Controversy over Cantor's theory
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
, the theory of
infinite set In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable. Properties The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
s was first developed by
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ;  – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
. Although this work has become a thoroughly standard fixture of classical
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, it has been criticized in several areas by mathematicians and philosophers.
Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
implies that there are sets having
cardinality The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
greater than the infinite cardinality of the set of
natural numbers In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positiv ...
. Cantor's argument for this theorem is presented with one small change. This argument can be improved by using a definition he gave later. The resulting argument uses only five axioms of set theory. Cantor's set theory was controversial at the start, but later became largely accepted. Most modern mathematics textbooks implicitly use Cantor's views on mathematical infinity. For example, a line is generally presented as the infinite set of its points, and it is commonly taught that there are more real numbers than rational numbers (see
cardinality of the continuum In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
).


Cantor's argument

Cantor's first proof that infinite sets can have different cardinalities was published in 1874. This proof demonstrates that the set of natural numbers and the set of
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s have different cardinalities. It uses the theorem that a bounded increasing
sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
of real numbers has a limit, which can be proved by using Cantor's or Richard Dedekind's construction of the
irrational number In mathematics, the irrational numbers are all the real numbers that are not rational numbers. That is, irrational numbers cannot be expressed as the ratio of two integers. When the ratio of lengths of two line segments is an irrational number, ...
s. Because
Leopold Kronecker Leopold Kronecker (; 7 December 1823 – 29 December 1891) was a German mathematician who worked on number theory, abstract algebra and logic, and criticized Georg Cantor's work on set theory. Heinrich Weber quoted Kronecker as having said, ...
did not accept these constructions, Cantor was motivated to develop a new proof. In 1891, he published "a much simpler proof ... which does not depend on considering the irrational numbers." His new proof uses his diagonal argument to prove that there exists an infinite set with a larger number of elements (or greater cardinality) than the set of natural numbers N = . This larger set consists of the elements (''x''1, ''x''2, ''x''3, ...), where each ''xn'' is either ''m'' or ''w''. Each of these elements corresponds to a
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
of N—namely, the element (''x''1, ''x''2, ''x''3, ...) corresponds to . So Cantor's argument implies that the set of all subsets of N has greater cardinality than N. The set of all subsets of N is denoted by ''P''(N), the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of N. Cantor generalized his argument to an arbitrary set ''A'' and the set consisting of all functions from ''A'' to . Each of these functions corresponds to a subset of ''A'', so his generalized argument implies the theorem: The power set ''P''(''A'') has greater cardinality than ''A''. This is known as
Cantor's theorem In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any Set (mathematics), set A, the set of all subsets of A, known as the power set of A, has a strictly greater cardinality than A itself. For finite s ...
. The argument below is a modern version of Cantor's argument that uses power sets (for his original argument, see
Cantor's diagonal argument Cantor's diagonal argument (among various similar namesthe diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof) is a mathematical proof that there are infin ...
). By presenting a modern argument, it is possible to see which assumptions of
axiomatic set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
are used. The first part of the argument proves that N and ''P''(N) have different cardinalities: * There exists at least one infinite set. This assumption (not formally specified by Cantor) is captured in formal set theory by the
axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
. This axiom implies that N, the set of all natural numbers, exists. * ''P''(N), the set of all subsets of N, exists. In formal set theory, this is implied by the power set axiom, which says that for every set there is a set of all of its subsets. * The concept of "having the same number" or "having the same cardinality" can be captured by the idea of
one-to-one correspondence In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equivale ...
. This (purely definitional) assumption is sometimes known as Hume's principle. As Frege said, "If a waiter wishes to be certain of laying exactly as many knives on a table as plates, he has no need to count either of them; all he has to do is to lay immediately to the right of every plate a knife, taking care that every knife on the table lies immediately to the right of a plate. Plates and knives are thus correlated one to one." Sets in such a correlation are called equinumerous, and the correlation is called a one-to-one correspondence. * A set cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with its power set. This implies that N and ''P''(N) have different cardinalities. It depends on very few assumptions of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, and, as John P. Mayberry puts it, is a "simple and beautiful argument" that is "pregnant with consequences". Here is the argument: *:Let A be a set and P(A) be its power set. The following theorem will be proved: If f is a function from A to P(A), then it is not
onto In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function ) is a function such that, for every element of the function's codomain, there exists one element in the function's domain such that . In other words, for a f ...
. This theorem implies that there is no one-to-one correspondence between A and P(A) since such a correspondence must be onto. Proof of theorem: Define the diagonal subset D = \. Since D \in P(A), proving that for all x \in A,\, D \ne f(x) will imply that f is not onto. Let x \in A. Then x \in D \Leftrightarrow x \notin f(x), which implies x \notin D \Leftrightarrow x \in f(x). So if x \in D, then x \notin f(x); and if x \notin D, then x \in f(x). Since one of these sets contains x and the other does not, D \ne f(x). Therefore, D is not in the
image An image or picture is a visual representation. An image can be Two-dimensional space, two-dimensional, such as a drawing, painting, or photograph, or Three-dimensional space, three-dimensional, such as a carving or sculpture. Images may be di ...
of f, so f is not onto. Next Cantor shows that A is equinumerous with a subset of P(A). From this and the fact that P(A) and A have different cardinalities, he concludes that P(A) has greater cardinality than A. This conclusion uses his 1878 definition: If ''A'' and ''B'' have different cardinalities, then either ''B'' is equinumerous with a subset of ''A'' (in this case, ''B'' has less cardinality than ''A'') or ''A'' is equinumerous with a subset of ''B'' (in this case, ''B'' has greater cardinality than ''A''). This definition leaves out the case where ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous with a subset of the other set—that is, ''A'' is equinumerous with a subset of ''B'' and ''B'' is equinumerous with a subset of ''A''. Because Cantor implicitly assumed that cardinalities are linearly ordered, this case cannot occur. After using his 1878 definition, Cantor stated that in an 1883 article he proved that cardinalities are well-ordered, which implies they are linearly ordered. This proof used his well-ordering principle "every set can be well-ordered", which he called a "law of thought". The well-ordering principle is equivalent to the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
. Around 1895, Cantor began to regard the well-ordering principle as a theorem and attempted to prove it. In 1895, Cantor also gave a new definition of "greater than" that correctly defines this concept without the aid of his well-ordering principle.Cantor 1895, pp. 483–484; English translation: Cantor 1954, pp. 89–90. By using Cantor's new definition, the modern argument that ''P''(N) has greater cardinality than N can be completed using weaker assumptions than his original argument: * The concept of "having greater cardinality" can be captured by Cantor's 1895 definition: ''B'' has greater cardinality than ''A'' if (1) ''A'' is equinumerous with a subset of ''B'', and (2) ''B'' is not equinumerous with a subset of ''A''. Clause (1) says ''B'' is at least as large as ''A'', which is consistent with our definition of "having the same cardinality". Clause (2) implies that the case where ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous with a subset of the other set is false. Since clause (2) says that ''A'' is not at least as large as ''B'', the two clauses together say that ''B'' is larger (has greater cardinality) than ''A''. * The power set P(A) has greater cardinality than A, which implies that ''P''(N) has greater cardinality than N. Here is the proof: *# Define the subset P_1 = \. Define f(x) = \, which maps A onto P_1. Since f(x_1) = f(x_2) implies x_1 = x_2, \, f is a one-to-one correspondence from A to P_1. Therefore, A is equinumerous with a subset of P(A). *# Using
proof by contradiction In logic, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical pr ...
, assume that A_1, a subset of A, is equinumerous with P(A).. Then there is a one-to-one correspondence g from A_1 to P(A). Define h from A to P(A)\text if x \in A_1, then h(x) = g(x); if x \in A \setminus A_1, then h(x) = \. Since g maps A_1 onto P(A), \, h maps A onto P(A), contradicting the theorem above stating that a function from A to P(A) is not onto. Therefore, P(A) is not equinumerous with a subset of A. Besides the axioms of infinity and power set, the axioms of separation,
extensionality In logic, extensionality, or extensional equality, refers to principles that judge objects to be equality (mathematics), equal if they have the same external properties. It stands in contrast to the concept of intensionality, which is concerned wi ...
, and
pairing In mathematics, a pairing is an ''R''- bilinear map from the Cartesian product of two ''R''- modules, where the underlying ring ''R'' is commutative. Definition Let ''R'' be a commutative ring with unit, and let ''M'', ''N'' and ''L'' be '' ...
were used in the modern argument. For example, the axiom of separation was used to define the diagonal subset D, the axiom of extensionality was used to prove D \ne f(x), and the axiom of pairing was used in the definition of the subset P_1.


Reception of the argument

Initially, Cantor's theory was controversial among mathematicians and (later) philosophers. Logician has commented on the energy devoted to refuting this "harmless little argument" (i.e.
Cantor's diagonal argument Cantor's diagonal argument (among various similar namesthe diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof) is a mathematical proof that there are infin ...
) asking, "what had it done to anyone to make them angry with it?" Mathematician
Solomon Feferman Solomon Feferman (December 13, 1928July 26, 2016) was an American philosopher and mathematician who worked in mathematical logic. In addition to his prolific technical work in proof theory, computability theory, and set theory, he was known for h ...
has referred to Cantor's theories as “simply not relevant to everyday mathematics.” Before Cantor, the notion of infinity was often taken as a useful abstraction which helped mathematicians reason about the finite world; for example the use of infinite limit cases in
calculus Calculus is the mathematics, mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithmetic operations. Originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the ...
. The infinite was deemed to have at most a potential existence, rather than an actual existence. "Actual infinity does not exist. What we call infinite is only the endless possibility of creating new objects no matter how many exist already".
Carl Friedrich Gauss Johann Carl Friedrich Gauss (; ; ; 30 April 177723 February 1855) was a German mathematician, astronomer, geodesist, and physicist, who contributed to many fields in mathematics and science. He was director of the Göttingen Observatory and ...
's views on the subject can be paraphrased as: "Infinity is nothing more than a figure of speech which helps us talk about limits. The notion of a completed infinity doesn't belong in mathematics." In other words, the only access we have to the infinite is through the notion of limits, and hence, we must not treat infinite sets as if they have an existence exactly comparable to the existence of finite sets. Cantor's ideas ultimately were largely accepted, strongly supported by
David Hilbert David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental idea ...
, amongst others. Hilbert predicted: "No one will drive us from the paradise which Cantor created for us." To which
Wittgenstein Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein ( ; ; 26 April 1889 – 29 April 1951) was an Austrian philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language. From 1929 to 1947, Witt ...
replied "if one person can see it as a paradise of mathematicians, why should not another see it as a joke?" The rejection of Cantor's infinitary ideas influenced the development of schools of mathematics such as constructivism and
intuitionism In the philosophy of mathematics, intuitionism, or neointuitionism (opposed to preintuitionism), is an approach where mathematics is considered to be purely the result of the constructive mental activity of humans rather than the discovery of fu ...
. Wittgenstein did not object to mathematical formalism wholesale, but had a finitist view on what Cantor's proof meant. The philosopher maintained that belief in infinities arises from confusing the intensional nature of mathematical laws with the extensional nature of sets, sequences, symbols etc. A series of symbols is finite in his view: In Wittgenstein's words: "...A curve is not composed of points, it is a law that points obey, or again, a law according to which points can be constructed." He also described the diagonal argument as "hocus pocus" and not proving what it purports to do.


Objection to the axiom of infinity

A common objection to Cantor's theory of infinite number involves the
axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
(which is, indeed, an axiom and not a
logical truth Logical truth is one of the most fundamental concepts in logic. Broadly speaking, a logical truth is a statement which is true regardless of the truth or falsity of its constituent propositions. In other words, a logical truth is a statement whic ...
). Mayberry has noted that "the set-theoretical axioms that sustain modern mathematics are self-evident in differing degrees. One of them—indeed, the most important of them, namely Cantor's Axiom, the so-called Axiom of Infinity—has scarcely any claim to self-evidence at all".Mayberry 2000, p. 10. Another objection is that the use of infinite sets is not adequately justified by analogy to finite sets.
Hermann Weyl Hermann Klaus Hugo Weyl (; ; 9 November 1885 – 8 December 1955) was a German mathematician, theoretical physicist, logician and philosopher. Although much of his working life was spent in Zürich, Switzerland, and then Princeton, New Jersey, ...
wrote: The difficulty with finitism is to develop foundations of mathematics using finitist assumptions that incorporate what everyone reasonably regards as mathematics (for example,
real analysis In mathematics, the branch of real analysis studies the behavior of real numbers, sequences and series of real numbers, and real functions. Some particular properties of real-valued sequences and functions that real analysis studies include co ...
).


See also

* Preintuitionism


Notes


References

* * * * * * * * * * * : "''Aus dem Paradies, das Cantor uns geschaffen, soll uns niemand vertreiben können.''" : Translated in * * * * (address to the Fourth International Congress of Mathematicians) * * * * *


External links


Doron Zeilberger's 68th Opinion

Philosopher Hartley Slater's argument against the idea of "number" that underpins Cantor's set theory

Wolfgang Mueckenheim: Transfinity - A Source Book

Hodges "An editor recalls some hopeless papers"
{{Infinity Discovery and invention controversies History of mathematics Philosophy of mathematics Set theory Georg Cantor