i.e. "citizen" or "[one] of a city". Contemporary usage defines the term as "citizen of the world".[2][3] Definitions[edit] Definitions of cosmopolitanism usually begin with the Greek etymology of "citizen of the world". However, as Appiah points out, "world" in the original sense meant "cosmos" or "universe", not earth or globe as current use assumes.[4] One definition that handles this issue is given in a recent book on political globalization:

Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
can be defined as a global politics that, firstly, projects a sociality of common political engagement among all human beings across the globe, and, secondly, suggests that this sociality should be either ethically or organizationally privileged over other forms of sociality.[5]

Philosophical[edit] Further information: Global justice and Moral universalism Philosophical roots[edit]

Diogenes

Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
can be traced back to Diogenes of Sinope
Diogenes of Sinope
(c. 412 B.C.), the founding father of the Cynic movement in Ancient Greece. Of Diogenes it is said: "Asked where he came from, he answered: 'I am a citizen of the world (kosmopolitês)'".[6] In Ancient Greece, the broadest basis of social identity in at that time was either the individual city-state or the Greeks (Hellenes) as a group. The Stoics, who later took Diogenes' idea and developed the idea, typically stressed that each human being "dwells [...] in two communities – the local community of our birth, and the community of human argument and aspiration".[7] A common way to understand Stoic cosmopolitanism is through Hierocles' circle model of identity that states that we should regard ourselves as concentric circles, the first one around the self, next immediate family, extended family, local group, citizens, countrymen, humanity. Within these circles human beings feel a sense of "affinity" or "endearment" towards others, which the Stoics termed Oikeiôsis. The task of world citizens becomes then to "draw the circles somehow towards the centre, making all human beings more like our fellow city dwellers, and so forth".[7]:9 Modern cosmopolitan thinkers[edit]

Immanuel Kant, who argued for a ius cosmopoliticum

In his 1795 essay Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, Immanuel Kant stages a ius cosmopoliticum (cosmopolitan law/right) as a guiding principle to protect people from war, and morally grounds this cosmopolitan right by the principle of universal hospitality. Kant there claimed that the expansion of hospitality with regard to "use of the right to the earth's surface which belongs to the human race in common" (see common heritage of humanity) would "finally bring the human race ever closer to a cosmopolitan constitution".[8] The philosophical concepts of Emmanuel Levinas, on ethics, and Jacques Derrida, on hospitality, provide a theoretical framework for the relationships between people in their everyday lives and apart from any form of written laws or codes. For Levinas, the foundation of ethics consists in the obligation to respond to the Other. In Being for the Other, he writes that there is no "universal moral law," only the sense of responsibility (goodness, mercy, charity) that the Other, in a state of vulnerability, calls forth. The proximity of the Other is an important part of Levinas's concept: the face of the Other is what compels the response. For Derrida, the foundation of ethics is hospitality, the readiness and the inclination to welcome the Other into one's home. Ethics, he claims, is hospitality. Pure, unconditional hospitality is a desire that underscores the conditional hospitality necessary in our relationships with others. Levinas's and Derrida's theories of ethics and hospitality hold out the possibility of an acceptance of the Other as different but of equal standing. Isolation is not a feasible alternative in the world, therefore, it is important to consider how best to approach these interactions, and to determine what is at stake for ourselves and the others: what conditions of hospitality to impose, and whether or not we have responded to the call of the Other. Further, both theories reveal the importance of considering how best to interact with the Other and others, and what is at stake. Derrida in an interview with Bennington (1997) summarized "cosmopolitanism",[9]

There is a tradition of cosmopolitanism, and if we had time we could study this tradition, which comes to us from, on the one hand, Greek thought with the Stoics, who have a concept of the 'citizen of the world'. You also have St. Paul in the Christian tradition, also a certain call for a citizen of the world as, precisely, a brother. St. Paul says that we are all brothers, that is sons of God, so we are not foreigners, we belong to the world as citizens of the world; and it is this tradition that we could follow up until Kant for instance, in whose concept of cosmopolitanism we find the conditions for hospitality. But in the concept of the cosmopolitical in Kant there are a number of conditions: first of all you should, of course, welcome the stranger, the foreigner, to the extent that he is a citizen of another country, that you grant him the right to visit and not to stay, and there are a number of other conditions that I can't summarise here quickly, but this concept of the cosmopolitical which is very novel, very worthy of respect (and I think cosmopolitanism is a very good thing), is a very limited concept. (Derrida cited in Bennington 1997). — Bennington. Politics and Friendship: A Discussion with Jacques Derrida. 1997.

A further state of cosmopolitanism occurred after the Second World War. As a reaction to the Holocaust
Holocaust
and the other massacres, the concept of crimes against humanity became a generally accepted category in international law. This clearly shows the appearance and acceptance of a notion of individual responsibility that is considered to exist toward all of humankind.[10] Philosophical cosmopolitans are moral universalists: they believe that all humans, and not merely compatriots or fellow-citizens, come under the same moral standards. The boundaries between nations, states, cultures or societies are therefore morally irrelevant. A widely cited example of a contemporary cosmopolitan is Kwame Anthony Appiah.[11] Some philosophers and scholars argue that the objective and subjective conditions arising in today's unique historical moment, an emerging planetary phase of civilization, creates a latent potential for the emergence of a cosmopolitan identity as global citizens and possible formation of a global citizens movement.[12] These emerging objective and subjective conditions in the planetary phase include improved and affordable telecommunications; space travel and the first images of our fragile planet floating in the vastness of space; the emergence of global warming and other ecological threats to our collective existence; new global institutions such as the United Nations, World Trade Organization, or International Criminal Court; the rise of transnational corporations and integration of markets often termed economic globalization; the emergence of global NGOs and transnational social movements, such as the World Social Forum; and so on. Globalization, a more common term, typically refers more narrowly to the economic and trade relations and misses the broader cultural, social, political, environmental, demographic, values and knowledge transitions taking place. Contemporary cosmopolitan thinkers[edit]

This section may require cleanup to meet's quality standards. No cleanup reason has been specified. Please help improve this section if you can. (February 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)

A number of contemporary theorists propose, directly and indirectly, various ways of becoming or being a cosmopolitan individual. Thich Nhat Hanh
Thich Nhat Hanh
discusses what he calls "Interbeing" as a way of living one's life in relation to others; "Interbeing" might easily be compared to cosmopolitanism. Nhat Hanh's philosophical beliefs are grounded in the precepts of Buddhist
Buddhist
teachings, which involve compassion and understanding to protect and live in harmony with all people, animals, plants, and minerals.[13]:88 He further describes what he calls "Mindfulness Training of the Order of Interbeing" as being aware of sufferings created by, but not limited to, the following causes: fanaticism and intolerances that disrupt compassion and living in harmony with others; indoctrination of narrow-minded beliefs; imposition of views; anger; and miscommunication.[13]:89–95 Understanding and compassion for others seems to be achieved by the understanding of others' suffering and the root causes of suffering. Therefore, to be responsible is to recognize and understand suffering, which then leads to compassion. It is through this process that others can be recognized as people. Other theorists, philosophers, and activists contend that recognizing suffering is necessary to end violence. In Scared Sacred, Velcrow Ripper takes a journey to different sites of great suffering that ultimately leads him toward developing compassion.[14] In "The Planet", Paul Gilroy
Paul Gilroy
explores how the construction and naturalization of race and the hierarchies produced by difference shape the hatred of others. It is the deconstruction of these ideologies that can lead to the compassion and humanization of others. Thus individual responsibility is being aware of what Judith Butler
Judith Butler
calls the precariousness of life in self and other; being a cosmopolitan seems to be, above all, a social, ethical enterprise. In Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, Kwame Anthony Appiah notices something important about how social ethics seem to operate: Whatever obligation one might have to another, especially a foreign other, that obligation does not supersede the obligations one has to those people most familiar to them. However, as Judith Butler questions, "at what cost do I establish the familiar as the criterion" for valuing others?[15] If one values the familiar more than the foreign, what are the consequences? Paul Gilroy
Paul Gilroy
offers a possible alternative to this emphasis on familiarity arguing that "methodical cultivation of a degree of estrangement from one's own culture and history ... might qualify as essential to a cosmopolitan commitment."[16]:67 This estrangement entails a "process of exposure to otherness" in order to foster "the irreducible value of diversity within sameness."[16]:67 Estrangement, therefore, could lead to de-emphasising the familiar in ethics by integrating otherness. For Gilroy, being cosmopolitan seems to involve both a social, ethical enterprise and a cultural enterprise. In "The Planet", Gilroy describes the cases of Tom Hurndall and Rachel Corrie;[16]:80–81 each seems to exemplify what might be considered Gilroy's figure of the cosmopolitan. Both Hurndall and Corrie removed themselves (geographically) from their home cultures, presumably both physically and mentally estranging themselves from their own cultures and histories. Interestingly, though, Hurndall and Corrie were both killed in 2003 (in separate incidents) and their stories might serve as affirmations of familiarity, rather than models of estrangement. Gilroy’s model of estrangement might actually undermine itself through its examples; this might be construed as a failure of Gilroy’s theory to address the practical difficulties of estranging oneself from the familiar.[16] The Venus Project, an international, multidisciplinary educational organization created by Jacque Fresco, works to spread cosmopolitan ideas by transcending artificial boundaries currently separating people and emphasizing an understanding our interdependence with nature and each other.

Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
is a broader concept than world government[citation needed]

Some forms of cosmopolitanism also fail to address the potential for economic colonization by powerful countries over less powerful ones.[citation needed] Frantz Fanon, in The Wretched of the Earth, observes that when nations achieved independence from European colonizers, frequently there was no system in place to secure their economic future, and they became "manager[s] for Western enterprise...in practise set[ting] up its country as the brothel of Europe."[17]:154 When "third world" nations are drawn into economic partnerships with global capital, ostensibly to improve their national quality of life, often the only ones benefitting from this partnership are well-placed individuals and not the nation itself. Further, Mahmood Mamdani in Good Muslim, Bad Muslim suggests that the imposition of Western cultural norms, democracy and Christianity
Christianity
to name only two, has historically resulted in nationalist violence;[18] however, Appiah has implied that democracy is a pre-requisite for cosmopolitan intervention in developing nations.[19]:169[20] Cosmopolitanism, in these instances, appears to be a new form of colonization: the powerful exploit the weak and the weak eventually fight back.[citation needed] Much of the political thinking of the last two centuries has taken nationalism and the framework of the sovereign nation-state for granted. Now, with the advance of globalization and the increased facility of travel and communication, some thinkers consider that the political system based on the nation-state has become obsolete and that it is time to design a better and more efficient alternative. Jesús Mosterín
Jesús Mosterín
analyzes how the world political system should be organized in order to maximize individual freedom and individual opportunity. Rejecting as muddled the metaphysical notion of free will, he focuses on political freedom, the absence of coercion or interference by others in personal decisions. Because of the tendencies to violence and aggression that lurk in human nature, some constraint on freedom is necessary for peaceful and fruitful social interaction, but the more freedom we enjoy, the better.[21] Especially, there is no rational ground for curtailing the cultural freedoms (of language, religion and customs) in the name of the nation, the church, or the party. From this point of view, the Internet
Internet
provides a much more attractive model than the nation-state. Neither is there any just reason for restraining the free circulation of people, ideas, or goods. Mosterín thinks that the nation-state is incompatible with the full development of freedom, whose blossoming requires the reorganization of the world political system along cosmopolitan lines. He proposes a world without sovereign nation-states, territorially organized in small autonomous but not-sovereign cantonal polities, complemented by strong world organizations.[22] He emphasizes the difference between international institutions, led by representatives of the national governments, and world or universal institutions, with clearly defined aims served by directors selected by their personal qualifications, independently of any national bias or proportion. Criticizing the abstract nature of most versions of cosmopolitanism, Charles Blattberg has argued that any viable cosmopolitanism must be "rooted," by which he means based upon a "global patriotism."[23] More general philosophical reviews of cosmopolitanism and multiculturalism are also available. Carol Nicholson compares the John Searle's opposition to multiculturalism with Charles Taylor's celebration of it. She uses Richard Rorty
Richard Rorty
as a triangulation point in that he remains neutral about multiculturalism, but his philosophical analysis of truth and practice can be deployed to argue against Searle and in favor of Taylor.[24] At a conference on "Philosophy in a Multicultural Context", Rasmus Winther excavated the philosophical assumptions and practices connected with cosmopolitanism and multiculturalism. He develops Bruno Latour's conception of the philosopher as public diplomat.[25] Political and sociological[edit] Emile Durkheim
Emile Durkheim
(1858–1917) observed the development of what he called the 'cult of the individual', which is a new religion that replaced the Christianity
Christianity
that was dying out, and which is centered around the sacredness of human dignity. This new religion would provide the new foundations of Western society, and these foundations are closely related to human rights and individual nation's constitutions. A society's sacred object would be the individual's human dignity, and the moral code guiding the society is found in that country's way of interpreting human dignity and human rights. Thus, rather than finding solidarity through national culture, or a particular traditional religious doctrine, society would be unified by its adherence to political values, i.e. individual rights and a defence of human dignity.[26] Durkheim's cult of the individual has many similarities to John Rawls' political liberalism, which Rawls developed almost a century after Durkheim.[27] Ulrich Beck
Ulrich Beck
(May 15, 1944 – January 1, 2015) was a sociologist who posed the new concept of cosmopolitan critical theory in direct opposition to traditional nation-state politics. Nation-state
Nation-state
theory sees power relations only among different state actors, and excludes a global economy, or subjugates it to the nation-state model. Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
sees global capital as a possible threat to the nation state and places it within a meta-power game in which global capital, states and civil society are its players. It is important to mark a distinction between Beck's cosmopolitanism and the idea of a world state. For Beck, imposing a single world order was considered hegemonic at best and ethnocentric at worst. Rather, political and sociological cosmopolitanism rests upon these fundamental foundations:

"Acknowledging the otherness of those who are culturally different" "Acknowledging the otherness of the future" "Acknowledging the otherness of nature" "Acknowledging the otherness of the object" "Acknowledging the otherness of other rationalities"

A number of philosophers, including Emmanuel Levinas, have introduced the concept of the "Other". For Levinas, the Other is given context in ethics and responsibility; we should think of the Other as anyone and everyone outside ourselves. According to Levinas, our initial interactions with the Other occur before we form a will—the ability to make choices. The Other addresses us and we respond: even the absence of response is a response. We are thus conditioned by the Other's address and begin to form culture and identity. After the formation of the will, we choose whether to identify with the addresses by others and, as a result, continue the process of forming identity.[28] During this process, it is possible to recognize ourselves in our interactions with Others. Even in situations where we engage in the most minimal interaction, we ascribe identities to others and simultaneously to ourselves. Our dependence on the Other for the continuous formation of language, culture, and identity means that we are responsible to others and that they are responsible to us. Also once we've formed a will, it becomes possible to recognize this social interdependence. When we have gained the capacity for recognition, the imperative is to perform that recognition and thereby become ethically responsible to the Other in conscience.[28] Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
shares some aspects of universalism – namely the globally acceptable notion of human dignity that must be protected and enshrined in international law. However, the theory deviates in recognising the differences between world cultures.[29] In addition, cosmopolitanism calls for equal protection of the environment and against the negative side effects of technological development. Human dignity, however, is convoluted because it is necessary to first distinguish who has the right to be respected and second to consider what rights are protectable. Under cosmopolitanism, all humans have rights; however, history shows that recognition of these rights is not guaranteed.[citation needed] As an example, Judith Butler
Judith Butler
discusses a Western discourse of "human" in Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence. Butler works through the idea of "human" and notes that "human" has been "naturalized in its 'Western' mold by the contemporary workings of humanism" (32). Thus, there is the idea that not all "human" lives will be supported in the same way, indeed, that some human lives are worth more protection than others. Others have extended this idea to examine how animals might be reconfigured as cosmopolitan, present the world-over with varying identities in different places.[30] This idea is reiterated in Sunera Thobani's "Nationality in the Age of Global Terror,"[citation needed] where she discusses a discourse in which Muslim people
Muslim people
fall into a good/bad dichotomy: a "good Muslim" is one who has been Westernized and a "bad Muslim" is one who visibly rejects Western cultural influences. Thobani notes that it is through media representations that these ideas become naturalized. Individuals who embrace Western ideals are considered fully "human" and are more likely to be afforded dignity and protection than those who defend their non-Westernized cultural identities. According to those who follow Beck's reasoning, a cosmopolitan world would consist of a plurality of states, which would use global and regional consensus to gain greater bargaining power against opponents. States would also utilize the power of civil society actors such as Non-governmental organizations (NGOs) and consumers to strengthen their legitimacy and enlist the help of investors to pursue a cosmopolitan agenda.[citation needed] Other authors imagine a cosmopolitan world moving beyond today's conception of nation-states. These scholars argue that a truly cosmopolitan identity of Global Citizen
Global Citizen
will take hold, diminishing the importance of national identities. The formation of a global citizens movement would lead to the establishment of democratic global institutions, creating the space for global political discourse and decisions, would in turn reinforce the notion of citizenship at a global level. Nested structures of governance balancing the principles of irreducibility (i.e., the notion that certain problems can only be addressed at the global level, such as global warming) and subsidiarity (i.e., the notion that decisions should be made at as local a level possible) would thus form the basis for a cosmopolitan political order.[31] Daniele Archibugi
Daniele Archibugi
proposes a renewed model for global citizenship:[32] institutional cosmopolitanism. It advocates some reforms in global governance to allow world citizens to take more directly a part into political life. A number of proposals have been made in order to make this possible. Cosmopolitan democracy, for example, suggests strengthening the United Nations
United Nations
and other international organizations by creating a World Parliamentary Assembly.[33] Political rhetoric[edit] Further information: Rootless cosmopolitan "Cosmopolitanism" became a rhetorical weapon used by nationalists against "alien" ideas that went counter to orthodoxy. European Jews were frequently accused of being "rootless cosmopolitans."[34] Joseph Stalin in a 1946 Moscow speech attacked writings in which “the positive Soviet hero is derided and inferior before all things foreign and cosmopolitanism that we all fought against from the time of Lenin, characteristic of the political leftovers, is many times applauded.”[35] In the 21st century the epithet became a weapon used by Vladimir Putin
Vladimir Putin
in Russia, and by nationalists in Hungary and Poland.[36] In modern times, Stephen Miller, a Trump administration senior policy advisor, has publicly criticized CNN reported Jim Acosta as exhibiting "cosmopolitan bias" during a discussion on the government's new immigration plan.[37] See also[edit]

Philosophy portal

Anarchism Anti-nationalism Anti-patriotism Antisemitism Cosmopolitan (other) Cross-culturalism Cultural universal Democratic globalization Europeanism Eurasianism Evolutionary ethics Existential migration Flag of Earth Global citizenship Global justice Human rights Humanism Interculturalism Internationalism (politics) Liberalism Libertarianism Multiculturalism Patriotism Rootless cosmopolitan Transculturation United Nations
United Nations
Parliamentary Assembly Vasudhaiva Kutumbakam

Notes[edit]

^ Anthony Appiah, Kwame (1997). "Cosmopolitan Patriots". Critical Inquiry. 23 (3): 617–39. doi:10.1086/448846.  ^ κοσμοπολίτης. Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert; A Greek–English Lexicon at the Perseus Project. ^ "cosmopolitan".  "cosmopolite". Online Etymology Dictionary.  ^ Kwame Anthony Appiah, Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, W.W. Norton, New York, 2006, p. xiv. ^ James, Paul (2014). Globalization
Globalization
and Politics, Vol. 4: Political Philosophies of the Global. London: Sage Publications. p. x.  ^ Diogenes Laertius, The Lives of Eminent Philosophers, Book VI, passage 63; online text in Greek and in English at the Perseus Project. ^ a b Nussbaum, Martha C. (1997). Kant and Stoic Cosmopolitanism, in The Journal of Political Philosophy Volume 5, Nr 1, pp. 1–25 ^ Immanuel Kant. 'Toward Perpetual Peace' in Practical Philosophy – Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Gregor MJ (trans.). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 1999. p329 (8:358). ^ Bennington, Geoffrey (1 December 1997). "Politics and Friendship: A Discussion with Jacques Derrida". Sussex, UK: Centre for Modern French Thought, University of Sussex. Retrieved 16 July 2012.  ^ Beck, Ulrich (2006). The Cosmopolitan Vision, Cambridge: Polity Press, p. 45 ^ Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2006), Cosmopolitanism. Ethics in a World of Strangers, London: Penguin Books ^ GTI Paper Series Archived 2008-02-11 at the Wayback Machine. see Dawn of the Cosmopolitan: The Hope of a Global Citizens Movement, paper #15, and Global Politics and Institutions, paper #3 ^ a b Nhất Hạnh, Thich (1996) [1987]. Kotler, Arnold, ed. Being Peace. Illustrations by Mayumi Oda. Berkeley: Parallax. ISBN 0-938077-97-X. OCLC 36745774.  ^ Ripper, Velcrow (director) (2004). Scared Sacred (Film). National Filmboard of Canada.  ^ Butler, Judith (2004). Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence. New York: Verso. p. 38. ISBN 978-1-84467-005-5. OCLC 803802111.  ^ a b c d Gilroy, Paul (2004). "The Planet". After Empire: Multiculture or Postcolonial Melancholia. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-34307-7. OCLC 56454095.  ^ Fanon, Frantz (1963). "The Pitfalls of National Consciousness". The Wretched of the Earth. Translated by Farrington, Constance. New York: Grove Press. pp. 148–205. ISBN 0-8021-5083-7. OCLC 817260777.  ^ Mamdani, Mahmood (2004). Good Muslim, Bad Muslim: America, the Cold War, and the Roots of Terror (1st ed.). New York: Pantheon Books. ISBN 978-0-375-42285-0. OCLC 53315228.  ^ Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2006). "Kindness to Strangers". Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers. Issues of our time (1st ed.). New York: W. W. Norton and Co. pp. 155–174. ISBN 978-0-393-06155-0. OCLC 475363652.  ^ Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2006). "Moral Disagreement". Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers. Issues of our time (1st ed.). New York: W. W. Norton and Co. pp. 45–68. ISBN 978-0-393-06155-0. OCLC 475363652.  ^ Mosterín, Jesús (2008). La cultura de la libertad (in Spanish). Madrid: Espasa-Calpe. ISBN 978-84-670-2697-9. OCLC 693823808.  ^ Mosterín, Jesús (2005). "A World without Nation States". Acta Institutionis Philosophiae et Aestheticae. Tokyo. 23: 55–77.  ^ Blattberg, Charles (5 April 2012). "We Are All Compatriots". In Kymlicka, Will; Walker, Kathryn. Rooted Cosmopolitanism. Vancouver: UBC Press. ISBN 978-0-7748-2262-6. OCLC 886376838. SSRN 2034932  – via Social Science Research Network.  ^ Nicholson, Carol (1998). Three Views of Philosophy and Multiculturalism: Searle, Rorty, and Taylor. Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy.  ^ Winther, Rasmus Grønfeldt (2012). Free to Universalize or Bound by Culture? Multicultural and Public Philosophy (PDF) (White Paper).  ^ Durkheim, Emile. " Individualism
Individualism
and Individuals": Originally published as "L'individualisme et les intellectuels," Revue bleue, 4e serie, 10 (1898): 7-13. Translated by Mark Traugott. Article accessed: https://www.scribd.com/document/85771137/Durkheim-Individualism-and-the-Intellectuals ^ See Cladis, Mark. 'A Communitarian Defense of Liberalism: Emile Durkheim and Contemporary Social Theory' (Stanford University Press: Stanford, 1992). ^ a b Emmanuel Levinas. Totality and Infinity. An Essay on Exteriority. Lingis A (trans) Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh, PA 1998. pp. 84, 100–01 ^ Stojadinović, Mladen (2014). "UNIVERSALISM REVIVED: NEEDS-BASED COSMOPOLITANISM AS A FOUNDATION OF GLOBAL DEMOCRACY". 13: 78–80. Retrieved 18 April 2017.  ^ Barua, Maan (2013). "Circulating Elephants: Unpacking the Geographies of a Cosmopolitan Animal". Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers. 0. Retrieved 21 December 2013.  ^ GTI Paper Series Archived 2008-02-11 at the Wayback Machine. see Global Politics and Institutions, paper #3 ^ Daniele Archibugi, The Global Commonwealth of Citizens: Toward a Cosmopolitan Democracy, Princeton University Press, 2009. ^ Daniele Archibugi, Debating Cosmopolitics, London: Verso, 2003. ^ Michael L. Miller and Scott Ury, "Cosmopolitanism: the end of Jewishness?" European Review of History—Revue européenne d'histoire 17.3 (2010): 337-359 abstract. ^ Jeff Greenfield, "The Ugly History of Stephen Miller’s ‘Cosmopolitan’ Epithet: Surprise, surprise—the insult has its roots in Soviet anti-Semitism." Politico 3 August, 2017 ^ Jeff Greenfield, "The Ugly History of Stephen Miller’s ‘Cosmopolitan’ Epithet" ^ "What 'Cosmopolitan Bias' Really Means". citylab.com. Retrieved 22 October 2017. 

References[edit]

Anderson, Amanda (1998). "Cosmopolitanism, Universalism, and the Divided Legacies of Modernity". In Cheah, Pheng; Robbins, Bruce. Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling beyond the Nation. Cultural Politics. 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 0-8166-3067-4. OCLC 875672972.  Ankerl, Guy (2000). Global communication without universal civilization. INU societal research. Geneva: INU Press. ISBN 2-88155-004-5. OCLC 50042854.  Archibugi, Daniele; Held, David, eds. (1995). Cosmopolitan Democracy. An Agenda for a New World Order. Cambridge: Polity Press. ISBN 0-7456-1381-0. OCLC 801020025.  Beck, Ulrich (2005). Power in the Global Age. Translated by Cross, Kathleen. Cambridge: Polity Press. ISBN 978-0-7456-3230-8. OCLC 60965050.  Brock, Gillian; Brighouse, Harry (2005). The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-84660-8. OCLC 470712082.  Cotesta, Vittorio (2012). "Global Society, Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
and Human Rights". Global Society
Society
and Human Rights. International Comparative Social Studies. 18. Translated by D'Auria, Matthew. Leiden: Brill. pp. 151–164. doi:10.1163/9789004225633_010. ISBN 978-90-04-22563-3. (Subscription required (help)).  Caney, Simon (2010). "Cosmopolitanism". In Bell, Duncan. Ethics and World Politics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954862-0. OCLC 781324049.  Delanty, Gerard, ed. Routledge Handbook of Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
Studies (2012). Kleingeld, Pauline; Brown, Eric. "Cosmopolitanism". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Fall 2002 ed.).  Martell, Luke (2011). " Cosmopolitanism
Cosmopolitanism
and Global Politics" (PDF). Political Quarterly. 82 (4): 618–627. doi:10.1111/j.1467-923X.2011.02237.x.  Miller, Michael L.; Ury, Scott (eds.). Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism and the Jews of East Central Europe. Oxon: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-01852-5. OCLC 901035778.  Miller, Michael L., and Scott Ury. "Cosmopolitanism: the end of Jewishness?" European Review of History—Revue européenne d'histoire 17.3 (2010): 337-359. abstract Palmer, Tom G. (2008). "Cosmopolitanism". In Hamowy, Ronald. The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE; Cato Institute. pp. 107–09. doi:10.4135/9781412965811.n68. ISBN 978-1-4129-6580-4. LCCN 2008009151. OCLC 750831024.  Robbins, Bruce (1998). "Comparative Cosmopolitanisms". In Cheah, Pheng; Robbins, Bruce. Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling beyond the Nation. Cultural Politics. 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 0-8166-3067-4. OCLC 875672972.  Schuett, Robert; Stirk, Peter M.R., eds. (2015). The Concept of the State in International Relations: Philosophy, Sovereignty, and Cosmopolitanism. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-9362-7. 

External links[edit]

Kleingeld, Pauline; Brown, Eric. "Cosmopolitanism". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  Living in the World Risk Society
Society
by Ulrich Beck
Ulrich Beck
at the London School of Economics The Venus Project 'Cosmopolitans' an essay on the philosophical history of cosmopolitanism ref 1: GTI Paper Series see Dawn of the Cosmopolitan: The Hope of a Global Citizens Movement, paper #15, and Global Politics and Institutions, paper #3

v t e

Global governance and identity

Proposals

United Nations
United Nations
Parliamentary Assembly World government

Theories

Anti-nationalism Cosmopolitanism Counter-hegemonic globalization Democratic globalization Democratic mundialization Global citizenship Global governance Globalism Internationalism Transnational governance World currency World taxation system

Organisations

Democratic World Federalists Global citizens movement World Federalist Movement World Service Authority

v t e

Social and political philosophy

Pre-modern philosophers

Aquinas Aristotle Averroes Augustine Chanakya Cicero Confucius Al-Ghazali Han Fei Laozi Marsilius Mencius Mozi Muhammad Plato Shang Socrates Sun Tzu Thucydides

Modern philosophers

Bakunin Bentham Bonald Bosanquet Burke Comte Emerson Engels Fourier Franklin Grotius Hegel Hobbes Hume Jefferson Kant Kierkegaard Le Bon Le Play Leibniz Locke Machiavelli Maistre Malebranche Marx Mill Montesquieu Möser Nietzsche Paine Renan Rousseau Royce Sade Smith Spencer Spinoza Stirner Taine Thoreau Tocqueville Vivekananda Voltaire

20th–21th-century Philosophers

Ambedkar Arendt Aurobindo Aron Azurmendi Badiou Baudrillard Bauman Benoist Berlin Judith Butler Camus Chomsky De Beauvoir Debord Du Bois Durkheim Foucault Gandhi Gehlen Gentile Gramsci Habermas Hayek Heidegger Irigaray Kirk Kropotkin Lenin Luxemburg Mao Marcuse Maritain Michels Mises Negri Niebuhr Nozick Oakeshott Ortega Pareto Pettit Plamenatz Polanyi Popper Radhakrishnan Rand Rawls Rothbard Russell Santayana Sarkar Sartre Schmitt Searle Simonović Skinner Sombart Spann Spirito Strauss Sun Taylor Walzer Weber Žižek

Social theories

Ambedkarism Anarchism Authoritarianism Collectivism Communism Communitarianism Conflict theories Confucianism Consensus theory Conservatism Contractualism Cosmopolitanism Culturalism Fascism Feminist political theory Gandhism Individualism Legalism Liberalism Libertarianism Mohism National liberalism Republicanism Social constructionism Social constructivism Social Darwinism Social determinism Socialism Utilitarianism Vaisheshika

Concepts

Civil disobedience Democracy Four occupations Justice Law Mandate of Heaven Peace Property Revolution Rights Social contract Society War more...

Related articles

Jurisprudence Philosophy and economics Philosophy of education Philosophy of history Philosophy of love Philosophy of sex Philosophy of social science Political ethics Social epistemology

Category Portal Task Force

v t e

Globalization

Journals Outline Studies

Aspects

Alter-globalization Anti-globalization Counter-hegemonic globalization Cultural globalization Deglobalization Democratic globalization Economic globalization Environmental globalization Financial globalization Global citizenship

education

Global governance Global health History of

archaic early modern

Military globalization Political globalization Trade globalization Workforce globalization

Issues

Global

Disease Digital divide Labor arbitrage Population Warming Water crisis

Other

Brain drain

reverse

Climate change Climate justice Development aid Economic inequality Endangered languages Fair trade Forced migration Human rights Illicit financial flows Invasive species Investor-state disputes New international division of labour North–South divide Offshoring Race to the bottom

pollution havens

Transnational crime McDonaldization Westernization American imperialism British Empire World war

Theories

Capital accumulation Dependency Development Earth system Fiscal localism Modernization

ecological history of

Primitive accumulation Social change World history World-systems

Notable scholars

Samir Amin Arjun Appadurai K. Anthony Appiah Daniele Archibugi Giovanni Arrighi Ravi Batra Jean Baudrillard Zygmunt Bauman Ulrich Beck Walden Bello Jagdish Bhagwati Robert Brenner Manuel Castells Noam Chomsky Alfred Crosby Christopher Chase-Dunn Andre G. Frank Thomas Friedman Anthony Giddens Peter Gowan Michael Hardt David Harvey David Held Paul Hirst Michael Hudson Paul James Ibn Khaldun Naomi Klein Antonio Negri George Ritzer Dani Rodrik Jeffrey Sachs Saskia Sassen John R. Saul Vandana Shiva Joseph Stiglitz John Urry Immanuel Wallerstein

Portal Category

v t e

Conformity

Group pressures

Authoritarian personality Bandwagon effect Collectivism Coercive persuasion Consensus reality Contagion

Behavioral Crime Hysterical Suicide

Groupthink Hazing Herd mentality Indoctrination Memory conformity Milieu control Mobbing Nationalism Normalization Normative social influence Ostracism Panopticon Patriotism Peer pressure Peer review Pluralistic ignorance Propaganda Right-wing authoritarianism Scapegoating Shunning Social influence Socialization Spiral of silence Teasing Tyranny of the majority Xeer

Conforming oneself

Compliance Countersignaling Herd behavior Internalisation Social proof Obedience

Experiments

Asch conformity experiments Milgram experiment Stanford prison experiment

Counterconformity

Anti-authoritarianism Antisocial tendencies Auto-segregation Civil disobedience Cosmopolitanism Counterculture Culture jamming Deviance Eclecticism Eccentricity Hermit Idiosyncrasy Individualism Rebellion Ritual clown Satire Shock value

Authority control

LCCN: sh2002009006 GND: 4189574-5 SUDOC: 126936374 BNF: cb1575

.